Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-dsjbd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-25T19:11:03.974Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

5 - Philosophical Perspectives on Imagination in the Western Tradition

from Part I - Theoretical Perspectives on the Imagination

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  26 May 2020

Anna Abraham
Affiliation:
University of Georgia
Get access

Summary

Philosophers in the Western tradition have both theorized about imagination and used imagination in their theorizing about other matters. In this chapter, I first provide a brief overview of philosophical theorizing about imagination with a special focus on its relation to other mental states such as belief and perception. I then turn to a discussion of the methodological role that imagination has played in philosophy. I here focus on the imaginability principle, i.e. the claim that the imaginability of a given scenario entails that such a scenario is in some sense possible. Relying on this kind of principle, philosophers have used imagination to justify theories in domains such as philosophy of mind, metaphysics and ethics.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2020

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Balcerak Jackson, M. (2016). On the Epistemic Value of Imagining, Supposing, and Conceiving. In Kind, A. and Kung, P., (eds.), Knowledge Through Imagination. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 4160.Google Scholar
Brann, E. (1991). The World of Imagination. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.Google Scholar
Byrne, R. M. J. (2005). The Rational Imagination: How People Create Alternatives to Reality. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Church, J. (2010). Seeing Reasons. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 80(3), 638670.Google Scholar
Churchland, P. S. (1998). The Hornswoggle Problem. In Shear, J. (ed.), Explaining Consciousness: The Hard Problem. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 3744.Google Scholar
Currie, G. (1990). The Nature of Fiction. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Currie, G., and Jureidini, J. (2004). Narrative and Coherence. Mind & Language, 19, 409427.Google Scholar
Currie, G., and Ravenscroft, I. (2002). Recreative Minds. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dennett, D. (1991). Consciousness Explained. Boston, MA: Little, Brown and Company.Google Scholar
Descartes, R. (1641/1986). Meditations on First Philosophy with Selections from the Objections and Replies. Translated by John Cottingham. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Doggett, T., and Egan, A. (2007). Wanting Things You Don’t Want: The Case for an Imaginative Analogue of Desire. Philosophers’ Imprint, 7(9), 117.Google Scholar
Egan, A. (2008). Imagination, Delusion, and Self-Deception. In Bayne, T. and Fernandez, J. (eds.), Delusion and Self-Deception: Affective Influences on Belief-Formation. New York, NY: Psychology Press, 263280.Google Scholar
Gendler, T., and Hawthorne, J. 2002. Conceivability and Possibility. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Gertler, B. (2007). In Defense of Mind-Body Dualism. In Feinberg, J. and Shafer-Landau, R. (eds.), Reason and Responsibility. Boston, MA: Wadsworth, 312324.Google Scholar
Gettier, E. (1963). Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Analysis, 23(6), 121123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldman, A. I. (2006). Simulating Minds: The Philosophy, Psychology, and Neuroscience of Mindreading. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hofstadter, D. (1979). Gödel, Escher, Bach: An Eternal Golden Braid. New York, NY: Random House Books.Google Scholar
Humberstone, I. L. (1992). Direction of Fit. Mind, 101(401), 5983.Google Scholar
Hume, D. (1739/1985). A Treatise of Human Nature. Edited by Nidditch, P. H.. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Jackson, F. (1982). Epiphenomenal Qualia. Philosophical Quarterly, 32, 127136.Google Scholar
Kant, I. (1787/1998). Critique of Pure Reason. Translated by P. Guyer and A. Wood. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kind, A. (2001). Putting the Image Back in Imagination. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 62(1), 85109.Google Scholar
Kind, A.(2013). The Heterogeneity of the Imagination. Erkenntnis, 78(1), 141159.Google Scholar
Kind, A.(2016). Desire-Like Imagination. In Kind, A. (ed.), The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Imagination. London, UK; New York, NY: Routledge, 163176.Google Scholar
Kind, A.(2017). Imaginative Vividness. Journal of the American Philosophical Association, 3(1), 3250.Google Scholar
Kind, A.(Forthcoming). Imaginative Experience. In Kriegel, U. (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of the Philosophy of Consciousness. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kind, A., and Kung, P. (eds.) (2016). Knowledge Through Imagination. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kriegel, U. (2015). The Varieties of Consciousness. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kung, P. (2010). Imagining as a Guide to Possibility. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 81, 620663.Google Scholar
McGinn, C. (2004). Mindsight. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Nagel, T. (1974). What is it like to Be a Bat? Philosophical Review, 83(October), 435450.Google Scholar
Nanay, B. (2010). Perception and Imagination: Amodal Perception as Mental Imagery. Philosophical Studies, 150, 239254.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nichols, S. (2004). Imagining and Believing: The Promise of a Single Code. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 62(2), 129139.Google Scholar
Parfit, D. (1984). Reasons and Persons. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pavese, C. (2016). Skill in Epistemology I. Philosophy Compass, 11, 642649.Google Scholar
Peacocke, C. (1985). Imagination, Experience and Possibility: A Berkeleian View Defended. In Foster, J. and Robinson, H. (eds.), Essays on Berkeley. Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press, 1935.Google Scholar
Perky, C. W. (1910). An Experimental Study of Imagination. American Journal of Psychology, 21, 422452.Google Scholar
Polyani, M. (1966/2009). Creative Imagination. Reprinted in Bardsley, K., Dutton, D., and Krausz, M. (eds.), The Idea of Creativity. Leiden, Netherlands: Brill, 147163.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. (1971). A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Sartre, J. (1936/1962). Imagination. Translated by Forrest Williams. Ann Arbor, MI: The University of Michigan Press.Google Scholar
Sartre, J.(1940/2010). The Imaginary. Translated by Jonathan Webber. London, UK: Routledge.Google Scholar
Schellenberg, S. (2013). Belief and Desire in Imagination and Immersion. Journal of Philosophy, 110(9), 497517.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shah, N., and Velleman, J. D. (2005). Doxastic Deliberation. Philosophical Review, 114(4), 497534.Google Scholar
Stanley, J., and Williamson, T. (2017). Skill. Noûs, 51(4), 713726.Google Scholar
Stock, K. (2017). Only Imagine. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Strawson, P. F. (1970). Imagination and Perception. In Foster, L. and Swanson, J. W. (eds.), Experience and Theory. Amherst, MA: University of Massachusetts Press, 3154.Google Scholar
Thomson, J. J. (1971). A Defense of Abortion. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 1(1), 4766.Google Scholar
Tidman, P. (1994). Conceivability as a Test for Possibility. American Philosophical Quarterly, 31(4), 297309.Google Scholar
Toon, A. (2012). Models as Make-Believe: Imagination, Fiction, and Scientific Representation. Basingstoke, UK: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Leeuwen, N. (2013). The Meanings of “Imagine” Part I: Constructive Imagination. Philosophy Compass, 8(3), 220230.Google Scholar
Walton, K. (1990). Mimesis as Make Believe. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Weinberg, J. M., and Meskin, A. (2006). Imagine That! In Kieran, M. (ed.), Contemporary Debates in Aesthetics and the Philosophy of Art. Oxford, UK: Blackwell, 222235.Google Scholar
White, A. R. (1990). The Language of Imagination. Oxford, UK: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×