Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-fbnjt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-09T06:29:50.705Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Quality, Sensible

from ENTRIES

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 January 2016

Jill Buroker
Affiliation:
California State University, San Bernardino
Lawrence Nolan
Affiliation:
California State University, Long Beach
Get access

Summary

Descartes’ theory of sensible qualities is situated in his mathematical physics, which rejects Aristotle's naïve realism, according to which bodies actually have the colors, flavors, odors, hot, and cold we sense in them. Echoing Galileo's claim in The Assayer, that physics does not need to assume the reality of these qualities, Descartes argues that the only real properties of body are extension, shape, and motion. To make his case he denies the resemblance thesis, that the ideas of sensible qualities resemble the properties in bodies that cause them. Following Descartes, John Locke similarly rejects this thesis by means of the famous distinction between primary and secondary qualities of bodies.

While this much is generally agreed on, several interpretive issues concerning sensible qualities have arisen, including differing accounts of Descartes’ reasons for rejecting the resemblance thesis and his basis for claiming that sensory experience is obscure and confused. Other questions concern whether Descartes eliminates sensible qualities altogether from physics, the referents of sensible-quality terms, the metaphysical status of sensible qualities, and his analysis of real physical properties. (Note that Descartes’ theory of sensible qualities is not to be confused with his rejection of the Scholastic doctrine of real qualities. See Menn 1995 and quality, real.)

Throughout his writings, Descartes distinguishes the “sensible qualities” from the properties in bodies intelligible to the understanding. In the Principles of Philosophy IV.191–95, he reserves the term “quality” for the content of sensations produced in the mind by the five external senses: touch, taste, smell, hearing, and sight. Tactile qualities include hardness, heaviness, heat, and humidity; taste results in sensations of flavors; smell yields sensations of odors; from hearing arise sounds; and vision produces sensations of light and colors (AT VIIIA 318–19, CSM I 281–83). In the wax analysis in Second Meditation, he separates the sensible qualities from the essential properties of bodies. After stripping off the changeable features of the wax, he concludes that a clear and distinct grasp of body by the intellect reveals it to be “merely something extended, flexible and changeable.” Thus the coolness, fragrance, and color of the wax are merely ways it appears to perceivers under certain conditions (AT VII 30–32, CSM II 20–21).

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2015

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Atherton, Margaret. 2004. “Green Is like Bread: The Nature of Descartes’ Account of Color Perception,” in Perception and Reality, ed. Schumacher, R.. Paderborn: Mentis, 27–42.Google Scholar
Buroker, Jill Vance. 1991. “Descartes on Sensible Qualities,” Journal of the History of Philosophy 29: 585–611.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cottingham, John. 1990. “Descartes on Colour,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, n.s.,90: 231–46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Des Chene, Dennis. 1996. Physiologia. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Downing, Lisa. 2011. “Sensible Qualities and Material Bodies,” in Primary and Secondary Qualities: The Historical and Ongoing Debate, ed. Nolan, L.. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 109–35.Google Scholar
Garber, Daniel. 1992. Descartes’ Metaphysical Physics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Gaukroger, Stephen. 1995. Descartes: An Intellectual Biography. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Jolley, Nicholas. 1990. The Light of the Soul: Theories of Ideas in Leibniz, Malebranche, and Descartes. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Menn, Stephen. 1995. “The Greatest Stumbling Block: Descartes’ Denial of Real Qualities,” in Descartes and His Contemporaries: Meditations, Objections and Replies, ed. Ariew, R. and Grene, M.. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 182–207.Google Scholar
Nelson, Alan. 1996. “The Falsity in Sensory Ideas: Descartes and Arnauld,” in Interpreting Arnauld, ed. Kremer, E.. Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 13–32.Google Scholar
Nolan, Lawrence. 2011. “Descartes on What We Call ‘Color,’” in Primary and Secondary Qualities: The Historical and Ongoing Debate, ed. Nolan, L.. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 81–108.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nolan, Lawrence, and Whipple, John. 2006. “The Dustbin Theory of Mind: A Cartesian Legacy?,” Oxford Studies in Early Modern Philosophy 3: 33–55.Google Scholar
Schmaltz, Tad M. 1995. “Malebranche's Cartesianism and Lockean Colors,” History of Philosophy Quarterly 12: 387–403.Google Scholar
Simmons, Alison. 1999. “Are Cartesian Sensations Representational?,” Noûs 33: 347–69.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilson, Margaret. 1992. “History of Philosophy in Philosophy Today; and the Case of the Sensible Qualities,” Philosophical Review 101: 191–243.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilson, Margaret. 1978. Descartes. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wolf-Devine, Celia. 1993. Descartes on Seeing: Epistemology and Visual Perception. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Quality, Sensible
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.213
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Quality, Sensible
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.213
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Quality, Sensible
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.213
Available formats
×