Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-t7fkt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-29T08:08:22.845Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false
This chapter is part of a book that is no longer available to purchase from Cambridge Core

Appendix

Doris Olin
Affiliation:
York University, Toronto
Get access

Summary

Here are some further paradoxes. Some are versions of paradoxes already considered; others are unrelated to what has gone before.

The racetrack paradox

Suppose Achilles is trying to break the record for the 100m dash. Not only will he not succeed, but he will not even finish the course. To complete the course, he first has to run half the track, or 50m; then he has to complete half the remaining distance, or 25m; then he has to complete half the remaining distance, or 12½m; and so on. First he is half-way there, then three-quarters of the way, then seven-eighths of the way. But however many of these segments of the track he completes, there will always be some distance left to the finish line. Thus, Achilles will never complete the course.

The racetrack, and the Achilles and the tortoise paradox from Chapter 1, are two of the paradoxes attributed to Zeno of Elea (c. 470bc). See W. Salmon, Zeno's Paradoxes (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1970).

Grelling's paradox

Some words, it seems, apply to themselves. For instance, the word “short” is short and the word “polysyllabic” is polysyllabic. Words that have this feature are called “autological”. Many words, however, do not apply to themselves. The word “long” is not long and the word “monosyllabic” is not monosyllabic. Call such words “heterological”.

Is “heterological” heterological? If it is, then it does not apply to itself, and is thus not heterological.

Type
Chapter
Information
Paradox , pp. 191 - 198
Publisher: Acumen Publishing
Print publication year: 2002

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Appendix
  • Doris Olin, York University, Toronto
  • Book: Paradox
  • Online publication: 05 February 2013
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/UPO9781844653508.010
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Appendix
  • Doris Olin, York University, Toronto
  • Book: Paradox
  • Online publication: 05 February 2013
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/UPO9781844653508.010
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Appendix
  • Doris Olin, York University, Toronto
  • Book: Paradox
  • Online publication: 05 February 2013
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/UPO9781844653508.010
Available formats
×