Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-t7fkt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-25T21:36:16.744Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Part I - On the Practical Implications of Free Will Skepticism

Optimism vs. Pessimism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  26 August 2019

Elizabeth Shaw
Affiliation:
University of Aberdeen
Derk Pereboom
Affiliation:
Cornell University, New York
Gregg D. Caruso
Affiliation:
Corning Community College, State University of New York
Get access

Summary

Recent free will denialism (FWD) tends to be optimistic, claiming that not only will the rejection of the belief in free will and moral responsibility not make matters dreadful but that we are indeed better off without them. I address the denialist claim that FWD has the philosophical resources to effectively safeguard human rights and respect for persons in the context of punishment, even without belief in free will, moral responsibility, and desert. I raise seven reasons for doubt concerning the ability of FWD to maintain deontological constraints. Together they present a strong case for doubting the optimism of FWD.

Type
Chapter
Information
Free Will Skepticism in Law and Society
Challenging Retributive Justice
, pp. 27 - 96
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2019

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

References

Caruso, G. D. (2017). Public Health and Safety: The Social Determinants of Health and Criminal behavior. London: ResearchLinks Books.Google Scholar
Hart, H. L. A. (1970). Punishment and Responsibility. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Kane, R. (1996). The Significance of Free Will. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lemos, J. (2016). Moral concerns about responsibility denial and the quarantine of violent criminals. Law and Philosophy, 35, 461483.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levy, N. (2012). Skepticism and sanction. Law and Philosophy, 31, 477493.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCloskey, H. J. (1965). A non-utilitarian approach to punishment. Inquiry, 8, 249263.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCloskey, H. J. (1967). Utilitarian and retributive punishment. Journal of Philosophy, 64, 91110.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moriarty, J. (2003). Against the asymmetry of desert. Nous, 37, 518536.Google Scholar
Moriarty, J. (2013). Smilansky, Arneson, and the asymmetry of desert. Philosophical Studies, 162, 537545.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pereboom, D. (2001). Living Without Free Will. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Pereboom, D. (2014). Free Will, Agency, and Meaning in Life. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pereboom, D. (2017). A defense of free will skepticism: Replies to commentaries by Victor Tadros, Saul Smilansky, Michael McKenna, and Alfred R. Mele on Free Will, Agency, and Meaning in Life. Criminal Law and Philosophy, 11, 617636.Google Scholar
Pereboom, D., and Caruso, G. D.. (2018). Hard-incompatibilist existentialism: Neuroscience, punishment and meaning in life. In Caruso, G. D. and Flanagan, O., eds., Neuroexistentialism: Meaning, Morals and Purpose in the Age of Neuroscience. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 193222.Google Scholar
Scheffler, S. (1992). Responsibility, reactive attitudes, and liberalism in philosophy and politics. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 21, 299323.Google Scholar
Scheffler, S. (2002). Justice and desert in liberal theory. In Scheffler, S., ed., Boundaries and Allegiances. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 173196.Google Scholar
Smilansky, S. (1990). Utilitarianism and the “punishment” of the innocent: The general problem. Analysis, 50, 256261.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smilansky, S. (1996a). Responsibility and desert: Defending the connection. Mind, 105, 157163.Google Scholar
Smilansky, S. (1996b). The connection between responsibility and desert: The crucial distinction. Mind, 105, 385386.Google Scholar
Smilansky, S. (2000). Free Will and Illusion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Smilansky, S. (2001). Free will: From nature to illusion. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 101, 7195.Google Scholar
Smilansky, S. (2003). Compatibilism: The argument from shallowness. Philosophical Studies, 115, 257282.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smilansky, S. (2005). Free will and respect for persons. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 29, 248261.Google Scholar
Smilansky, S. (2006). Control, desert and the difference between distributive and retributive justice. Philosophical Studies, 131(3), 511524.Google Scholar
Smilansky, S. (2010). Free will: Some bad news. In Campbell, J. K., O’Rourke, M., and Silverstein, H. S., eds., Action, Ethics and Responsibility. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 187202.Google Scholar
Smilansky, S. (2011a). Hard determinism and punishment: A practical reduction. Law and Philosophy, 30, 353367.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smilansky, S. (2011b). Free will, fundamental dualism and the centrality of illusion (revised version). In Kane, R., ed., The Oxford Handbook of Free Will, 2nd edn. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 425441.Google Scholar
Smilansky, S. (2012). Free will and moral responsibility: The Trap, the appreciation of agency, and the bubble. Journal of Ethics, 16, 211239.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smilansky, S. (2016). Parfit on free will, desert, and the fairness of punishment. Journal of Ethics, 20, 139148.Google Scholar
Smilansky, S. (2017a). The free will problem: Nonstandard views. In Griffith, M., Levy, N., and Timpe, K., eds., The Routledge Companion to Free Will. New York: Routledge, pp. 136146.Google Scholar
Smilansky, S. (2017b). Pereboom on punishment: Funishment, innocence, motivation, and other difficulties. Criminal Law and Philosophy, 11, 591603.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smilansky, S. (In press). Illusionism. In D. Pereboom and D. Nelkin, eds., The Oxford Handbook of Moral Responsibility. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sommers, T. (2012). Relative Justice. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Sprigge, T. L. S. (1965). A utilitarian reply to Dr. McCloskey. Inquiry, 8, 264291.Google Scholar
Vilhauer, B. (2013). Persons, punishment, and free will skepticism. Philosophical Studies, 162: 143163.Google Scholar
Waller, B. N. (2018). The Injustice of Punishment. Abingdon: Routledge.Google Scholar

References

Alicke, M. D. (1994). Evidential and extra-evidential evaluations of social conduct. Journal of Social Behavior and Personality, 9, 591615.Google Scholar
Alicke, M. D. (2008). Blaming badly. Journal of Cognition and Culture, 8, 179186.Google Scholar
Alicke, M. D., Buckingham, J., Zell, E., and Davis, T.. (2008). Culpable control and counterfactual reasoning in the psychology of blame. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 34, 13711381.Google Scholar
Altemeyer, R. A. (1981). Right-Wing Authoritarianism. Manitoba: University of Manitoba Press.Google Scholar
Altemeyer, R. A. (1996). The Authoritarian Specter. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Altemeyer, R. A. (2003). Why do religious fundamentalists tend to be prejudiced? International Journal for the Psychology of Religion, 13,1728.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aspinwall, L. G., Brown, T. R, and Tabery, J.. (2012). The double-edged sword: Does biomechanism increase or decrease judges’ sentencing of psychopaths? Science, 337, 846849.Google Scholar
Barna Research Group Survey. (1999). U.S. divorce rates for various faith groups, age groups, and geographic areas. Available at www.religioustolerance.org/chr_dira.htm (last accessed 22 June 2009).Google Scholar
Barna Research Group Survey. (2007). Atheists and agnostics take aim at Christians. Available at www.barna.org/barna-update/article/12-faithspirituality/102-atheists-and-agnostics-take-aim-at-christians (last accessed 22 June 2009).Google Scholar
Baumeister, R. F. (2008). Free will, consciousness, and cultural animals. In Bear, J., Kaufman, J., and Baumeister, R., eds., Are We Free? Psychology and Free Will. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 6585.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Baumeister, R. F., Masicampo, E. J., and DeWall, C. N.. (2009). Prosocial benefits of feeling free: Disbelief in free will increases aggression and reduces helpfulness. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 35(2), 260268.Google Scholar
Berg, K. S., and Vidmar, N.. (1975). Authoritarianism and recall of evidence about criminal behavior. Journal of Research in Personality, 9, 147157.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brinkerhoff, M., Grandin, E., and Lupri, E.. (1992). Religious involvement and spousal violence: The Canadian case. Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion, 31,1531.Google Scholar
Carey, J. M., and Paulhus, D. L.. (2013). Worldview implication of believing in free will and/or determinism: Politics, morality, and punitiveness. Journal of Personality, 81(2), 130141.Google Scholar
Carey, B., and Roston, M.. (2015). Three popular psychology studies that didn’t hold up. The New York Times. Retrieved from: www.nytimes.com/interactive/2015/08/28/science/psychology-studies-redid.html.Google Scholar
Caruso, G. D. (2012). Free Will and Consciousness: A Determinist Account of the Illusion of Free Will. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books.Google Scholar
Caruso, G. D. (2016). Free will skepticism and criminal behavior: A public health-quarantine model. Southwest Philosophy Review, 32(1), 2548.Google Scholar
Caruso, G. D. (2017a). Public Health and Safety: The Social Determinants of Health and Criminal Behavior. London: ResearchLinks Books.Google Scholar
Caruso, G. D. (2017b). Free will skepticism and the questions of creativity: Creativity, desert, and self-creation. Ergo, 3(23), 591607.Google Scholar
Caruso, G. D. (2018). Skepticism about moral responsibility. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Available at: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/skepticism-moral-responsibility/Google Scholar
Caruso, G. D. (2019a). The public health-quarantine model. In Nelkin, D. and Pereboom, D., eds., Oxford Handbook on Moral Responsibility. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Caruso, G. D. (2019b). A defense of the luck pincer: Why luck (still) undermines free will and moral responsibility. Journal of Information Ethics, April/May Issue.Google Scholar
Caruso, G. D., and Morris, S.. (2017). Compatibilism and retributivist desert moral responsibility: On what is of central philosophical and practical importance. Erkenntnis, 82, 837855.Google Scholar
Clark, T. (2013). Experience and autonomy: Why consciousness does and doesn’t matter. In Caruso, G. D., ed., Exploring the Illusion of Free Will and Moral Responsibility. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books, pp. 239254.Google Scholar
Clark, C. J., Ditto, P. H., Shariff, A. F., et al. (2014). Free to punish: A motivated account of free will belief. Attitudes of Social Cognition, 106(4), 501513.Google Scholar
Corrado, M. L. (2013). Why do we resist hard incompatibilism? Thoughts on freedom and punishment. In Nadelhoffer, T., ed., The future of punishment. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 79106.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crick, F. (1994). The Astonishing Hypothesis. New York: Scriber.Google Scholar
Crone, D., and Levy, N.. (2018). Are free will believers nicer people (Four studies suggest not). Open Science Framework, January 10. Retrieved from: osf.io/m9sreGoogle Scholar
Dalbert, C., and Yamauchi, L.. (1994). Belief in a just world and attitudes toward immigrants and foreign workers: A cultural comparison between Hawaii and Germany. Journal of Applied Social Psychology, 24, 16121626.Google Scholar
Death Penalty Information Center. (2008). Regional murder rates, 2001–2007. Available at: www.death-penaltyinfo.org/murder-rates-1996-2007 (last accessed 22 June 2009).Google Scholar
Earp, B. D., Everett, J. A. C., Nadelhoffer, T., et al. (2018). Determined to be humble? Exploring the relationship between belief in free will and humility. PsyArXiv. Available at: https://psyarxiv.com/3bxraGoogle Scholar
Efran, M. G. (1974). The effect of physical appearance on the judgment of guilt, interpersonal attraction, and severity of recommended punishment in a simulated jury task. Journal of Research and Personality, 8, 4554.Google Scholar
Ellison, C., Burr, J. and McCall, P.. (2003). The enduring puzzle of southern homicide. Homicide Studies, 7, 326352.Google Scholar
Epley, N., and Dunning, D.. (2000). Feeling “holier than thou”: Are self-serving assessments produced by errors in self or social prediction? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 79, 861875.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Everett, J. A. C., Luguri, J. B., Clark, C. J., et al. (2018). Free to blame? Political differences in free will belief are driven by differences in moralization. Available at: https://psyarxiv.com/nx9rj/Google Scholar
Fajnzylber, O., Lederman, D., and Loatza, N.. (2002). Inequality and violent crime. Journal of Law and Economics, XLV, 140.Google Scholar
Fox, J. and Levin, J.. (2000). The Will to Kill. Boston, MA: Allyn and Bacon.Google Scholar
Furnham, A. (2003). Belief in a just world: Research progress over the past decade. Personality and Individual Differences, 34, 795817.Google Scholar
Furnham, A., and Gunter, B.. (1984). Just world beliefs and attitudes towards the poor. British Journal of Social Psychology, 15, 265269.Google Scholar
Gazzinga, M. (2011). Who’s in Charge? Free Will and the Science of the Brain. New York: Harper.Google Scholar
Greene, J. D., and Cohen, J.. (2004). For the law, neuroscience changes nothing, and everything. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London, B 359, 17751785. DOI: 10.1098/rstb.2004.1546 (accessed 26 October 2012).Google ScholarPubMed
Hardcastle, V. (2018). The neuroscience of criminality and our sense of justice: An analysis of recent appellate decisions in criminal cases. In Caruso, G. D. and Flanagan, O., eds., Neuroexistentialism: Meaning, Morals, and Purpose in the Age of Neuroscience. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 311332.Google Scholar
Harper, D., and Manasse, P.. (1992). The just world and the third world: British explanations for poverty abroad. Journal of Social Psychology, 132, 783785.Google Scholar
Jensen, G. F. (2006). Religious cosmologies and homicide rates among nations. The Journal of Religion and Society, 8, 113.Google Scholar
Jost, J. T. (2006). The end of the end of ideology. American Psychologist, 61, 651670.Google Scholar
Jost, J. T., Blount, S., Pfeffer, J., and Hunyady, G.. (2003). Fair market ideology: Its cognitive-motivational underpinnings. Research in Organizational Behavior, 25, 5391.Google Scholar
Lagnado, D. A., and Channon, S.. (2008). Judgments of cause and blame: The effects of intentionality and foreseeability. Cognition, 108, 754770.Google Scholar
Lerner, M. J. (1965). Evaluation of performance as a function of performer’s reward and attractiveness. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 1, 355360.Google Scholar
Lerner, M. J. (1980). The Belief in a Just World: A Fundamental Delusion. New York: Plenum Press.Google Scholar
Lerner, M. J., and Miller, D. T.. (1978). Just world research and the attribution process: Looking back and ahead. Psychological Bulletin, 85, 10301051.Google Scholar
Lerner, M. J., Miller, D. T., and Holmes, J. G.. (1976). Deserving and the emergence of forms of justice. In L. Berkowitz and E. Walster, eds., Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, pp. 134–162.Google Scholar
Lerner, M. J., and Simmons, C. H.. (1966). Observer’s reaction to the “innocent victim”: Compassion or rejection? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 4, 203210.Google Scholar
Levy, N. (2011). Hard Luck: How Luck Undermines Free Will and Moral Responsibility. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Levy, N. (2012). Skepticism and sanctions: The benefit of rejecting moral responsibility. Law and Philosophy, 31(5), 477493.Google Scholar
Lewis, C. S. (1971). The humanitarian theory of punishment. In his, God in the Dock: Essays on Theology and Ethics. Cambridge: William B. Eerdmans Publishing, pp. 287294.Google Scholar
MacKenzie, M. J., Vohs, K. D., and Baumeister, B. F.. (2014). You didn’t have to do that: Belief in free will promotes gratitude. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, DOI: 10.1177/0146167214549322.Google Scholar
Milam, P-E. (2016). Reactive attitudes and personal relationships. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 46(1), 102122.Google Scholar
Montada, L. (1998). Belief in a just world: A hybrid of justice motive and self-interest. In , L. M. and Lerner, M., eds., Responses to Victimizations and Belief in the Just World. New York: Plenum, pp. 217245.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Monterosso, J., Royzman, E. B., and Schwartz, B.. (2005). Explaining away responsibility: Effects of scientific explanation on perceived culpability. Ethics and Behavior, 15, 139158.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Monterosso, J., Royzman, E. B., and Schwartz, B.. (2012). Did your brain make you do it? New York Times. July 27, 2014.Google Scholar
Morris, H. (1968). Persons and punishment. The Monist, 52, 475501.Google Scholar
Nadelhoffer, T. 2006. Bad acts, blameworthy agents, and intentional actions: Some problems for juror impartiality. Philosophical Explorations, 9(2), 203219.Google Scholar
Nadelhoffer, T. 2011. The threat of shrinking agency and free will disillusionism. In Nadel, L. and Sinnott-Armstrong, W., eds., Conscious Will and Responsibility: A Tribute to Benjamin Libet. New York: Oxford University Press, pp.173188.Google Scholar
Nadelhoffer, T., and Goya Tocchetto, D.. (2013). The potential dark side of believing in free will (and related concepts): Some preliminary findings. In Caruso, G. D., ed., Exploring the Illusion of Free Will and Moral Responsibility. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books, pp. 121140.Google Scholar
Nadelhoffer, T., Nahmias, E., Ross, L., Shepard, J., and Sripada, C.. (2014). The free will inventory: Measuring beliefs about agency and responsibility. Consciousness and Cognition, 25, 2741.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Nadelhoffer, T., and Wright, J. C.. (2018). Humility, free will beliefs, and existential angst: How we got from a preliminary investigation to a cautionary tale. In Caruso, G. D. and Flanagan, O., eds., Neuroexistentialism: Meaning, Morals, and Purpose in the Age of Neuroscience. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 269297.Google Scholar
Neimeth, C., and Sosis, R. H.. (1973). A simulated jury: Characteristics of the defendant and the jurors. Journal of Social Psychology, 90, 221229.Google Scholar
Nichols, S. (2011). Is free will an illusion? Scientific American Mind, 22, 1819.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, M. (2011). Creating capabilities: The human development approach. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Oldenquist, A. (1988). An explanation of retribution. Journal of Philosophy, 85, 464478.Google Scholar
Open Science Collaboration. (2015). Estimating the reproducibility of psychological science. Science, 349(6251), aac4716: DOI: 10.1126/science.aac4716.Google Scholar
Paul, G. S. (2005). Is the Baylor religion study reliable?: An analysis from the council for secular humanism. Available at: http://ga1.org/center_for_inquiry/notice-description.tcl?newsletter_id=11076763.Google Scholar
Paulhus, D. L., and Carey, J. M.. (2011). The FAD-Plus: Measuring lay beliefs regarding free will and related constructs. Journal of Personality Assessment, 93, 96104.Google Scholar
Pereboom, D. (2001). Living Without Free Will. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Pereboom, D. (2013a). Optimistic skepticism about free will. In Russell, P. and Deery, O., eds., The Philosophy of Free Will: Selected Contemporary Readings. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 421449.Google Scholar
Pereboom, D. (2013b). Skepticism about free will. In Caruso, G. D., ed., Exploring the Illusion of Free Will and Moral Responsibility. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books, pp. 1940.Google Scholar
Pereboom, D. (2013c). Free will skepticism and criminal punishment. In Nadelhoffer, T., ed., The Future of Punishment. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 4978.Google Scholar
Pereboom, D. (2014). Free Will, Agency, and Meaning in Life. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pereboom, D. (2017). A defense of free will skepticism: Replies to commentaries by Victor Tadros, Saul Smilansky, Michael McKenna, and Alfred R. Mele on Free Will, Agency, and Meaning in Life. Criminal Law and Philosophy, 11(3), 617636.Google Scholar
Pereboom, D., and Caruso, G. D.. (2018). Hard-incompatibilist existentialism: Neuroscience, punishment, and meaning in life. In Caruso, G. D. and Flanagan, O., ed., Neuroexistentialism: Meaning, Morals, and Purpose in the Age of Neuroscience. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 193222.Google Scholar
Pizarro, D., Ulhmann, E., and Salovey, P.. (2003). Asymmetry in judgments of moral blame and praise: The of perceived metadesires. Psychological Science, 14, 267272.Google Scholar
Powers, M. and Faden, R. (2006). Social Justice: The Moral Foundations of Public Health and Health Policy. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Rubin, Z., and Peplau, L. A.. (1975). Who believes in a just world? Journal of Social Issues, 31, 6589.Google Scholar
Schlenker, B. R. (1980). Impression Management: The Self-Concept, Social Identity, and Interpersonal Relations. Monterey, CA: Brooks/Cole.Google Scholar
Sen, A. (1985). Commodities and Capabilities. Amsterdam: North-Holland.Google Scholar
Sen, A. (1999). Development as Freedom. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Shariff, A. F., Greene, J. D., Karremans, J. C., et al. (2014). Free will and punishment: A mechanistic view of human nature reduces retribution. Psychological Science, June 10, 1–8.Google Scholar
Sie, M. (2013). Free will, an illusion? An answer from a pragmatic sentimentalist point of view. In Caruso, G. D., ed., Exploring the Illusion of Free Will and Moral Responsibility. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books, pp. 273290.Google Scholar
Smilansky, S. (2000). Free Will and Illusion. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Smilansky, S. (2013). Free will as a case of “crazy ethics.” In Caruso, G. D., ed., Exploring the Illusion of Free Will and Moral Responsibility. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books, pp. 103120.Google Scholar
Snyder, C. R., Higgins, R. L., and Stuckey, R. J.. (1983). Excuses: Masquerades in Search of Grace. Clinton Corners, NY: Eliot Werner Publications.Google Scholar
Sorrentino, R. M., and Hardy, J.. (1974). Religiousness and derogation of an innocent victim. Journal of Personality, 42, 372382.Google Scholar
Sosis, R. H. (1974). Internal-external control and the perception of responsibility of another for an accident. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 30, 393399.Google Scholar
Stillman, T. F., and Baumeister, R. F.. (2010). Guilt, free, and wise: Belief in free will facilitates Learning from self-conscious emotions. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 46, 951960.Google Scholar
Stillman, T. F., Baumeister, R. F., Vohs, K. D., Lambert, N. M., Fincham, F. D., and Brewer, L. E.. (2010). Personal philosophy and personnel achievement: Belief in free will predicts better job performance. Social Psychological and Personal Science, 1(1), 4350.Google Scholar
Strawson, G. (1986). Freedom and Belief. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Strawson, G. (1994). The impossibility of moral responsibility. Philosophical Studies, 75(1), 524.Google Scholar
Strawson, G. (2010). Freedom and Belief, Revised edition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Strawson, G. (2018). Things That Bother Me: Death, Freedom, the Self, etc. New York: New York Review Book.Google Scholar
Tabandeh, A. P., Gardoni, P., and Murphy, C.. (2018). A reliability-based capability approach. Risk Analysis, 38(2), 410424.Google Scholar
Tonry, M. (2004). Thinking About Crime: Sense and Sensibility in American Penal Culture. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Vilhauer, B. (2010). Persons, punishment, and free will skepticism. Philosophical Studies, DOI: 10.1007/s11098-011-9752-z.Google Scholar
Vilhauer, B. (2013). The people problem. In Caruso, G. D., ed., Exploring the Illusion of Free Will and Moral Responsibility. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books, pp. 141160.Google Scholar
Vohs, K. D., and Schooler, J. W.. (2008). The value of believing in free will: Encouraging a belief in determinism increases cheating. Psychological Science, 19, 4954.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wagstaff, G. F. (1983). Correlates of the just world in Britain. Journal of Social Psychology, 121, 145146.Google Scholar
Waller, B. (2011). Against Moral Responsibility. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Waller, B. (2013). The stubborn illusion of moral responsibility. In Caruso, G. D., ed., Exploring the Illusion of Free Will and Moral Responsibility. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books, pp. 6586.Google Scholar
Waller, B. (2014a). The culture of moral responsibility. Southwest Philosophical View, 30(1), 317.Google Scholar
Waller, B. (2014b). The Stubborn System of Moral Responsibility. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Waller, B. (2015). Restorative Free Will: Back to the Biological Base. Lanham, MA: Lexington Books.Google Scholar
Weiner, B. (1993). On sin and sickness: A theory of perceived responsibility and social motivation. American Psychologist, 48, 957965.Google Scholar
Zuckerman, P. (2009). Atheism, secularity, and well-being: How the findings of social science counter negative stereotypes and assumptions. Sociology Compass, 3/6, 949971.Google Scholar
Zwaan, R. (2013). The value of believing in free will: a replication attempt. March 18, 2013. Retrieved from: https://rolfzwaan.blogspot.com/2013/03/the-value-of-believing-in-free-will.html.Google Scholar

References

Bandura, A. (1997). Self-Efficacy: The Exercise of Control. New York: W. H. Freeman.Google Scholar
Barash, D. P., and Lipton, J. E.. (2011). Payback: Why we Retaliate, Redirect Aggression, and Take Revenge. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Beckett, K. (1997). Making Crime Pay: Law and Order in Contemporary American Politics. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bottoms, A. E. (1995). The philosophy and politics of punishment and sentencing. In Clarkson, C. and Morgan, R., eds., The Politics of Sentencing Reform. Oxford: Clarendon, pp. 1549.Google Scholar
Braithewaite, J. (1999). Restorative justice: assessing optimistic and pessimistic accounts. Crime and Justice: A Review of Research, 25, 1110.Google Scholar
Braithewaite, J. (2002). Restorative Justice and Response Regulation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Canton, R. (2010). Not another medical model: using metaphor and analogy to explore crime and criminal justice. British Journal of Community Justice, 8, 4057.Google Scholar
Cavadino, M., and Dignan, J.. (2006a). Penal policy and political economy. Criminology and Criminal Justice, 6, 435456.Google Scholar
Cavadino, M., and Dignan, J.. (2006b). Penal Systems: A Comparative Approach. London: Sage.Google Scholar
Clark, T. W. (2007). Encountering Naturalism: A Worldview and Its Uses. Somerville, MA: Center for Naturalism.Google Scholar
Dalbert, C., and Yamauchi, L.. (1994). Belief in a just world and attitudes toward immigrants and foreign workers: A cultural comparison between Hawaii and Germany. Journal of Applied Social Psychology, 24, 16121626.Google Scholar
Damasio, A. R. (2003). Looking for Spinoza: Joy, Sorrow, and the Feeling Brain. Orlando, FL: Harcourt.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. (1984). Elbow Room. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Doob, A. N., and Roberts, J. V.. (1983). An Analysis of the Public View of Sentencing. Ottawa: Department of Justice (Canada).Google Scholar
Esping-Andersen, G. (1990). The Three Worlds of Welfare Capitalism. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Esping-Andersen, G. (1999). Social Foundations of Postindustrial Economies. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Fischer, J. M. (2012). Deep Control: Essays on Free Will and Value. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Fishkin, J. (1996). Bringing deliberation to democracy. The Public Perspective, 7, 14.Google Scholar
French, P. (2001). The Virtues of Vengeance. Lawrence, KS: The University Press of Kansas.Google Scholar
Furnham, A. (2003). Belief in a just world: research progress over the past decade. Personality and Individual Differences, 34, 795817.Google Scholar
Furnham, A., and Gunter, B.. (1984). Just world beliefs and attitudes towards the poor. British Journal of Social Psychology, 15, 265269.Google Scholar
Gilligan, J. (2001). Preventing Violence. New York: Thames and Hudson.Google Scholar
Hafer, C. L., and Bègue, L.. (2005). Experimental research on just-world theory: problems, developments, and future challenges. Psychological Bulletin, 131, 128167.Google Scholar
Harper, D., and Manasse, P.. (1992). The just world and the third world: British explanations for poverty abroad. Journal of Social Psychology, 132, 783785.Google Scholar
Hart, H. L. A. (1968). Punishment and Responsibility. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Hernu, P. (2011). Norway’s controversial ‘cushy prison’ experiment – Could it catch on in the UK? Daily Mail. Updated July 25, 2011: www.dailymail.co.uk/home/moslive/article1384308Google Scholar
Indermaur, D., Roberts, L., Spiranovic, C., Mackenzie, G., and Gelb, K.. (2012). A matter of judgment: the effect of information and deliberation on public attitudes to punishment. Punishment and Society, 14, 147165.Google Scholar
Johnstone, G., ed. (2003). A Restorative Justice Reader. Cullompton UK: Willan Publishing.Google Scholar
Kawamura, S. (1967). Aggression as studied in troops of Japanese monkeys. In Clemente, C. and Lindsley, D., eds., Aggression and Defense, Brain Function. Berkeley: University of California Press, pp. 195224.Google Scholar
Lacey, N. (2008). The Prisoners’ Dilemma: Political Economy and Punishment in Contemporary Democracies. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Leape, L. (1994). Error in medicine. Journal of the American Medical Association, 272, 18511857.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Lerner, M. J. (1980). The Belief in a Just World: A Fundamental Delusion. New York: Plenum Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lerner, M. J. and Miller, D. T.. (1978). Just world research and the attribution process: looking back and ahead. Psychological Bulletin, 85, 10301051.Google Scholar
Levy, N. 2011. Hard Luck: How Luck Undermines Free Will and Moral Responsibility. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Major, J. (1993). Interview with the editor of the Mail (London), Jonathan Holbrow, February 21, 8.Google Scholar
Martinson, R. (1974). What works?—Questions and answers about prison reform. The Public Interest, 35, 2254.Google Scholar
Martinson, R. (1979). New findings, new view: a note of caution regarding sentencing reform. Hofstra Law Review, 7, 243258.Google Scholar
Montada, L. (1998). Belief in a just world: a hybrid of justice motive and self-interest. In Montada, L. and Lerner, M., eds., Responses to Victimizations and Belief in the Just World. New York: Plenum, pp. 217245.Google Scholar
Moore, M. S. (1997). Placing Blame: A General Theory of the Criminal Law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Morris, A. (2002). Critiquing the critics: a brief response to critics of restorative justice. British Journal of Criminology, 42, 596615.Google Scholar
Nichols, S. (2007). After incompatibilism: a naturalistic defense of the reactive attitudes. Philosophical Perspectives, 21, 405428.Google Scholar
Potegal, M. (1994). Aggressive arousal: the amygdala connection. In Potegal, M. and Knutson, J. F., eds., The Dynamics of Aggression: Biological and Social Processes in Dyads and Groups. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, pp. 73112.Google Scholar
Sher, G. (1987). Desert. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Smilansky, S. (2011). Hard determinism and punishment: A practical reductio. Law and Philosophy, 30, 353367.Google Scholar
Solomon, R. C. (2004). In Defense of Sentimentality. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sommers, T. (2009). A Very Bad Wizard. San Francisco, CA: Believer Books.Google Scholar
Strawson, P. F. (1962). Freedom and resentment. Proceedings of the British Academy, 48, 125.Google Scholar
Virgin, C. E., and Sapolsky, R.. (1997). Styles of male social behavior and their endocrine correlates among low-ranking baboons. American Journal of Primatology, 42, 2539.Google Scholar
Wagstaff, G. F. (1983). Correlates of the just world in Britain. Journal of Social Psychology, 121, 145146.Google Scholar
Waller, B. N. (2007). Sincere apology without moral responsibility. Social Theory and Practice, 33, 441465.Google Scholar
Watson, G. (1987). Responsibility and the limits of evil. In Schoeman, F., ed., Responsibility, Character, and the Emotions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 256286.Google Scholar
Wilson, J. Q. (1998). Selective incapacitation. In von Hirsch, A. and Ashworth, A., eds., Principled Sentencing: Readings on Theory and Policy, 2nd ed. Oxford: Hart Publishing, pp. 113120.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×