Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-p9bg8 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-27T17:14:20.293Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

23 - The Nation-State

from VII - Society

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 December 2012

Allen W. Wood
Affiliation:
Stanford University, California
Songsuk Susan Hahn
Affiliation:
Université Concordia, Montréal, Québec
Get access

Summary

The concept of the nation entered the political arena in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries. It was used to express a new doctrine of political legitimacy based on a corporate metaphor: that there is, or should be, a body of subjects enduring over generations and changes of government, and that this body is authorized to confirm or reject the basic laws of the land. Since its first appearances in English republican rhetoric, the word ‘nation’ was used to mean a body of people who had ultimate authority or sovereignty over rulers and laws and who possessed in this capacity a moral identity distinct from the state. This distinctness made it possible to think of nations as the source of legitimacy in states. Although some later authors argued that national bodies must be defined by cultural features such as language or religion, the earliest political uses of the term ‘nation’ were open-ended about the characteristics that should distinguish one sovereign entity from another. If the early modern language of nationhood expressed any core idea, it was that polities should ideally be grounded in the authority conferred by a sovereign people who share both a sense of corporate identity with each other and a sense of being distinct from other peoples. The ‘nation’ in nation-state came to imply that states should have a special kind of legitimacy based on an identity among an entire population of a territory, cutting across diverse regions and social groups. A corollary of this idea was that legitimacy should originate in the people or polity, not be imposed from without.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2012

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Fichte, Johann Gottlieb. Fichtes sämtliche Werke. Ed. Fichte, I. H.. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1970.Google Scholar
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich.Werke: Theoriewerkausgabe. Eds. Moldenhauer, Eva and Michel, Karl Markus. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1970–.Google Scholar
Herder, Johann Gottfried. Werke in zehn Bänden. Eds. Bollacher, Martin et al. Frankfurt: Deutscher Klassiker, 1985.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel. Kants Gesammelte Schriften. Ed. Preussische, Königlich (later Deutsche und Berlin-Brandenburgische) Akademie der Wissenschaften. 29 vols. Berlin: G. Reimer (later Walter de Gruyter), 1900–.Google Scholar
Mill, John Stuart. Collected Works of John Stuart Mill. Ed. Robson, John M.. Toronto: University of Toronto Press; London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1963–91.Google Scholar
Herder, J. G., Werke in zehn Bänden, eds. Martin Bollacher et al. (Frankfurt: Deutscher Klassiker, 1985) [henceforth Herder, Werke], 9/2:11–126; Auch eine Philosophie der Geschichte, Herder, Werke 4:11–107Google Scholar
Fichte, J. G., Fichtes sämtliche Werke, ed. Fichte, I. H. (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1970) [henceforth Fichte, SW], 7:311–12Google Scholar
“Idee zu einer allgemeinen Geschichte,” Kant, Ak 8:17–30; in Kant: Political Writings, ed. Hans Reiss, 2nd ed. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 44–5
Kritik der praktischen Vernunft, Kant, Ak 5:85; in Practical Philosophy, ed. Mary Gregor (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999), 208
Die Verfassung Deutschlands, Hegel, Werke 1:461–72; in Hegel: Political Writings, eds. Laurence Dickey and H. B. Nisbet (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999), 7
Enzyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften III, Hegel, Werke 10:350; Philosophy of Mind, trans. William Wallace (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1971), 279
Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts, Hegel, Werke 7:409–11; Philosophy of Right, trans T. M. Knox (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1967), 208–10
Marx, Karl and Engels, Friedrich, Collected Works, vol. 7 (New York: International, 1975–; reprint, London: Lawrence & Wishart, 2000)Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×