Book contents
- Frontmatter
- Contents
- Contributors
- Acknowledgements
- List of abbreviations
- Introduction: German literature and philosophy
- Chapter One Criticism and experience: philosophy and literature in the German Enlightenment
- Chapter Two The pursuit of the subject: literature as critic and perfecter of philosophy 1790–1830
- Chapter Three Two realisms: German literature and philosophy 1830–1890
- Chapter Four Modernism and the self 1890–1924
- Chapter Five The subjects of community: aspiration, memory, resistance 1918–1945
- Chapter Six Coming to terms with the past in postwar literature and philosophy
- Bibliography
- Index
Chapter Two - The pursuit of the subject: literature as critic and perfecter of philosophy 1790–1830
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 22 September 2009
- Frontmatter
- Contents
- Contributors
- Acknowledgements
- List of abbreviations
- Introduction: German literature and philosophy
- Chapter One Criticism and experience: philosophy and literature in the German Enlightenment
- Chapter Two The pursuit of the subject: literature as critic and perfecter of philosophy 1790–1830
- Chapter Three Two realisms: German literature and philosophy 1830–1890
- Chapter Four Modernism and the self 1890–1924
- Chapter Five The subjects of community: aspiration, memory, resistance 1918–1945
- Chapter Six Coming to terms with the past in postwar literature and philosophy
- Bibliography
- Index
Summary
In 1798 the Romantic writer Friedrich Schlegel (1772–1829) boldly reduced the age in which he lived to three dominant tendencies. That the French Revolution, the most significant single political and cultural development in modernity, should be written large no one then or now would dispute. Alongside this historical cataclysm, however, Schlegel ranks phenomena from the republic of letters: a philosophy, Johann Gottlieb Fichte's ‘Wissenschaftslehre’ (theory of knowledge); and a literary work, the novel Wilhelm Meisters Lehrjahre (1795–6; Wilhelm Meister's years of apprenticeship) by Johann Wolfgang Goethe (1749–1832). Schlegel's intention, of course, is to emphasise and provoke. But he clearly intends a fundamental relation between the Revolution, philosophy and literature in our epoch. Of what kind? The age around 1800, it will be argued with Schlegel, was one in which literature and philosophy self-consciously co-operated and competed for Germany's intellectual leadership. The Revolution ultimately determined their relationship. Both literature and philosophy sought words to express its meaning. Both hoped to launch actions out of those words.
The Revolution then as now was in fact seen philosophically – as the fulfilment of the project of Enlightenment, which Immanuel Kant (1724–1804) had famously defined as the emergence of humanity from its self-imposed tutelage, that is, as a race of fully self-conscious free beings. Concretely, as Kant said, Enlightenment meant rampant criticism – of all received forms of thought and action – by the new authority in matters of truth: human reason (KrV, 13n).
- Type
- Chapter
- Information
- Philosophy and German Literature, 1700–1990 , pp. 57 - 101Publisher: Cambridge University PressPrint publication year: 2002