Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-gb8f7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-29T07:24:38.458Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

7 - How Do Concepts Contribute to Scientific Advancement?

Evolutionary Biology As a Case Study

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  04 September 2020

Kostas Kampourakis
Affiliation:
Université de Genève
Tobias Uller
Affiliation:
Lunds Universitet, Sweden
Get access

Summary

In 1962 Thomas Kuhn published one of the twentieth century’s most fruitful and most scandalous books, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (Kuhn 1962). He argued that the form of inquiry we call natural science periodically undergoes more or less sudden shifts in what he called paradigms. His paradigmatic examples were the displacement of Ptolemaic astronomy by Copernican heliocentrism in the sixteenth century; and in the late eighteenth century the discrediting of alchemy, which sought to turn one element into another, by Lavoisier’s chemistry, which took the elements to be atomic and chemical change to consist of compounding these elements in particular ways. These are not especially disconcerting cases, since they helped give birth to modern science in the first place. What was disconcerting was Kuhn’s contention that, even after it was up and running, modern science – institutionalized practices of inquiry in which hypotheses and theories are rigorously tested by careful observation and experimentation – shows the same pattern. Disciplinary communities, he claimed, typically rally around a new paradigm until enough anomalies pile up to invite an even newer one.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2020

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Beatty, J. (1982). What's Wrong with the Received View of Evolutionary Biology? In Asquith, P. D. & Giere, R. N. (eds.), PSA 1980, vol. 2, pp. 3455. East Lansing, MI: Philosophy of Science Association.Google Scholar
Beatty, J. (1995). The Evolutionary Contingency Thesis. In Wolters, G. & Lennox, J. (eds.), Concepts, Theories, and Rationality in the Biological Sciences, pp. 4581. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.Google Scholar
Biémont, C. (2010). A Brief History of the Status of Transposable Elements: From Junk DNA to Major Players in Evolution. www.genetics.org/content/186/4/1085CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Black, M. (1962). Models and Metaphors. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bogen, J. & Woodward, J. (1988). Saving the Phenomena. Philosophical Review 97: 303352.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bowler, P. (1983). The Eclipse of Darwinism: Anti-Darwinian Evolution Theories in the Decades Around 1900. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
Bowler, P. (2013). Darwin Deleted: Imagining a World without Darwin. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Brandon, R. (1981). Biological Teleology: Questions and Explanations. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science 12: 91105.Google Scholar
Burian, R. & Kampourakis, K. (2013). Against “Genes For”: Could an Inclusive Concept of Genetic Material Replace Gene Concepts? In Kampourakis, K. (ed.), The Philosophy of Biology: A Companion for Educators, pp. 597628. Dordrecht: Springer Verlag.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cavalli, G. & Heard, E. (2019). Advances in Epigenetics Link Genetics to the Environment and Disease. Nature 571 : 489499.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Darwin, C. (1859). On the Origin of Species. Mayr, E. (ed.). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Facsimile of 1st ed.Google Scholar
Darwin, C. (1861). On the Origin of Species. London: John Murray. 3rd ed.Google Scholar
Darwin, C. (1862). On the Various Contrivances by which Orchids Are Fertilized by Insects. London: John Murray.Google Scholar
Darwin, C. (1875a). The Movements and Habits of Climbing Plants. London: John Murray.Google Scholar
Darwin, C. (1875b). Insectivorous Plants. London: John Murray.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Darwin, C. (1881). On the Formation of Vegetable Mould Through the Action of Worms, with Observations on Their Habits. London: John Murray.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Darwin, C. (1958). The Autobiography of Charles Darwin. Barlow, N. (ed.). London: Collins.Google Scholar
Darwin, C. (1975 ). Charles Darwin’s Natural Selection. Stauffer, R. C., (ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Dawkins, R. (1986). The Selfish Gene. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 2nd ed. (1st ed., 1976).Google Scholar
Dawkins, R. (2006). The God Delusion. London: Bantam Books.Google Scholar
Depew, D. (2013). The Rhetoric of Evolutionary Theory. Biological Theory 7(4): 380389.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Depew, D. (2015). Accident, Adaptation, and Teleology in Empedocles, Aristotle, and Darwin. In Sloan, P., Eggleson, K., & McKenny, G., Darwin in the Twenty-First Century: Nature, Man, and God, pp. 116143. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Depew, D. & Weber, B. (1995). Darwinism Evolving. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Depew, D. & Weber, B. (2013). Challenging Darwinism: Expanding, Extending, or Replacing the Modern Evolutionary Synthesis. In Ruse, M. (ed.), The Cambridge Encyclopedia of Darwin, pp. 405411. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Depew, D. & Weber, B. H. (2017). Developmental Biology, Natural Selection, and the Conceptual Boundaries of the Modern Evolutionary Synthesis. Zygon 52 : 468490.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dobzhansky, T. (1937). Genetics and the Origin of Species. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Dupré, J. & Nicholson, D. (2018). A Manifesto for a Processual Philosophy of Biology. In Nicholson, D. & Dupre, J. (eds.), Everything Flows: Towards a Processual Philosophy of Biology, pp. 345. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fisher, R. A. (1918). The Correlation between Relatives on the Supposition of Mendelian Inheritance. Transactions of the Royal Society of Edinburgh 52: 399433.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fisher, R. A. (1930). The Genetical Theory of Natural Selection. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Forest, D. (2018). Darwin est-il resistable? Mill sur le Dessein et la selection naturelle. In Merlin, F. & Huneman, P. (eds.), Philosophie, histoire, biologie: mélanges offerts á Jean Gayon, pp. 183194. Paris: Editions Materiologiques.Google Scholar
Gayon, J. (1997). The “Paramount Power” of Selection: From Darwin to Kauffman. In Della Chiara, J. (ed.), Structure and Norms in Science, pp. 265282. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gayon, J. (1998). Darwinism’s Struggle for Survival. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Gigerenzer, G., Swijtink, Z., Porter, T., & Daston, L. (1990). The Empire of Chance: How Probability Changed Science and Everyday Life. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Giere, R. (1979). Understanding Scientific Reasoning. New York: Holt Reinhart.Google Scholar
Gould, S. J. (1977). Ontogeny and Phylogeny. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Griffiths, P. & Gray, R. (1995). Developmental Systems and Evolutionary Explanation. The Journal of Philosophy 91: 277304.Google Scholar
Hesse, M. (1966). Models and Analogies in Science. Notre Dame, IN: Notre Dame University Press. Revised ed.Google Scholar
Herschel, J. W. F. (1831). Preliminary Discourse on the Study of Natural Philosophy. London: Longmans.Google Scholar
Hodge, M. J. (1982). Darwin and the Laws of the Animate Part of the Terrestrial System, 1835–1837: On the Lyellian Origins of His Zoonomial Explanatory Program. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Biology 6: 1106.Google Scholar
Hofmann, J. & Weber, B. (2003). The Fact of Evolution: Implications for Science Education. Science & Education 12: 729760.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hull, D. (1978). A Matter of Individuality. Philosophy of Science 45: 335360.Google Scholar
Huneman, P. & Walsh, D. (eds.) (2018). Challenges to the Modern Synthesis Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kampourakis, K. (2017). Making Sense of Genes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kampourakis, K. & Reiss, M. J. (2018). Teaching Biology in Schools: Global Research, Issues and Trends. New York: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kuhn, T. (1962). The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Lakatos, I. (1970). Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes. In Lakatos, I. & Musgrove, A. (eds.), Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge, pp. 91195. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Lakoff, G. & Johnson, M. (1980). Metaphors We Live By. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Latour, B. (1987). Science in Action. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Laudan, L. (1977). Progress and Its Problems. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Lennox, J. (1993). Darwin Was a Teleologist. Biology and Philosophy 8: 409421.Google Scholar
Lloyd, E. (1988). The Structure and Confirmation of Evolutionary Theory. New York: Greenwood Press. Reprinted Princeton University Press, 1994.Google Scholar
Mayr, E. (1980). Prologue. In Mayr, E. & Provine, W. (eds.), The Evolutionary Synthesis, pp. 148. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mills, S. & Beatty, J. (1979). The Propensity Interpretation of Fitness. Philosophy of Science 46: 263286.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moss, L. (2003). What Genes Can’t Do. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Nicholson, D. & Dupré, J. (eds.) (2018). Everything Flows: Toward a Processual Philosophy of Biology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pigliucci, M. (2007). Do We Need an Extended Evolutionary Synthesis? Evolution 61: 27432749.Google Scholar
Neander, K. (1991). Functions as Selected Effects. Philosophy of Science 58 : 168184.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pigliucci, M & Müller, G. (eds.) (2010). Evolution: The Extended Synthesis. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Ruse, M. (1975). Darwin’s Debt to Philosophy: An Examination of the Influence of the Philosophical Ideas of John F. W. Herschel and William Whewell on the Development of Charles Darwin’s Theory of Evolution. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science 6: 159–81.Google Scholar
Snyder, L. (2006). Reforming Philosophy: A Victorian Debate on Science and Society. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Sober, E. (1993 [1984]). The Nature of Selection: Evolutionary Theory in Philosophical Focus. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Uller, T. (2013). Nongenetic Inheritance and Evolution. In Kampourakis, K (ed.), The Philosophy of Biology: A Campanion For Educators, pp. 267287. Dordrecht: Springer Verlag,Google Scholar
van Frassen, B. 1980. The Scientific Image. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Vosniadou, S. (ed.) (2013). International Handbook of Research on Conceptual Change. 2nd ed. New York and London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Walsh, D. (2015). Organisms, Agency, and Evolution. Cambridge: University of Cambridge Press.Google Scholar
Watson, J. (1968). The Double Helix. New York: Simon and Schuster.Google Scholar
Weismann, A. (1889). Essays Upon Heredity. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Whewell, W. (1840). Philosophy of the Inductive Sciences. London: John W. Parker. Reprint of 2nd ed., New York, Johnson Reprint Co., 1967.Google Scholar
Wright, L. (1976). Teleological Explanations. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wright, S. (1932). The Roles of Mutation, Inbreeding, Crossbreeding, and Selection in Evolution. Proceedings of the Sixth Annual Congress of Genetics 1: 356366.Google Scholar
Zammito, J. (2004). A Nice Derangement of Epistemes: Post-Positivism in the Study of Science from Quine to Latour. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×