Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-mlc7c Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-17T17:12:16.713Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Part I - Reporting and Ascribing

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 October 2022

Daniel Altshuler
Affiliation:
University of Oxford
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2022

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

References

Aboh, E. O. (2010). Event operator movement in factives: Some facts from Gungbe. Theoretical Linguistics, 36(2–3), 153162.Google Scholar
Arsenijević, B. (2009). Clausal complementation as relativization. Lingua, 119(1), 3950.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Axel-Tober, K. (2017). The development of the declarative complementizer in German. Language, 93(2), e29e65. http://doi.org/10.1353/lan.2017.0030Google Scholar
Bary, C., & Maier, E. (2021). The landscape of speech reporting. https://ling.auf.net/lingbuzz/003526.Google Scholar
Beebee, H., & Fisher, A. J. R. (Eds.). (2020). Philosophical Letters of David K. Lewis. Volume 2: Mind, Language, Epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bigelow, J. C. (1975a). Contexts and quotation Ⅰ. Linguistische Berichte, 38, 121.Google Scholar
Bigelow, J. C. (1975b). Contexts and quotation Ⅱ. Linguistische Berichte, 39, 121.Google Scholar
Bigelow, J. C. (1978). Believing in semantics. Linguistics and Philosophy, 2(1), 101144.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blumberg, K., & Holguín, B. (2018). Ultra-liberal attitude reports. Philosophical Studies, 175, 20432062.Google Scholar
Blumberg, K., & Holguín, B. (2019). Embedded attitudes. Journal of Semantics, 36, 377406.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blumberg, K., & Lederman, H. (2021). Revisionist reporting. Philosophical Studies, 178, 755783.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brasoveanu, A., & Farkas, D. F. (2007). Say reports, assertion events and meaning dimensions. In Mos, P. (Ed.), A Building with a View: Papers in Honor of Alexandra Cornilescu. Bucharest: Editura Universitatii din Bucuresti.Google Scholar
Bricker, P. (1983). Worlds and Propositions: The Structure and Ontology of Logical Space. PhD dissertation, Princeton University.Google Scholar
Bricker, P. (2020). Modal Matters: Essays in Metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Burge, T. (2019). Introduction. Alonzo Church: Life and work. Philosophy and intensional logic. In Burge, T. & Enderton, H. (Eds.), The Collected Works of Alonzo Church (pp. xxxxiv). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Burge, T., & Enderton, H. (Eds.). (2019). The Collected Works of Alonzo Church. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Carnap, R. (1947). Meaning and Necessity. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Carnap, R. (1956). Meaning and Necessity, 2nd ed. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Carnap, R. (1963). Replies and systematic expositions: Language, modal logic, and semantics. In Schilpp, P. A. (Ed.), The Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap (pp. 889–943). La Salle, IL: Open CourtGoogle Scholar
Carnap, R. (1972). Notes on semantics. Philosophia, 2(1–2), 354.Google Scholar
Charlow, S., & Sharvit, Y. (2014). Bound ‘de re’ pronouns and the LFs of attitude reports. Semantics and Pragmatics, 7(3), 143.Google Scholar
Chierchia, G. (1989). Introduction. In Chierchia, G., Partee, B. H., & Turner, R. (Eds.), Properties, Types and Meaning. Volume II: Semantic Issues (pp. 120). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.Google Scholar
Chierchia, G., Partee, B. H., & Turner, R. (Eds.). (1989). Properties, Types, and Meaning. Volume II: Semantic Issues. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.Google Scholar
Church, A. (1940). A formulation of the simple theory of types. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 5, 5668.Google Scholar
Church, A. (1946). Abstract of a formulation of the logic of sense and denotation. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 11, 31.Google Scholar
Church, A. (1950). On Carnap’s analysis of statements of assertion and belief. Analysis, 10, 9799.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Church, A. (1951a). A formulation of the logic of sense and denotation. In Henley, P., Kallen, H. M., & Langer, S. K. (Eds.), Structure, Method and Meaning: Essays in Honor of Henry M. Sheffer (pp. 324). New York: Liberal Arts Press.Google Scholar
Church, A. (1951b). The need for abstract entities in semantic analysis. Proceedings of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences, 80(1), 100112.Google Scholar
Church, A. (1973). Outline of a revised formulation of the logic of sense and denotation (Part I). Nous, 7, 2433.Google Scholar
Church, A. (1974). Outline of a revised formulation of the logic of sense and denotation (Part II). Nous, 8, 135156.Google Scholar
Church, A. (1993). Revised formulation of the logic of sense and denotation: Alternative 1. Nous, 27, 141157.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Church, A. (2019). Correspondence with Rudolf Carnap, 1943–1954. In Burge, T. & Enderton, H. (Eds.), The Collected Works of Alonzo Church (pp. 10381073). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Cresswell, M. J. (1975). Hyperintensional logic. Studia Logica: An International Journal for Symbolic Logic, 34(1), 2538.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cresswell, M. J. (1985). Structured Meanings: The Semantics of Propositional Attitudes. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Cresswell, M. J., & von Stechow, A. (1982). De re belief generalized. Linguistics and Philosophy, 5, 503535.Google Scholar
Davidson, K. (2015). Quotation, demonstration, and iconicity. Linguistics and Philosophy, 38, 477520.Google Scholar
DeGraff, M. (2020). The politics of education in post-colonies: Kreyòl in Haiti as a case study of language as technology for power and liberation. Journal of Postcolonial Linguistics, 3, 89125.Google Scholar
Gallin, D. (1975). Intensional Logic and Higher-Order Logic. Amsterdam: North-Holland Publishing Company.Google Scholar
Gutzmann, D. (2015). Use-Conditional Meaning: Studies in Multidimensional Semantics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Gutzmann, D. (2019). The Grammar of Expressivity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hawthorne, J., & Manley, D. (2012). The Reference Book. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Heim, I. (1992). Presupposition projection and the semantics of attitude verbs. Journal of Semantics, 9, 183221.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heim, I., & Kratzer, A. (1998). Semantics in Generative Grammar. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.Google Scholar
Hintikka, J. (1962). Knowledge and Belief. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Hunter, J., & Thompson, K. (2022). On the role of relations and structure in discourse interpretation. In Altshuler, D. (Ed.), Linguistics Meets Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Janssen, T. M. V. (2012). Compositionality: Its historic context. In Werning, M., Hinzen, W., & Machery, E. (Eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Compositionality (pp. 1946). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kamp, H. (2022). Referential and attributive descriptions. In Altshuler, D. G. (Ed.), Linguistics Meets Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kanger, S. (1957). Provability in Logic. PhD dissertation, Uppsala University.Google Scholar
Kaplan, D. (1964). Foundations of Intensional Logic. PhD dissertation, University of California, Los Angeles.Google Scholar
Kaplan, D. (1968–69). Quantifying in. Synthese, 19, 178214.Google Scholar
Kayne, R. S. (2008). Antisymmetry and the lexicon. Linguistic Variation Yearbook, 8(1), 132.Google Scholar
Kemeny, J. G. (1948). Models of logical systems. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 13(1), 1630.Google Scholar
Kemeny, J. G. (1956a). A new approach to semantics. Part I. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 21(1), 127.Google Scholar
Kemeny, J. G. (1956b). A new approach to semantics. Part II. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 21(2), 149161.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kratzer, A. (1978). Semantik der Rede. Kontexttheorie, Modalwörter, Konditionalsätze. Königstein: Scriptor.Google Scholar
Kratzer, A. (2012). Modals and Conditionals. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kratzer, A. (2016). Evidential moods in attitude and speech reports. Amherst/Mass: Scholarworks@UMassAmherst. https://works.bepress.com/angelika_kratzer/10/Google Scholar
Kripke, S. (1959). A completeness theorem in modal logic. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 24(1), 114.Google Scholar
Kripke, S. (1963). Semantical analysis of modal logic I: Normal modal propositional calculi. Zeitschrift für mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik, 9, 6796.Google Scholar
Lederman, H. (2021). Fine-grained semantics for attitude reports. Semantics and Pragmatics, 14(1), 133. doi:10.3765/sp.14.1Google Scholar
Lewis, D. (1970). General semantics. Synthese, 22, 1867.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D. (1986). On the Plurality of Worlds. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. (2020a). To Max Cresswell and Arnim von Stechow, 17 June 1981. In Beebee, H. & Fisher, A. R. J. (Eds.), Philosophical Letters of David Lewis. Volume 2: Mind, Language, Epistemology (pp. 104108). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. (2020b). To Frank Jackson and Valina Rainer, 29 March 1983. In Beebee, H. & Fisher, A. R. J. (Eds.), Philosophical Letters of David Lewis. Volume 2: Mind, Language, Epistemology (pp. 123125). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. (2020c). To Peter Inwagen and Hartry Field, 24 February 1988. In Beebee, H. & Fisher, A. J. R. (Eds.), Philosophical Letters of David Lewis. Volume 1: Causation, Modality, Ontology (pp. 585589). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Maier, E. (2020). Quotes as complements: A Kratzerian approach. In Bhatt, R., Frana, I., & Menéndez-Benito, P. (Eds.), Making Worlds Accessible: Essays in Honor of Angelika Kratzer (pp. 9198). Amherst: Scholarworks@UMassAmherst. https://scholarworks.umass.edu/ak_festsite_schrift/1/Google Scholar
Markman, E. M., & Wachtel, G. F. (1988). Children’s use of mutual exclusivity to constrain the meaning of words. Cognitive Psychology, 20(2), 121157.Google Scholar
Mates, B. (1952). Synonymity. In Linsky, L. (Ed.), Semantics and the Philosophy of Language (pp. 111136). Urbana, IL: The University of Illinois Press.Google Scholar
Montague, R. (1960). Logical necessity, physical necessity, ethics, and quantifiers. Inquiry, 3(1–4), 259269.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Montague, R. (1970). Universal grammar. Theoria, 36(3), 373398.Google Scholar
Moulton, K. (2015). CPs: Copies and compositionality. Linguistic Inquiry, 46(2), 305342.Google Scholar
Parsons, T. (2001). The logic of sense and denotation: Extensions and applications. In Anderson, C. A. & Zelëny, M. (Eds.), Logic, Meaning and Computation (pp. 507543). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.Google Scholar
Partee, B. (1973). The semantics of belief sentences. In Hintikka, J., Suppes, P., & Moravcsik, E. (Eds.), Approaches to Natural Language (pp. 309336). Dordrecht: D. Reidel.Google Scholar
Percus, O., & Sauerland, U. (2003). On the LFs of attitude reports. Sinn und Bedeutung, 7, 228242.Google Scholar
Pilley, J. W. (2013). Chaser: Unlocking the Genius of the Dog Who Knows a Thousand Words. Boston, MA: Houghton Mifflin Harcourt.Google Scholar
Potts, C. (2005). The Logic of Conventional Implicatures. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. (1975). The meaning of “meaning.” In Gunderson, K. (Ed.), Language, Mind and Knowledge (pp. 131193). Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. O. (1956). Quantifiers and propositional attitudes. The Journal of Philosophy, 53(5), 177187.Google Scholar
Recanati, F. (2012). Mental Files. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Richard, M. (1990). Propositional Attitudes: An Essay on Thoughts and How We Ascribe Them. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Rogers, R. (1963). A survey of formal semantics. Synthese, 15(1), 1756.Google Scholar
Schiffer, S. (1977). Naming and knowing. Midwest Studies in Philosophy Ⅱ, 28–41.Google Scholar
Sharvit, Y., & Moss, M. (2022). Acquaintance relations. In Altshuler, D. (Ed.), Linguistics Meets Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Sosa, E. (1970). Propositional attitudes de dictu and de re. The Journal of Philosophy, 67(21), 883896.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Inwagen, P. (1981). Why I don’t understand substitutional quantification. Philosophical Studies, 39(3), 281285.Google Scholar
von Fintel, K. (1999). NPI licensing, Strawson entailment, and context dependency. Journal of Semantics, 16, 97148.Google Scholar
von Fintel, K. (2001). Counterfactuals in a dynamic context. In Kenstowicz, M. (Ed.), Ken Hale: A Life in Language (pp. 123152). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Werning, M., Hinzen, W., & Machery, E. (Eds.). (2012). The Oxford Handbook of Compositionality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Williamson, T. (2020). Suppose and Tell. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Yalcin, S. (2015). Quantifying in from a Fregean perspective. The Philosophical Review, 124(2), 207253.Google Scholar

References

Abusch, D. (1988). Sequence of tense, intensionality and scope. In Borer, H. (Ed.), The Proceedings of the 7th West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics. Stanford Linguistics Association.Google Scholar
Abusch, D. (1994). Sequence of tense revisited: Two semantic accounts of tense in intensional contexts. In Kamp, H. (Ed.), Ellipsis, Tense and Questions, Dyana-2 Esprit Basic research Project 6852, Deliverable R2.2.B.Google Scholar
Abusch, D. (1997). Sequence of tense and temporal ‘de re’. Linguistics and Philosophy, 20, 150.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Altshuler, D., & Schwarzschild, R. (2013). Moment of change, cessation implicatures and simultaneous readings. Sinn und Bedeutung, 17, 4562.Google Scholar
Bary, C. (2022). Present Tense. In Altshuler, D. (Ed.), Linguistics Meets Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Cariani, F., & Santorio, P. (2018). Will done better: Selection semantics, future credence, and indeterminacy. Mind, 127(505), 129165.Google Scholar
Chierchia, G., & McConnell-Ginet, S. (2000). Meaning and Grammar. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Comrie, B. (1985). Tense. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Cresswell, M. J. (1985). Structured Meanings. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Cresswell, M. J., & von Stechow, A. (1982). ‘De re’ belief generalized. Linguistics and Philosophy, 5, 503535.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. (1987). The Intentional Stance. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Enç, M. (1981). Tense without Scope: An Analysis of Nouns as Indexicals. PhD dissertation, University of Wisconsin-Madison.Google Scholar
Gennari, S. (2003). Tense meanings and temporal interpretation. Journal of Semantics, 20, 3571.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. D. (1970). The Linguistic Description of Opaque Contexts. PhD dissertation, Massachusetts Institute of Technology.Google Scholar
Frege, G. (1892). Über Sinn und Bedeutung. Zeitschrift für Philosophie und philosophische Kritik, 100, 2550.Google Scholar
Hawthorne, J., & Manley, D. (2012). The Reference Book. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heim, I. (1994). Comments on Abusch’s theory of tense. In Kamp, H. (Ed.), Ellipsis, Tense and Questions, DYANA deliverable R2.2.B, 143170. Amsterdam: University of Amsterdam.Google Scholar
Higginbotham, J. (2001). Why is sequence of tense obligatory? In Liakata, M., Jensen, B., & Maillat, D. (Eds.), Oxford University Working Papers in Linguistics, Philosophy and Phonetics, Vol. 6 (pp. 6790). Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
Jespersen, O. (1931). A Modern English Grammar on Historical Principles, Part IV, Syntax, Third Volume, Time and Tense. Heidelberg: Carl Winters Universitatsbuchhandlung.Google Scholar
Kaplan, D. (1968). Quantifying in. Synthese, 19(1), 178214.Google Scholar
Kaplan, D. (1989). Demonstratives. In Almog, J., Perry, J., & Wettstein, H. (Eds.), Themes from Kaplan (pp. 481563). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kauf, C., & Zeijlstra, H. (2018). Towards a new explanation of sequence of tense. In Maspong, S., Stefánsdóttir, B., Blake, K., & Davis, F. (Eds.), Semantics and Linguistic Theory (SALT), Vol. 28 (pp. 59–77).Google Scholar
Klecha, P. (2015). Double access. Unpublished manuscript, University of Connecticut.Google Scholar
Klecha, P. (2016). Modality and embedded temporal operators. Semantics and Pragmatics, 9, 155.Google Scholar
Klein, E. H. (1979). On Sentences Which Report Beliefs, Desires, and Other Mental Attitudes. PhD dissertation, University of Cambridge.Google Scholar
Kratzer, A. (2022). Attitude Ascriptions and Speech Reports. In Altshuler, D. (Ed.), Linguistics Meets Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kripke, S. (1980). Naming and Necessity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Ladusaw, W. (1977). Some problems with tense in PTQ. Texas Linguistic Forum, 6, 89102.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. K. (1979). Attitudes de dicto and de se. Philosophical Review, 88(4), 513543.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McGinn, C. (1981). The mechanism of reference. Synthese, 29, 157186.Google Scholar
Ninan, D. (2012). Counterfactual attitudes and multi-centered worlds. Semantics and Pragmatics, 5(5), 157.Google Scholar
Ogihara, T. (1996). Tense, attitudes, and scope. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic.Google Scholar
Ogihara, T., & Sharvit, Y. (2012). Embedded tenses. In Binnick, R. (Ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Tense and Aspect (pp. 638668). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Partee, B. H. 1973. Some structural analogies between tenses and pronouns in English. The Journal of Philosophy, 70, 601609.Google Scholar
Pearson, H. (2018). Counterfactual de se. Semantics and Pragmatics, 11(2). https://doi.org/10.3765/sp.11.2.Google Scholar
Percus, O. (2000). Constraints on some other variables in syntax. Natural Language Semantics, 8(3), 173229.Google Scholar
Percus, O., & Sauerland, U. (2003). On the LFs of attitude reports. Sinn und Bedeutung, 7, 228242.Google Scholar
Proops, I. (2014). Russellian acquaintance revisited. Journal of the History of Philosophy, 52, 779811.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. O. (1956). Quantifiers and propositional attitudes. Journal of Philosophy, 53, 177218.Google Scholar
Russell, B. (1911). Knowledge by acquaintance and knowledge by description. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 11, 108128.Google Scholar
Salmon, N. (2004). The good, the bad, and the ugly. In Bezuidenhout, A. & Reimer, M. (Eds.), Descriptions and Beyond. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Schwager, M. (2011). Speaking of qualities. In Cormany, E., Ito, S., & Lutz, D. (Eds.), Semantics and Linguistic Theory (SALT), Vol. 19 (pp. 395–412).Google Scholar
Sharvit, Y. (2018). Sequence of tense: Syntax, semantics, pragmatics. In Patel-Grosz, P., Grosz, P., & Zobel, S. (Eds.), Studies in Linguistics and Philosophy Vol. 99: Pronouns in Embedded Contexts at the Syntax–Semantics Interface (pp. 215247). Cham: Springer.Google Scholar
Sharvit, Y. (2020). Sequence of tense. In Matthewson, L., Meier, C., Rullmann, H., Zimmermann, T. E., & Gutzmann, D. (Eds.), The Wiley Blackwell Companion to Semantics. Chichester: Wiley.Google Scholar
Smith, C. (1978). The syntax and interpretation of temporal expressions in English. Linguistics and Philosophy, 2, 4399.Google Scholar
von Stechow, A. (1995). On the proper treatment of tense. In Simons, M. & Galloway, T. (Eds.), Semantics and Linguistic Theory (SALT), Vol. 5 (pp. 362–386).Google Scholar
Tsilia, A. (2021). Embedded Tense: Insights from Modern Greek. MA thesis, École Normale Supérieure, Paris.Google Scholar
Tsompanidis, V. (2015). Mental files and times. Topoi, 34(1), 233240.Google Scholar
Wettstein, H. (1986). Has semantics rested on a mistake? The Journal of Philosophy, 83, 185209.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Reporting and Ascribing
  • Edited by Daniel Altshuler, University of Oxford
  • Book: Linguistics Meets Philosophy
  • Online publication: 06 October 2022
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108766401.002
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Reporting and Ascribing
  • Edited by Daniel Altshuler, University of Oxford
  • Book: Linguistics Meets Philosophy
  • Online publication: 06 October 2022
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108766401.002
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Reporting and Ascribing
  • Edited by Daniel Altshuler, University of Oxford
  • Book: Linguistics Meets Philosophy
  • Online publication: 06 October 2022
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108766401.002
Available formats
×