Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-dk4vv Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-21T16:00:40.799Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

7 - Human rights, climate change, and discounting

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 June 2011

Simon Caney
Affiliation:
University of Oxford, UK
Karen O'Brien
Affiliation:
Universitetet i Oslo
Asunción Lera St. Clair
Affiliation:
Universitetet i Bergen, Norway
Berit Kristoffersen
Affiliation:
Universitetet i Tromsø, Norway
Get access

Summary

In its Fourth Assessment Report, the Intergovernmental Panel of Climate Change (IPCC) has provided further confirmation that climate change will have serious impacts on human life. It reports that:

The global average surface temperature has increased, especially since about 1950. The updated 100-year trend (1906–2005) of 0.74°C ± 0.18°C is larger than the 100-year warming trend at the time of the TAR (1901–2000) of 0.6°C ± 0.2°C due to additional warm years. The total temperature increase from 1850–1899 to 2001–2005 is 0.76°C ± 0.19°C. The rate of warming averaged over the last 50 years (0.13°C ± 0.03°C per decade) is nearly twice that for the last 100 years.

(Solomon et al., 2007: 36)

In addition to this, the IPCC projects that temperatures will continue to rise. It employed six different Special Report of Emission Scenarios (SRES) and these all found that temperatures will rise by 2090–2099 as compared to the temperatures between 1980 and 1999. In some scenarios temperatures will increase by 1.8°C (the best estimate of the B1 scenario). In others temperatures will increase by 4.0°C (the best estimate of the A1FI scenario). If we examine the ‘likely range,’ then the lower limit is 1.1°C and the higher limit is 6.4°C (Solomon et al., 2007: 70). Climate change will also involve a rise of sea levels. Again the IPCC employs six different SRES scenarios. In some, sea levels are projected to rise by 0.18–0.38 metres (B1 scenario) and on others the increase is projected to be 0.26–0.59 metres (A1FI scenario).

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2010

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Adger, W. N. 2004. The right to keep cold. Environment and Planning A, 36(10), 1711–15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ainslie, G. 2001. Breakdown of the Will. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arrow, K. 1999. Discounting, morality, and gaming. In Portney, P. R. and Weyant, J. P., eds., Discounting and Intergenerational Equity. Washington, DC: Resources for the Future, pp. 13–21.Google Scholar
Azar, C. and Schneider, S. H. 2002. Are the economic costs of stabilizing the atmosphere prohibitive?Ecological Economics, 42(1), 73–80.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barker, T.et al. 2007. Summary for Policymakers. In Metz, B., Davidson, O. R., Bosch, P. R., Dave, R. and Meyer, L. A., eds., Climate Change 2007. Mitigation: Contribution of Working Group III to the Fourth Assessment Report of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, pp. 1–23.Google Scholar
Beckerman, W. and Hepburn, C. 2007. Ethics of the discount rate in the Stern review on the economics of climate change. World Economics, 8(1), 187–210.Google Scholar
Beckerman, W. and Pasek, J. 2001. Justice, Posterity, and the Environment. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Broome, J. 1992. Counting the Cost of Global Warming. Cambridge, UK: White Horse Press.Google Scholar
Caney, S. 2005. Cosmopolitan justice, responsibility and global climate change. Leiden Journal of International Law, 18(4), 747–75.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Caney, S. 2009a. Global climate change and the duties of the advantaged. Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy, 12(4), 693–717.Google Scholar
Caney, S. 2009b. Human rights, responsibilities and climate change. In Beitz, C. and Goodin, R., eds., Global Basic Rights. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, pp. 227–47.Google Scholar
Caney, S. 2009c. Climate change and the future: time, wealth and risk. Journal of Social Philosophy, 40(2), 163–86.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Caney, S. 2009d. Climate change, human rights and moral thresholds. In Humphreys, S., ed., Human Rights and Climate Change, Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, pp. 69–90.Google Scholar
Confalonieri, U.et al. 2007. Human health. In Parry, M. L., Canziani, O. F., Palutikof, J. P., Linden, P. J. and Hanson, C. E., eds., Climate Change 2007: Impacts, Adaptation and Vulnerability. Contribution of Working Group II to the Fourth Assessment Report of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, pp. 391–431.Google Scholar
Cropper, M. L., Aydede, S. K. and Portney, P. R. 1994. Preferences for life saving programs: how the public discounts time and age. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 8(3), 243–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dasgupta, P. 2007. Commentary: The Stern review's economics of climate change. National Institute Economic Review, 199(1), 4–7.Google Scholar
Davidson, M. D. 2006. A social discount rate for climate damage to future generations based on regulatory law. Climatic Change, 76(1/2), 55–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
de-Shalit, A. 1995. Why Posterity Matters: Environmental Policies and Future Generations. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Elliott, R. 1989. The Rights of Future People. Journal of Applied Philosophy, 6(2), 159–70.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feinberg, J. 1980. The rights of animals and unborn generations. In Rights, Justice, and the Bounds of Liberty: Essays in Social Philosophy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 159–84.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frederick, S. 2003. Measuring intergenerational time preference: are future lives valued less?Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 26(1), 39–53.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Groom, B., Hepburn, C., Koundouri, P. and Pearce, D. 2005. Declining discount rates: the long and the short of it. Environmental and Resource Economics, 32(4), 445–93.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hare, B. 2006. Relationship between increases in global mean temperature and impacts on ecosystems, food production, water and socio-economic systems. In Schellnhuber, H. J., Cramer, W., Nakicenovic, N., Wigley, T. and Yohe, G., eds., Avoiding Dangerous Climate Change. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, pp. 177–87.Google Scholar
Hayward, T. 2005. Constitutional Environmental Rights. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kovats, R. S., Campbell-Lendrum, D. and Matthies, F. 2005.Climate change and human health: estimating avoidable deaths and disease. Risk Analysis, 25(6), 1409–18.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Loewenstein, G. and Prelec, D. 2000. Anomalies in intertemporal choice: evidence and an interpretation. In Kahneman, D. and Tvsersky, A., eds., Choices, Values, and Frames. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, pp. 578–96.Google Scholar
Loewenstein, G. and Thaler, R. 1989. Anomalies: intertemporal choice. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 3(4), 181–93.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lomborg, B. 2001. The Skeptical Environmentalist: Measuring the Real State of the World. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McMichael, A. J.et al., eds. 2003. Climate Change and Human Health: Risks and Responses. Geneva: World Health Organization.
McMichael, A. J.et al. 2004. Chapter 20: Global Climate Change. In Ezzati, M., Lopez, A. D., Rodgers, A. and Murray, C. J. L., eds., Comparative Quantification of Health Risks: Global and Regional Burden of Disease Attribution to selected Major Risk Factors. Geneva: World Health Organization, pp. 1543–649.Google Scholar
Mendelsohn, R. 2006–2007. A Critique of the Stern Report. Regulation 29(4), 42–6.Google Scholar
Meyer, L. H. 2003. Past and future: the case for a threshold notion of harm. In Meyer, L. H., Paulson, S. L. and Pogge, T. W., eds., Rights, Culture, and the Law: Themes from the Legal and Political Philosophy of Joseph Raz. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, pp. 143–59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nickel, J. 1993. The human right to a safe environment: philosophical perspectives on its scope and justification. Yale Journal of International Law, 18(1), 281–95.Google Scholar
Nordhaus, W. D. 1997. Discounting in economics and climate change. Climatic Change, 37(2), 315–28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nordhaus, W. D. 2007. A review of the Stern review on the economics of climate change. Journal of Economic Literature, 45(3), 686–702.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nordhaus, W. D. and Boyer, J. 2000. Warming the World: Economic Models of Global Warming. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Page, E. 2006. Climate Change, Justice and Future Generations. Cheltenham, UK: Edward Elgar.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Parfit, D. 1986. Reasons and Persons. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Patz, J.et al. 2000. The potential health impacts of climate variability and change for the United States: Executive Summary of the Report of the Health Sector of the US National Assessment. Environmental Health Perspectives, 108(4), 367–76.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pearce, D., Groom, B., Hepburn, C. and Koundouri, P. 2003. Valuing the future: recent advances in social discounting. World Economics, 4(2), 121–41.Google Scholar
Pearce, D., Markandya, A. and Barbier, E. B. 1989. Blueprint for a Green Economy. London: Earthscan.Google Scholar
Pigou, A. C. 1946. The Economics of Welfare. 4th edn. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Posner, R. 2004. Catastrophe: Risk and Response. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Ramsey, F. 1928. A mathematical theory of saving. Economic Journal, 38(152), 543–59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Raupach, M. R.et al. 2007. Global and regional drivers of accelerating CO2 emissions. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 104(24), 10 288–93.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Rawls, J. 1999. A Theory of Justice, revised edn. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Raz, J. 1986. The Morality of Freedom. Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Sagoff, M. 1988. The Economy of the Earth. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Scheffler, S. 1982. The Rejection of Consequentialism: A Philosophical Investigation of the Considerations Underlying Rival Moral Conceptions. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Schelling, T. 1995. Intergenerational discounting. Energy Policy, 23(4/5), 395–401.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sen, A. K., 1961. On optimizing the rate of saving. Economic Journal, 71.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sen, A. K., 1967. Isolation, assurance and the social rate of discount. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 81(1), 112–24.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sen, A. K. 1982. Approaches to the choice of discount rates for social benefit–cost analysis. In Lind, Robert C.et al., eds., Discounting for Time and Risk in Energy Policy. Washington, DC: Resources for the Future, pp. 325–53.Google Scholar
Sidgwick, H. 1981 [1907]. The Methods of Ethics, 7th edn. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Company.Google Scholar
Stern, N. 2007. The Economics of Climate Change: The Stern Review. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Solomon, S.et al. 2007. Technical summary. In Solomon, S.et al., eds., Climate Change 2007: The Physical Science Basis. Contribution of Working Group I to the Fourth Assessment Report of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, pp. 20–91.Google Scholar
Turner, R. K., Pearce, D. and Bateman, I. 1994. Environmental Economics: An Elementary Introduction. New York, NY: Harvester Wheatsheaf.Google Scholar
Weitzman, M. L. 2001. Gamma discounting. American Economic Review, 91(1), 260–71.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weitzman, M. L. 2007. A review of the Stern review on the economics of climate change. Journal of Economic Literature, 45(3), 703–24.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×