Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-j824f Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-07T10:29:56.188Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

20 - Divine Omnipotence, Omniscience, and Human Freedom

from V - Metaphysics and Philosophical Theology

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 May 2009

Steven Nadler
Affiliation:
University of Wisconsin, Madison
T. M. Rudavsky
Affiliation:
Ohio State University
Get access

Summary

Is anything impossible for the Lord?

(Genesis 18:14)

Know this for a certain, that your descendants will be aliens living in a land that is not theirs; they will be slaves, and will be held in oppression there for four hundred years.

(Genesis 15:13)

Choose life.

(Deuteronomy 30:19)

INTRODUCTION

The religious traditions of Judaism, Christianity, and Islam all seem to require belief in God’s unlimited power, all-encompassing knowledge, and human choice. The Bible is full of stories about miracles, but how would miracles be possible if God is not omnipotent? Prophecy is an essential component of scripture, but would prophecy be possible if God did not know the future? Man is commanded to perform all kinds of commandments. If he obeys, he is rewarded; if he disobeys, he is punished. This presupposes that he has the choice to obey or disobey, and thus is responsible for his choices. Once we begin to reflect on these religious dogmas, we realize that things may not be so clear. Is God’s power really unlimited? Can He do the impossible? Moreover, if God is truly omniscient and knows the future, are the outcomes of the future so fixed that no alternatives are possible? If so, it would seem that man is not really free when he appears to be making a choice. It is thus no surprise that the philosophical and theological literature of Judaism, Christianity, and Islam are replete with discussions of these perplexing problems.

Type
Chapter
Information
The Cambridge History of Jewish Philosophy
From Antiquity through the Seventeenth Century
, pp. 659 - 704
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2008

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Abrabanel, Isaac (1863). Mif⼸alot Elohim. Lemberg.Google Scholar
Abrabanel, Isaac (1964). Commentary on the Torah. Jerusalem: Benei Arabel.Google Scholar
Al-Ghazālī, Abu Hamid (1997). The Incoherence of the Philosophers. Marmura, Michael E. (trans. and ed.). Provo, UT: Brigham Young University Press.Google Scholar
Albo, Joseph (1946). Sefer Iqqarim (Book of Principles). Husik, I. (trans.). Philadelphia: Jewish Publication Society.Google Scholar
Altmann, Alexander (1974). “Free Will, and Predestination in Saadia, Bahya and Maimonides,” in Goitein, S.D. (ed.), Religion in a Religious Age. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Arama, Isaac (1849). ⼸Aqedat Yitzhaq. Pressburg (Jerusalem Reprint).Google Scholar
Averroes, (1969). Tahāfut al-Tahāfut (The Incoherence of the Incoherence). Bergh, Simon (trans.). London: Luzac and Co.Google Scholar
Baer, F.I. (1940). “Abner of Burgos’ Minḥath Kenaoth and its Influence on Hasdai Crescas,” Tarbiz. 11:. [Hebrew]Google Scholar
Baer, F.I. (1971). A History of the Jews in Spain. Philadelphia: Jewish Publication Society.Google Scholar
Borodowski, A. (2003). Isaac Abravanel on Miracles, Creation, Prophecy and Evil: The Tension Between Medieval Jewish Philosophy and Biblical Commentary. New York: Peter Lang.Google Scholar
Craig, W.L. (1988). The Problem of Divine Foreknowledge and Future Contingents from Aristotle to Suarez. Leiden: E.J. Brill.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Duran, Profiat (1872). Commentary on the Guide of the Perplexed. Warsaw.Google Scholar
Feldman, Seymour (1982). “Crescas’ Theological Determinism,” Da⼸at. 9:.Google Scholar
Feldman, Seymour (1985). “The Binding of Isaac: A Test Case for Divine Omniscience,” in Rudavsky 1985.Google Scholar
Feldman, Seymour (1994). “R. Isaac Abravanel’s Defense of Creation “Ex Nihilo.” Proceedings of the Eleventh World Congress of Jewish Studies, Division C. Jerusalem:.Google Scholar
Feldman, Seymour (2003). Philosophy in a Time of Crisis: Don Isaac Abravanel, Defender of the Faith. London: Routledge Curzon.Google Scholar
Fischer, John M. and Ravizza, M. (1993). Perspectives on Moral Responsibility. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Gellman, J. (1989). “Freedom and Determinism in Maimonides’ Philosophy,” in Ormsby, E. (ed.), Moses Maimonides and his Time. Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press.Google Scholar
Gersonides, (1999). The Wars of the Lord, volume 3: Books Five and Six. Feldman, Seymour (trans.). Philadelphia: Jewish Publication Society.Google Scholar
Guttmann, Julius (1935). “Das Problem der Willensfreiheit bei Hasdai Crescas und den islamischen Aristotelikern,” in Baron, S.W. and Marx, A. (eds.). Jewish Studies in Memory of G. A. Kohut. New York.Google Scholar
Guttmann, Julius (1946). “The Philosophy of Isaac Albalag,” Louis Ginzberg Jubilee Volume. New York: Jewish Theological Seminary Press. [Hebrew]Google Scholar
Guttmann, Julius (1964). Philosophies of Judaism: the History of Jewish Philosophy from Biblical Times to Franz Rosenzweig. Silverman, David W. (trans.). New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston.Google Scholar
Harvey, Warren Zev (1984-5). “Notes on the term ‘feeling of compulsion and necessity’ in Ḥasdai Crescas,” Jerusalem Studies in Jewish Thought. 4:.Google Scholar
Hayoun, Maurice Reuben. (1989). La Philosophie et la Théologie de Moise de Narbonne. Tubingen: C.B. Mohr.Google Scholar
Hourani, G. (1972). “Ibn Sina on Necessary and Possible Existence,” Philosophical Forum. 4:.Google Scholar
Husik, Isaac (1916). A History of Medieval Jewish Philosophy. New York: Atheneum.Google Scholar
Hyman, Arthur and Walsh, James (1973). Philosophy in the Middle Ages. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Company.Google Scholar
Hyman, Arthur (1997). “Aspects of the Medieval Jewish and Islamic Discussions of Free Choice,” in Manekin, C. and Kellner, M. (eds.), Freedom and Responsibility: General and Jewish Perspectives, Baltimore: University Press of Maryland.Google Scholar
Ivry, Alfred (1982). “Maimonides on Possibility,” in Reinhard, J. and Schwetschinski, D. (eds.), Mystics, Philosophers and Politicians: Essays in Jewish Intellectual History in Honor of Alexander Altmann. Durham: Duke University Press.Google Scholar
Ivry, Alfred (1985). “Providence, Divine Omniscience and Possibility: The Case of Maimonides,” in Rudavsky 1985.Google Scholar
Kellner, Menachem (1980). “Gersonides on Miracles, the Messiah and Resurrection,” Da⼸at. 4:.Google Scholar
Kellner, Menachem (1992). “Bibliographia Gersonideana. An Annotated List of Writings by and About R. Levi ben Gershom,” in Freudenthal 1992.Google Scholar
Knuuttila, S. (1993). Modalities in Medieval Philosophy. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Kogan, Barry S. (1985). “Some Reflections on the Problem of Future Contingency in Al-Fārābī, Avicenna and Averroes,” in Rudavsky 1985.Google Scholar
Maimonides, (1963). The Guide of the Perplexed. 2 vols., Pines, Shlomo (trans.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Maimonides, (1970-1). The Medical Aphorisms of Moses Maimonides. Rosner, Fred and Muntner, Suessman (eds. and trans.). New York: Yeshiva University Press.Google Scholar
Maimonides, (1985b). Essay on Resurrection, in Maimonides 1985a.Google Scholar
Manekin, Charles H. (1998). “On the Limited-Omniscience Interpretation of Gersonides’ Theory of Divine Knowledge,” in Ivry, A., Wolfson, E., and Arkush, A. (eds.), Perspectives on Jewish Thought and Mysticism. Amsterdam: Harwood Academic Publishing.Google Scholar
Manekin, Charles H. (2002). “Maimonides on Divine Knowledge: Moses of Narbonne’s Averroist Reading,” American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly. 76:.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marmura, M. (1985). “Divine Omniscience and Future Contingents in Al-Fārābī and Avicenna,” in Rudavsky 1985.Google Scholar
,Nissim of Gerona (1973). Derashot Ha-Ran. Feldman, Leon (ed.). Jerusalem: Institute Shalem.Google Scholar
Philoponus, John (1899). On the Eternity of the World: Against Proclus. Rabe, H. (ed.). Berlin.Google Scholar
Pines, Shlomo (1960). “Studies in Abū-Barakāt al-Baghdādi’s Poetics and Metaphysics,” Scripta Hierosolymitana. 6:.Google Scholar
Pines, Shlomo (1986c). “Some Topics dealt with in Pulgar’s treatise ⼸Ezer Ha-Dat and Parallels in Spinoza,” in Studies Presented to Isaiah Tishby. Jerusalem. [Hebrew]Google Scholar
Pollegar, Isaac. (1984). Ezer Ha-Dat (The Support of Religion). Levinger, J. (ed.). Tel-Aviv: Tel-Aviv University Press.Google Scholar
Prior, A. (1968). “The Formalities of Omniscience,” in Prior, A., Papers on Time and Tense. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Proclus, (1833). Ten Doubts on Providence. Taylor, T. (trans.). London.Google Scholar
Ravitsky, Aviezer (1988). Crescas’ Sermon on the Passover and Studies in his Philosophy. Jerusalem: Israel Academy of Sciences and Humanities. [Hebrew]Google Scholar
Rudavsky, T.M. (2000). Time Matters: Time, Creation and Cosmology in Medieval Jewish Philosophy. Albany: SUNY Press.Google Scholar
Rudavsky, T.M. (2003). “The Impact of Scholasticism upon Jewish Philosophy in the fourteenth and fifteenth Centuries”, in Frank and Leaman, 2003.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Samuelson, Norbert Max (1977a). Gersonides on God’s Knowledge. Toronto, Ontario: Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies.Google Scholar
Schwamm, Hermann (1934). Das goettliche Vorherwissen und seinen ersten Aufhaengern. Innsbruck: Felizian Rauch.Google Scholar
Schweid, Eliezer (1970b). Dibre Mabo, in Crescas 1970.Google Scholar
Sirat, Colette, Klein-Braslavy, Sara and Weijers, Olga (2003). Les méthodes de travail de Gersonide et le maniement du savoir chez les scolastiques. Paris: Vrin.Google Scholar
Sirat, Colette (1985). A History of Jewish Philosophy in the Middle Ages. Paris: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Sorabji, R. (1980). Necessity, Cause and Blame: Perspectives in Aristotle’s Theory. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Stern, Josef (1997). “Maimonides’ Conceptions of Freedom and the Sense of Shame,” in Manekin, C. and Kellner, M.. (eds.), Freedom and Moral Responsibility: General and Jewish Perspectives. University of Maryland Press.Google Scholar
Touati, C. (1990c). Prophetes, Talmudistes, Philosophes. Paris: Les Editions du Cerf.Google Scholar
Touati, Charles (1962). “Verité philosophique et vérite prophetique chez Isaac Albalag,” Revue des études juives. 121:.Google Scholar
Touati, Charles (1973). La Pensée philosophique et théologique de Gersonide. Paris: Éditions de Minuit.Google Scholar
Wilensky, S. (1956). The Philosophy of Isaac Arama. Jerusalem: Mossad Bialik. [Hebrew]Google Scholar
Wolfson, Harry A. (1929a). Crescas’ Critique of Aristotle. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Wolfson, Harry A. (1976). The Philosophy of the Kalām. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×