Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-6bf8c574d5-xtvcr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-23T08:39:38.588Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

24 - Lessons from Moral Psychology for Moral Philosophy

from Part V - Applications and Extensions

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  20 February 2025

Bertram Malle
Affiliation:
Brown University, Rhode Island
Philip Robbins
Affiliation:
University of Missouri
Get access

Summary

This chapter of the handbook suggests some lessons from moral psychology for ethics and metaethics. The authors note that empirical research on a wide range of topics, including moral character, happiness and well-being, free will and moral responsibility, and moral judgment, has had a profound influence on recent philosophical theorizing about the foundations of morality. In their chapter they focus on one issue of particular importance: the reliability and trustworthiness of moral judgment. They critically assess three lines of argument that threaten to undermine epistemic confidence in our moral judgments, namely process debunking arguments, arguments from disagreement, and arguments from irrelevant influences. Though the jury is still out on how successful these arguments are, there is little question that they have potentially profound implications both for moral epistemology and philosophical methodology. Perhaps the most important lesson for ethics and metaethics to be drawn from moral psychology, then, may be that future progress in moral philosophy is likely to depend on philosophers and psychologists working together, rather than in isolation from one another.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2025

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Aldrich, D., & Kage, R. (2003). Mars and Venus at twilight: A critical investigation of moralism, age effects, and sex differences. Political Psychology, 24(1), 2340.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alexander, J., Mallon, R., & Weinberg, J. M. (2014). Accentuate the negative. In Knobe, J. & Nichols, S (Eds.), Experimental philosophy (Vol. 2, pp. 3150). Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alexandrova, A. (2017). A philosophy for the science of well-being. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Andow, J. (2016). Qualitative tools and experimental philosophy. Philosophical Psychology, 29(8), 11281141.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ansani, A., D’Errico, F., & Poggi, I. (2017). “It sounds wrong…” Does music affect moral judgement? In Gervasi, O., Murgante, B., Misra, S., Borruso, G., Torre, C. M., Rocha, A. M. A. C., Taniar, D., Apduhan, B. O., Stankova, E., & Cuzzocrea, A. (Eds.), Computational science and its applications – ICCSA 2017, 10409 (pp. 753760). Springer International Publishing.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anscombe, G. E. M. (1958). Modern moral philosophy. Philosophy, 33(124), 119.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aramovich, N. P., Lytle, B. L., & Skitka, L. J. (2012). Opposing torture: Moral conviction and resistance to majority influence. Social Influence, 7(1), 2134.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aristotle. (2019). Nicomachean ethics (T. Irwin, Trans.; 3rd ed.). Hackett Publishing Company, Inc.Google Scholar
Arutyunova, K. R., Alexandrov, Y. I., & Hauser, M. D. (2016). Sociocultural influences on moral judgments: East–west, male–female, and young–old. Frontiers in Psychology, 7, Article 1334.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Asendorpf, J. B., Conner, M., Fruyt, F. D., Houwer, J. D., Denissen, J. J. A., Fiedler, K., Fiedler, S., Funder, D. C., Klieg, R., Nosek, B. A., Perugini, M., Roberts, B. W., Schmitt, M., van Aken, M. A. G., Weber, H., & Wicherts, J. M. (2013). Recommendations for increasing replicability in psychology. European Journal of Personality, 27(2), 108119.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Audi, R. (2008). Intuition, inference, and rational disagreement in ethics. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 11(5), 475492.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Banerjee, K., Huebner, B., & Hauser, M. (2010). Intuitive moral judgments are robust across variation in gender, education, politics and religion: A large-scale web-based study. Journal of Cognition and Culture, 10(3–4), 253281.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bauman, C. W., McGraw, A. P., Bartels, D. M., & Warren, C. (2014). Revisiting external validity: Concerns about trolley problems and other sacrificial dilemmas in moral psychology. Social and Personality Psychology Compass, 8(9), 536554.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bengson, J. (2013). Experimental attacks on intuitions and answers. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 86(3), 495532.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berker, S. (2009). The normative insignificance of neuroscience. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 37(4), 293329.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bishop, M. (2015). The good life: Unifying the philosophy and psychology of well-being. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Björklund, F. (2003). Differences in the justification of choices in moral dilemmas: Effects of gender, time pressure and dilemma seriousness. Scandinavian Journal of Psychology, 44(5), 459466.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bloom, P. (2010). How do morals change? Nature, 464(7288), 490490.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Boyd, R. (1988). How to be a moral realist. In Sayre-McCord, G (Ed.), Essays on moral realism (pp. 181228). Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Buchanan, A., & Powell, R. (2015). The limits of evolutionary explanations of morality and their implications for moral progress. Ethics, 126(1), 3767.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cameron, C. D., Payne, B. K., & Doris, J. M. (2013). Morality in high definition: Emotion differentiation calibrates the influence of incidental disgust on moral judgments. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 49(4), 719725.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Capraro, V., & Sippel, J. (2017). Gender differences in moral judgment and the evaluation of gender-specified moral agents. Cognitive Processing, 18(4), 399405.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Carlsmith, K. M. (2008). On justifying punishment: The discrepancy between words and actions. Social Justice Research, 21(2), 119137.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chapman, H. A., & Anderson, A. K. (2013). Things rank and gross in nature: A review and synthesis of moral disgust. Psychological Bulletin, 139(2), 300327.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Chituc, V., & Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (2020). Moral conformity and its philosophical lessons. Philosophical Psychology, 33(2), 262282.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, D., & Nisbett, R. E. (1994). Self-protection and the culture of honor: Explaining southern violence. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 20(5), 551567.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Costa, A., Foucart, A., Hayakawa, S., Aparici, M., Apesteguia, J., Heafner, J., & Keysar, B. (2014). Your morals depend on language. Sigman, M. (Ed.). PLoS ONE, 9(4), Article e94842.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Côté, S., Piff, P. K., & Willer, R. (2013). For whom do the ends justify the means? Social class and utilitarian moral judgment. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 104(3), 490503.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Curry, O. S. (2016). Morality as cooperation: A problem-centred approach. In Shackelford, T. K. & Hansen, R. D. (Eds.), The evolution of morality (pp. 2751). Springer International Publishing.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Daniels, N. (2020). Reflective equilibrium. In Zalta, E. N. (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Summer 2020 ed.). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2020/entries/reflective-equilibrium/Google Scholar
Darwall, S., Gibbard, A., & Railton, P. (1992). Toward fin de siecle ethics: Some trends. The Philosophical Review, 101(1), 115189.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
De Brigard, F. (2010). If you like it, does it matter if it’s real? Philosophical Psychology, 23(1), 4357.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Demaree-Cotton, J. (2016). Do framing effects make moral intuitions unreliable? Philosophical Psychology, 29(1), 122.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Deutsch, M. (2010). Intuitions, counter-examples, and experimental philosophy. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 1(3), 447460.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Doris, J. M. (2002). Lack of character: Personality and moral behavior. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Doris, J. M., & Plakias, A. (2008). How to argue about disagreement: Evaluative diversity and moral realism. In Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (Ed.), Moral psychology: Vol. 2. The cognitive science of morality: Intuition and diversity (pp. 303–231). MIT Press.Google Scholar
Dreyfus, H. L., & Dreyfus, S. E. (1991). Towards a phenomenology of ethical expertise. Human Studies, 14(4), 229250.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Driver, J. (2001). Uneasy virtue. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Driver, J. (2013). Moral expertise: Judgement, practice, and analysis. Social Philosophy and Policy, 30(1–2), 280296.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Enoch, D. (2010). Not just a truthometer: Taking oneself seriously (but not too seriously) in cases of peer disagreement. Mind, 119(476), 953997.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eskine, K. J., Kacinik, N. A., & Prinz, J. J. (2011). A bad taste in the mouth: Gustatory disgust influences moral judgment. Psychological Science, 22(3), 295299.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
FitzPatrick, W. (2016). Morality and evolutionary biology. In Zalta, E. N. (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2016 ed.). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2016/entries/morality-biology/Google Scholar
Flanagan, O. (1991). Varieties of moral personality. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Frances, B., & Matheson, J. (2019). Disagreement. In Zalta, E. N. (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Winter 2019 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab.Google Scholar
Fraser, B., & Hauser, M. (2010). The argument from disagreement and the role of cross-cultural empirical data. Mind & Language, 25(5), 541560.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Friedman, W. J., Robinson, A. B., & Friedman, B. L. (1987). Sex differences in moral judgments? A test of Gilligan’s theory. Psychology of Women Quarterly, 11(1), 3746.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Friesdorf, R., Conway, P., & Gawronski, B. (2015). Gender differences in responses to moral dilemmas: A process dissociation analysis. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 41(5), 696713.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Fumagalli, M., Ferrucci, R., Mameli, F., Marceglia, S., Mrakic-Sposta, S., Zago, S., Lucchiari, C., Consonni, D., Nordio, F., Pravettoni, G., Cappa, S., & Prioriet, A. (2010). Gender-related differences in moral judgments. Cognitive Processing, 11(3), 219226.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Galotti, K. M. (1989). Gender differences in self-reported moral reasoning: A review and new evidence. Journal of Youth and Adolescence, 18(5), 475488.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gawronski, B., Conway, P., Armstrong, J., Friesdorf, R., & Hütter, M. (2018). Effects of incidental emotions on moral dilemma judgments: An analysis using the CNI model. Emotion, 18(7), 9891008.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Geipel, J., Hadjichristidis, C., & Surian, L. (2015). How foreign language shapes moral judgment. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 59, 817.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ghelfi, E., Christopherson, C. D., Urry, H. L., Lenne, R. L., Legate, N., Fischer, M. A., Wagemans, F. M. A., Wiggins, B., Barrett, T., Bornstein, M., de Haan, B., Guberman, J., Issa, N., Kim, J., Na, E., O’Brien, J., Paulk, A., Peck, T., Sashihara, M., …, Sullivan, D. (2020). Reexamining the effect of gustatory disgust on moral judgment: A multilab direct replication of Eskine, Kacinik, and Prinz (2011). Advances in Methods and Practices in Psychological Science, 3(1), 323.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gilligan, C. (1982). In a different voice: Psychological theory and women’s development. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Gleichgerrcht, E., & Young, L. (2013). Low levels of empathic concern predict utilitarian moral judgment. PLoS ONE, 8(4), Article e60418.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Graham, J., Meindl, P., Beall, E., Johnson, K. M., & Zhang, L. (2016). Cultural differences in moral judgment and behavior, across and within societies. Current Opinion in Psychology, 8, 125130.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Greene, J. D. (2008). The secret joke of Kant’s soul. In Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (Ed.), Moral psychology: Vol. 3. The neuroscience of morality: Emotion, brain disorders, and development (pp. 3579). MIT Press.Google Scholar
Gump, L. S., Baker, R. C., & Roll, S. (2000). Cultural and gender differences in moral judgment: A study of Mexican Americans and Anglo-Americans. Hispanic Journal of Behavioral Sciences, 22(1), 7893.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haidt, J. (2001). The emotional dog and its rational tail: A social intuitionist approach to moral judgment. Psychological Review, 108(4), 814834.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Haidt, J., & Baron, J. (1996). Social roles and the moral judgement of acts and omissions. European Journal of Social Psychology, 26(2), 201218.3.0.CO;2-J>CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haidt, J., Koller, S. K., & Dias, M. G. (1993). Affect, culture, and morality, or is it wrong to eat your dog? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 65(4), 613628.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hall, L., Johansson, P., & Strandberg, T. (2012). Lifting the veil of morality: Choice blindness and attitude reversals on a self-transforming survey. PLoS ONE, 7(9), Article e45457.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hauser, M., Cushman, F., Young, L., Kang-Xing Jin, R., & Mikhail, J. (2007). A dissociation between moral judgments and justifications. Mind & Language, 22(1), 121.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haybron, D. M. (2010). The pursuit of unhappiness: The elusive psychology of well-being. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Henrich, J., Heine, S. J., & Norenzayan, A. (2010). The weirdest people in the world? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 33(2–3), 6183.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Horne, Z., & Livengood, J. (2017). Ordering effects, updating effects, and the specter of global skepticism. Synthese, 194(4), 11891218.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horowitz, T. (1998). Philosophical intuitions and psychological theory. Ethics, 108(2), 367385.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Huemer, M. (2005). Ethical intuitionism. Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Huemer, M. (2011). Epistemological egoism and agent-centered norms. In Dougherty, T. (Ed.), Evidentialism and its discontents (pp. 1733). Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hume, D. (2007). A treatise of human nature (Norton, D. F. & Norton, M. J., Eds.) (Vol. 1). Oxford University Press. (Original work published 1739)Google Scholar
Ioannidis, J. P. A. (2005). Why most published research findings are false. PLOS Medicine, 2(8), Article e124.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ioannidis, J. P. A. (2014). How to make more published research true. PLOS Medicine, 11(10), Article e1001747.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Jaffee, S., & Hyde, J. S. (2000). Gender differences in moral orientation: A meta-analysis. Psychological Bulletin, 126(5), 703726.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
James, W. (1918). The principles of psychology (Vol. 1). Henry Holt and Company. (Original work published 1890a)Google Scholar
James, W. (1918). The principles of psychology (Vol. 2). Henry Holt and Company. (Original work published 1890b)Google Scholar
Johnson, D. J., Wortman, J., Cheung, F., Hein, M., Lucas, R. E., Donnellan, M. B., Ebersole, C. R., & Narr, R. K. (2016). The effects of disgust on moral judgments: Testing moderators. Social Psychological and Personality Science, 7(7), 640647.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Joyce, R. (2006). Metaethics and the empirical sciences. Philosophical Explorations, 9(1), 133148.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kahane, G. (2011). Evolutionary debunking arguments. Noûs, 45(1), 103125.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kamm, F. M. (1993). Morality, mortality: Death and whom to save from it (Vol. 1). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kant, I. (1998). Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten (Hansen, F., Ed.). directmedia. (Original work published 1785)Google Scholar
Kauppinen, A. (2007). The rise and fall of experimental philosophy. Philosophical Explorations, 10(2), 95118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kelly, M., Ngo, L., Chituc, V., Huettel, S., & Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (2017). Moral conformity in online interactions: Rational justifications increase influence of peer opinions on moral judgments. Social Influence, 12(2–3), 5768.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Khader, S. J. (2011). Adaptive preferences and women’s empowerment. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kiehl, K. A., & Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (Eds.). (2013). Handbook on psychopathy and law. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kohlberg, L. (1971). From is to ought: How to commit the naturalistic fallacy and get away with it in the study of moral development. In Mischel, T. (Ed.), Cognitive development and epistemology (pp. 151235). Academic Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kumar, V., & May, J. (2019). How to debunk moral beliefs. In Suikkanen, J. & Kauppinen, A. (Eds.), Methodology and moral philosophy (pp. 2548). Routledge.Google Scholar
Landy, J. F., & Goodwin, G. P. (2015). Does incidental disgust amplify moral judgment? A meta-analytic review of experimental evidence. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 10(4), 518536.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Lanteri, A., Chelini, C., & Rizzello, S. (2008). An experimental investigation of emotions and reasoning in the trolley problem. Journal of Business Ethics, 83(4), 789804.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levine, C., Kohlberg, L., & Hewer, A. (1985). The current formulation of Kohlberg’s theory and a response to critics. Human Development, 28(2), 94100.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Machery, E., Kelly, D., & Stich, S. P. (2005). Moral realism and cross-cultural normative diversity. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 28(6), 830.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Machery, E., & Mallon, R. (2010). Evolution of morality. In Doris, J. M. (Ed.), The moral psychology handbook (pp. 346). Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maoz, U., & Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (Eds.). (2022). Free will: Philosophers and neuroscientists in conversation. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Margoni, F., Geipel, J., Hadjichristidis, C., & Surian, L. (2018). Moral judgment in old age: Evidence for an intent-to-outcome shift. Experimental Psychology, 65(2), 105114.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
May, J. (2018). Regard for reason in the moral mind. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
May, J. (2019). Précis of Regard for reason in the moral mind. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 42(e146), 160.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McDonald, K., Graves, R., Yin, S., Weese, T., & Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (2021). Valence framing effects on moral judgments: A meta-analysis. Cognition, 212, Article 104703.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
McDonald, K., Yin, S., Weese, T., & Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (2019). Do framing effects debunk moral beliefs? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 42(e162), 3536.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
McNair, S., Okan, Y., Hadjichristidis, C., & Bruine de Bruin, W. (2019). Age differences in moral judgment: Older adults are more deontological than younger adults. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 32(1), 4760.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Merritt, M. (2000). Virtue ethics and situationist personality psychology. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 3(4), 365383.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, C. (2013). Moral character: An empirical theory. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moore, G. E. (1959). Principia ethica. Cambridge University Press. (Original work published 1903)Google Scholar
Moran, J. M., Jolly, E., & Mitchell, J. P. (2012). Social-cognitive deficits in normal aging. Journal of Neuroscience, 32(16), 55535561.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Muda, R., Pieńkosz, D., Francis, K. B., & Białek, M. (2020). The moral foreign language effect is stable across presentation modalities. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 73(11), 19301938.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Muthukrishna, M., & Henrich, J. (2019). A problem in theory. Nature Human Behaviour, 3(3), 221229.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Nadelhoffer, T., & Feltz, A. (2008). The actor–observer bias and moral intuitions: Adding fuel to Sinnott-Armstrong’s fire. Neuroethics, 1(2), 133144.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nado, J. (2014). Philosophical expertise. Philosophy Compass, 9(9), 631641.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nichols, S. (2014). Process debunking and ethics. Ethics, 124(4), 727749.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nisbett, R. E., & Wilson, T. D. (1977). Telling more than we can know: Verbal reports on mental processes. Psychological Review, 84(3), 231259.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Norenzayan, A. (2013). Big gods: How religion transformed cooperation and conflict. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, M. (2011). Creating capabilities: The human development approach. Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pastötter, B., Gleixner, S., Neuhauser, T., & Bäuml, K. T. (2013). To push or not to push? Affective influences on moral judgment depend on decision frame. Cognition, 126(3), 373377.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Paulo, N. (2020). The unreliable intuitions objection against reflective equilibrium. The Journal of Ethics, 24(3), 333353.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Paxton, J. M., Ungar, L., & Greene, J. D. (2012). Reflection and reasoning in moral judgment. Cognitive Science, 36(1), 163177.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Petrinovich, L., & O’Neill, P. (1996). Influence of wording and framing effects on moral intuitions. Ethology and Sociobiology, 17(3), 145171.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pratt, M. W., Golding, G., Hunter, W., & Sampson, R. (1988). Sex differences in adult moral orientations. Journal of Personality, 56(2), 373391.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Prinz, J., & Nichols, S. (2016). Diachronic identity and the moral self. In Kiverstein, J. (Ed.), The Routledge handbook of philosophy of the social mind (pp. 449464). Routledge.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. (1971). A theory of justice. Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rehren, P., & Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (2021). Moral framing effects within subjects. Philosophical Psychology, 34(5), 611636.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rehren, P., & Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (2022). How stable are moral judgments? Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 14, 13771403.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosen, J. B., Brand, M., & Kalbe, E. (2016). Empathy mediates the effects of age and sex on altruistic moral decision making. Frontiers in Behavioral Neuroscience, 10, Article 67.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ross, D. (2002). The right and the good (Stratton-Lake, P., Ed.). Clarendon Press. (Original work published 1930)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rozin, P., Lowery, L., Imada, S., & Haidt, J. (1999). The CAD triad hypothesis: A mapping between three moral emotions (contempt, anger, disgust) and three moral codes (community, autonomy, divinity). Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 76(4), 574586.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ryberg, J. (2013). Moral intuitions and the expertise defence. Analysis, 73(1), 39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sauer, H. (2018). Debunking arguments in ethics. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sauer, H. (2019). Butchering benevolence moral progress beyond the expanding circle. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 22(1), 153167.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schnall, S., Haidt, J., Clore, G. L., & Jordan, A. H. (2008). Disgust as embodied moral judgment. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 34(8), 10961109.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Schwarz, N. (2012). Feelings-as-information theory. In Van Lange, P. A. M., Kruglanski, A. W., & Higgins, E. T. (Eds.), Handbook of theories of social psychology (Vol. 1, pp. 289308). SAGE Publications Ltd.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schwitzgebel, E., & Cushman, F. (2012). Expertise in moral reasoning? Order effects on moral judgment in professional philosophers and non-philosophers. Mind & Language, 27(2), 135153.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schwitzgebel, E., & Cushman, F. (2015). Philosophers’ biased judgments persist despite training, expertise and reflection. Cognition, 141, 127137.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Seidel, A., & Prinz, J. (2013). Sound morality: Irritating and icky noises amplify judgments in divergent moral domains. Cognition, 127(1), 15.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sen, A. (1993). Capability and well-being. In Nussbaum, M. & Sen, A. (Eds.), The quality of life (pp. 3053). Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shafer-Landau, R. (2003). Moral realism: A defence. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shafer-Landau, R. (2008). Defending ethical intuitionism. In Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (Ed.), Moral psychology: Vol. 2. The cognitive science of morality: Intuition and diversity (pp. 8395). MIT Press.Google Scholar
Shrout, P. E., & Rodgers, J. L. (2018). Psychology, science, and knowledge construction: Broadening perspectives from the replication crisis. Annual Review of Psychology, 69(1), 487510.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Singer, P. (2005). Ethics and intuitions. The Journal of Ethics, 9(3–4), 331352.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Singh, J. J., Garg, N., Govind, R., & Vitell, S. J. (2018). Anger strays, fear refrains: The differential effect of negative emotions on consumers’ ethical judgments. Journal of Business Ethics, 151(1), 235248.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (2008a). Framing moral intuitions. In Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (Ed.), Moral psychology: Vol. 2. The cognitive science of morality: Intuition and diversity (pp. 4776). MIT Press.Google Scholar
Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (Ed.). (2008b). Moral psychology: Vol. 1. The evolution of morality: Adaptations and innateness. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (Ed.). (2008c). Moral psychology: Vol. 2. The cognitive science of morality: Intuition and diversity. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (Ed.). (2008d). Moral psychology: Vol. 3. The neuroscience of morality: Emotion, brain disorders, and development. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (Ed.). (2014). Moral psychology: Vol. 4. Free will and moral responsibility. MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sinnott-Armstrong, W., & Miller, C. B. (Eds.). (2017). Moral psychology: Vol. 5. Virtue and character. MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Song, F., Parekh, S., Hooper, L., Loke, Y. K., Ford, J. K., Sutton, A. J., Hing, C., Kwok, C. S., Pang, C., & Harvey, I. (2010). Dissemination and publication of research findings: An updated review of related biases. Health Technology Assessment, 14(8), iii, ix–xi, 1193.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sorell, T. (2018). Experimental philosophy and the history of philosophy. British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 26(5), 829849.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sripada, C. (2018). Addiction and fallibility. Journal of Philosophy, 115(11), 569587.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stanley, T. D., Carter, E. C., & Doucouliagos, H. (2018). What meta-analyses reveal about the replicability of psychological research. Psychological Bulletin, 144(12), 13251346.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Street, S. (2006). A Darwinian dilemma for realist theories of value. Philosophical Studies, 127(1), 109166.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Strohminger, N., Lewis, R. L., & Meyer, D. E. (2011). Divergent effects of different positive emotions on moral judgment. Cognition, 119(2), 295300.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Strohminger, N., & Nichols, S. (2014). The essential moral self. Cognition, 131(1), 159171.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Stuart, M. T., Colaço, D., & Machery, E. (2019). P-curving x-phi: Does experimental philosophy have evidential value? Analysis, 79(4), 669684.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Summers, J. S., & Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (2019). Clean hands: Philosophical lessons from scrupulosity. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sytsma, J., & Livengood, J. (2015). The theory and practice of experimental philosophy. Broadview Press.Google Scholar
Tersman, F. (2022). Moral disagreement. In Zalta, E. N. & Nodelman, U. (Eds.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Fall 2022 ed.). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2022/entries/disagreement-moral/Google Scholar
Tiberius, V. (2013). Well-being, wisdom, and thick theorizing: On the division of labor between moral philosophy and positive psychology. In Kirchin, S. (Ed.), Thick concepts (pp. 217233). Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tiberius, V. (2015). Moral psychology: A contemporary introduction. Routledge.Google Scholar
Tiberius, V. (2018). Well-being as value fulfillment: How we can help each other to live well. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tobia, K. P., Chapman, G. B., & Stich, S. (2013). Cleanliness is next to morality, even for philosophers. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 20(11–12), 195204.Google Scholar
Tropman, E. (2011). Non-inferential moral knowledge. Acta Analytica, 26(4), 355366.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Valdesolo, P., & DeSteno, D. (2006). Manipulations of emotional context shape moral judgment. Psychological Science, 17(6), 476477.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Vavova, K. (2015). Evolutionary debunking of moral realism: Evolutionary debunking of moral realism. Philosophy Compass, 10(2), 104116.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weinberg, J. M., Gonnerman, C., Buckner, C., & Alexander, J. (2010). Are philosophers expert intuiters? Philosophical Psychology, 23(3), 331355.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wheatley, T., & Haidt, J. (2005). Hypnotic disgust makes moral judgments more severe. Psychological Science, 16(10), 780784.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wiegmann, A., & Waldmann, M. R. (2014). Transfer effects between moral dilemmas: A causal model theory. Cognition, 131(1), 2843.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Williamson, T. (2007). The philosophy of philosophy (The Blackwell/Brown Lectures in Philosophy 2). Blackwell Publishing.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilson, T. D., & Dunn, E. W. (2004). Self-knowledge: Its limits, value, and potential for improvement. Annual Review of Psychology, 55, 493518.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×