Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-4rdpn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-08T17:32:13.371Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Chapter 24 - Introduction to Polyadic Pure Inductive Logic

from Part 3 - Polyadic Pure Inductive Logic

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 May 2015

Jeffrey Paris
Affiliation:
University of Manchester
Alena Vencovská
Affiliation:
University of Manchester
Get access

Summary

In Part 1 we placed no conditions on the arity of the relation symbols in L, the restriction to unary only happened in Part 2. In this third part we shall again allow into our language binary, ternary etc. relation symbols. As we have seen, despite the logical simplicity of unary languages, for example every formula becomes equivalent to a boolean combination of Π1 and Σ1 formulae, Unary PIL has still a rather rich theory. For this reason it is hardly surprising that with very few exceptions (for example Gaifman [30], Gaifman & Snir [32], Scott & Krauss [132], Krauss [69], Hilpinen [46] and Hoover [52]) ‘Inductive Logic’ meant ‘Unary Inductive Logic’ up to the end of the 20th century.

Of course there was an awareness of this further challenge, Carnap [12, p123 -4] and Kemeny [61], [64] both made this point. There were at least two other reasons why the move to the polyadic was so delayed. The first is that simple, everyday examples of induction with non-unary relations are rather scarce. However they do exist and we do seem to have some intuitions about them. For example suppose that you are planting an orchard and you read that apples of variety A are good pollinators and apples of variety B are readily pollinated. Then you might expect that if you plant an A apple next to a B apple you will be rewarded with an abundant harvest, at least from the latter tree. In this case one might conclude that you had applied some sort of polyadic induction to reach this conclusion, and that may be it has a logical structure worthy of further investigation.

Having said that it is still far from clear what probability functions should be proposed here (and possibly this is a third reason for the delay).

Type
Chapter
Information
Pure Inductive Logic , pp. 181 - 182
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2015

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×