Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-rdxmf Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-29T13:29:27.389Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Part VI - Critique

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  21 January 2021

Torben Spaak
Affiliation:
Stockholms Universitet
Patricia Mindus
Affiliation:
Uppsala Universitet, Sweden
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2021

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

References

Alexy, R. 1992. Begriff und Geltung des Rechts. Alber.Google Scholar
Alexy, R. 1997. Der Beschluß des Bundesverfassungsgerichts zu den Tötungen an der innerdeutschen Grenze vom 24. Oktober 1996. Jungius.Google Scholar
Alexy, R. 1999. ‘A Defence of Radbruch’s Formula’. In Dyzenhaus, D. (ed.). Recrafting the Rule of Law: The Limits of Legal Order. Hart: 1539.Google Scholar
Alexy, R. 2002. The Argument from Injustice: A Reply to Legal Positivism. Trans. Paulson, B. Litschewski and Paulson, S. L.. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Alexy, R. 2008. ‘On the Nature and the Concept of Law’. Ratio Juris 21: 281–99.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alexy, R. 2018. ‘Gustav Radbruchs Rechtsbegriff’. In von Arnauld, A., Augsberg, I. and Meyer-Pritzl, R. (eds.). 350 Jahre Rechtswissenschaftliche Fakultät der Christian-Albrechts-Universität zu Kiel. Mohr Siebeck: 237–49.Google Scholar
Baratta, A. 1959. ‘Relativismus und Naturrecht im Denken Gustav Radbruchs’. Archives for Philosophy of Law and Social Philosophy 45: 505–37.Google Scholar
Bix, B. 2011. ‘Radbruch’s Formula and Conceptual Analysis’. American Journal of Jurisprudence 56: 4557.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Borowski, M. 2015. ‘Begriff und Geltung des Rechts bei Gustav Radbruch’. In Borowski, M. and Paulson, S. L. (eds.). Die Natur des Rechts bei Gustav Radbruch. Mohr Siebeck: 229–65.Google Scholar
Borowski, M. 2018. Grundrechte als Prinzipien. 3rd ed. Nomos.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Borowski, M. 2019. ‘Radbruch’s Formula and Human Rights’. In La Torre, M., Niglia, L. and Susi, M. (eds.). The Quest for Rights. Edward Elgar: 2748.Google Scholar
Dreier, H. 1997. ‘Gustav Radbruch und die Mauerschützen’. Juristenzeitung 52: 421–34.Google Scholar
Dreier, H. 2015. ‘Die Radbruchsche Formel – Erkenntnis oder Bekenntnis?’. In Borowski, M. and Paulson, S. L. (eds.). Die Natur des Rechts bei Gustav Radbruch. Mohr Siebeck: 122.Google Scholar
Dreier, R. 1981. ‘Bemerkungen zur Rechtserkenntnistheorie’. In Aarnio, A., Niiniluoto, I. and Uusitalo, J. (eds.). Methodologie und Erkenntnistheorie der juristischen Argumentation. Duncker & Humblot: 89105.Google Scholar
Dreier, R. 1993. ‘Gesetzliches Unrecht im SED-Staat? Am Beispiel des DDR-Grenzgesetzes’. In Haft, F. et al. (eds.). Strafgerechtigkeit. Festschrift für Arthur Kaufmann. C.F. Müller: 5792.Google Scholar
Dreier, R. 2011. ‘Gustav Radbruchs Rechtsbegriff’. In Mahlmann, M. (ed.). Gesellschaft und Gerechtigkeit. Festschrift für Hubert Rottleuthner. Nomos: 1744.Google Scholar
Dreier, R. 2015. ‘Kontinuitäten und Diskontinuitäten in der Rechtsphilosophie Radbruchs’. In Borowski, M. and Paulson, S. L. (eds.). Die Natur des Rechts bei Gustav Radbruch. Mohr Siebeck: 183228.Google Scholar
Dyzenhaus, D. 2010. Hard Cases in Wicked Legal Systems. 2nd ed. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Engisch, K. 1949–50. ‘Gustav Radbruch als Rechtsphilosoph’. Archives for Philosophy of Law and Social Philosophy 38: 305–16.Google Scholar
Evers, H.-U. 1956. Der Richter und das unsittliche Gesetz. De Gruyter.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Funke, A. 2003. ‘Überlegungen zu Gustav Radbruchs “Verleugnungsformel”’. Archives for Philosophy of Law and Social Philosophy 89: 116.Google Scholar
Haldemann, F. 2005. ‘Gustav Radbruch vs. Hans Kelsen: A Debate on Nazi Law’. Ratio Juris 18: 162–78.Google Scholar
Hart, H. L. A. 1958. ‘Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals’. Harvard Law Review 74: 593625.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hoerster, N. 2006. Was ist Recht? C.H. Beck.Google Scholar
Kant, I. 1996. ‘The Conflict of the Faculties’. Trans. Gregor, M. J. and Anchor, R.. In Wood, A. W., di Giovanni, G. and Kant, I. (eds.). Religion and Rational Theology. Cambridge University Press: 233327.Google Scholar
Kant, I. [1797]1999. Metaphysical Elements of Justice. First part of the Metaphysics of Morals. Trans. Ladd, J.. 2nd ed. Hackett.Google Scholar
Kelsen, H. 1945. General Theory of Law and State. Trans. Wedberg, A.. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Kelsen, H. [1961]1967. Pure Theory of Law. Trans. Knight, M.. University of California Press.Google Scholar
Kelsen, H. [1934]1992. Introduction to the Problems of Legal Theory. Trans. Paulson, B. Litschewski and Paulson, S. L.. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Müller, I. 1991. Hitler’s Justice: The Courts of the Third Reich. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Neumann, U. 2007. ‘Naturrecht und Positivismus im Denken Gustav Radbruchs. Kontinuitäten und Diskontinuitäten’. In Härle, W. and Vogel, B. (eds.). Vom Rechte, das mit uns geboren ist. Aktuelle Probleme des Naturrechts. Herder: 1132.Google Scholar
Neumann, U. 2015. ‘Zum Verhältnis von Rechtsgeltung und Rechtsbegriff’. In Borowski, M. and Paulson, S. L. (eds.). Die Natur des Rechts bei Gustav Radbruch. Mohr Siebeck: 129–49.Google Scholar
Paulson, S. L. 2006. ‘On the Background and Significance of Gustav Radbruch’s Post-War Papers’. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 26: 1740.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Paulson, S. L. 2008. ‘Ein ewiger Mythos: Gustav Radbruch als Rechtspositivist’. Juristenzeitung 63: 105–15.Google Scholar
Paulson, S. L. 2015. ‘Zur Kontinuität der nichtpositivistischen Rechtsphilosophie Gustav Radbruchs’. In Borowski, M. and Paulson, S. L. (eds.). Die Natur des Rechts bei Gustav Radbruch. Mohr Siebeck: 151–82.Google Scholar
Radbruch, G. [1914]1993 (RGA vol. 2). Grundzüge der Rechtsphilosophie. Quelle & Meyer. Reprinted in Kaufmann, A. and Radbruch, G. (eds.). Gesamtausgabe or Collected Works vol. 2: Rechtsphilosophie II. C.F. Müller: 9204.Google Scholar
Radbruch, G. 1924. ‘Die Problematik der Rechtsidee’. Die Dioskuren. Jahrbuch für Geisteswissenschaften 3: 4350. Reprinted in RGA vol. 2: 460–7.Google Scholar
Radbruch, G. [1932]1973. Rechtsphilosophie. Eds. Wolf, E. and Schneider, H.-P.. 8th ed. Koehler. Reprinted in RGA vol. 2: 206450.Google Scholar
Radbruch, G. [1932]1950. ‘Legal Philosophy’. Trans. Wilk, K.. In Wilk, K. (ed.). The Legal Philosophies of Lask, Radbruch, and Dabin. Harvard University Press: 47224.Google Scholar
Radbruch, G. 1934. ‘Le Relativisme dans la Philosophie du Droit’. Archives de Philosophie du Droit et de Sociologie Juridique 4: 105–10.Google Scholar
Radbruch, G. 1937–8. ‘Le But du Droit’. Annuaire de l’Institut de Philosophie du Droit et de Sociologie: 4859.Google Scholar
Radbruch, G. 1945. ‘Fünf Minuten Rechtsphilosophie’. Rhein-Neckar-Zeitung from 12 September. Reprinted in RGA vol. 3: 78–9.Google Scholar
Radbruch, G. 1946. ‘Gesetzliches Unrecht und übergesetzliches Recht’. Süddeutsche Juristenzeitung 1: 105–8. Reprinted in RGA vol. 3: 8393.Google Scholar
Radbruch, G. 1947. ‘Gesetz und Recht’. Stuttgarter Rundschau January: 56. Reprinted in RGA vol. 3: 96100.Google Scholar
Radbruch, G. 1948. Vorschule der Rechtsphilosophie. Schubert, H. and Stoltzenburg, J. (eds.). Scherer. Reprinted in RGA vol. 3: 121227.Google Scholar
Radbruch, G. [1934]1957. ’Der Relativismus in der Rechtsphilosophie’. In Radbruch, G.. Der Mensch im Recht. Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht: 80–7. Reprinted in RGA vol. 3: 17–22.Google Scholar
Radbruch, G. [1937]1957. ‘Der Zweck des Rechts’. In Radbruch, G.. Der Mensch im Recht. Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht: 88104. Reprinted in RGA vol. 3: 3950.Google Scholar
Radbruch, G. 1999. ‘Nachwort-Entwurf’. In Dreier, R. and Paulson, S. L. (eds.). Rechtsphilosophie. Studienausgabe. C.F. Müller: 193208. Reprinted in RGA vol. 2: 2539.Google Scholar
Radbruch, G. 2003. Rechtsphilosophische Tagesfragen. Eds. Adachi, H. and Teifke, N.. Nomos.Google Scholar
Radbruch, G. 2006a. ‘Five Minutes of Legal Philosophy’. Trans. Paulson, B. Litschewski and Paulson, S. L.. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 26: 1315.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Radbruch, G. 2006b. ‘Statutory Lawlessness and Supra-Statutory Law’. Trans. Paulson, B. Litschewski and Paulson, S.L.. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 26: 111.Google Scholar
Schröder, J. 2005. ‘Gab es im deutschen Kaiserreich einen Gesetzespositivismus?’. In Baumann, W. et al. (eds.). Gesetz, Recht, Rechtsgeschichte. Festschrift für Gerhard Otte. Sellier: 571–9.Google Scholar
Seidel, K. 1999. Rechtsphilosophische Aspekte der ‘Mauerschützen’-Prozesse. Duncker & Humblot.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Spaak, T. 2009. ‘Meta-ethics and Legal Theory: The Case of Gustav Radbruch’. Law and Philosophy 28: 261–90.Google Scholar
Waldron, J. 1996. ‘Kant’s Legal Positivism’. Harvard Law Review 109: 1535–66.Google Scholar
Wiegandt, M.-A. 2004. Unrichtiges Recht. Mohr Siebeck.Google Scholar

References

Barnard, C. I. 1938/1942. The Functions of the Executive. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Barzun, C. L. 2017. ‘Jerome Frank, Lon Fuller, and a Romantic Pragmatism’. Yale Journal of Law and the Humanities 29: 129–76.Google Scholar
Berman, H. J. 1956. On the Teaching of Law in the Liberal Arts Curriculum. Foundation Press.Google Scholar
Chase, W. C. 1982. The American Law School and the Rise of Administrative Government. University of Wisconsin Press.Google Scholar
De Tocqueville, A. 1988. Democracy in America. Harper Perennial.Google Scholar
Fuller, L. 1930–1/1967. Legal Fictions. Illinois Law Review 25/Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Fuller, L. 1934. ‘American Legal Realism’. University of Pennsylvania Law Review 82: 429–62.Google Scholar
Fuller, L. 1939. ‘Williston on Contracts’. North Carolina Law Review 18: 115.Google Scholar
Fuller, L. 1940/1966. The Law in Quest of Itself. Northwestern University Press/Beacon Press.Google Scholar
Fuller, L. 1946. ‘Reason and Fiat in Case Law’. Harvard Law Review 59: 376–95.Google Scholar
Fuller, L. 1948. ‘What the Law Schools Can Contribute to the Making of Lawyers’. In Education for Professional Responsibility. Carnegie Press.Google Scholar
Fuller, L. 1949a. ‘The Place and Uses of Jurisprudence in the Law School Curriculum’. Journal of Legal Education 1: 495507.Google Scholar
Fuller, L. 1949b. The Problems of Jurisprudence. Temporary ed. Foundation Press.Google Scholar
Fuller, L. 1955a. ‘Freedom: A Suggested Analysis’. Harvard Law Review 68: 1305–25.Google Scholar
Fuller, L. 1955b. ‘The Philosophy of Codes of Ethics’. Electrical Engineering 74: 916–18.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fuller, L. 1958. ‘Positivism and Fidelity to Law: A Reply to Professor Hart’. Harvard Law Review 71: 630–72.Google Scholar
Fuller, L. 1965. ‘Irrigation and Tyranny’. Stanford Law Review 17: 1021–42.Google Scholar
Fuller, L. 1969. The Morality of Law. Revised ed. Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Fuller, L. 1970. ‘Jurisprudence’. Encyclopedia Britannica. 14th ed.Google Scholar
Fuller, L. 2001a. ‘Human Interaction and the Law’. In Winston, K. (ed.) The Principles of Social Order: Selected Essays of Lon L. Fuller. Revised ed. Hart Publishing: 211–48.Google Scholar
Fuller, L. 2001b. ‘The Lawyer as an Architect of Social Structures’. In Winston, K. (ed.) The Principles of Social Order: Selected Essays of Lon L. Fuller. Revised ed. Hart Publishing: 264–70.Google Scholar
Fuller, L. 2001c. ‘On Legal Education’. In Winston, K. (ed.) The Principles of Social Order: Selected Essays of Lon L. Fuller. Revised ed. Hart Publishing: 271–81.Google Scholar
Gilson, E. 1925. Saint Thomas D’Aquin. 2nd ed. Librairie Victor Lecoffre.Google Scholar
Hayek, F. 1952. The Counter-Revolution of Science. Free Press.Google Scholar
Hume, D. 1739/1888. A Treatise of Human Nature. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Llewellyn, K. N. and Hoebel, E. A. 1941. The Cheyenne Way. University of Oklahoma Press.Google Scholar
Maine, H. S. 1861/1963. Ancient Law. Beacon Press.Google Scholar
Ross, D. 1979. ‘The Development of the Social Sciences’. In Oleson, A. and Voss, J. (eds.). The Organization of Knowledge in Modern America, 1860–1920. Johns Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
Rundle, K. 2012. Forms Liberate: Reclaiming the Jurisprudence of Lon L Fuller. Hart Publishing.Google Scholar
Von Mises, R. 1951. Positivism: A Study in Human Understanding. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Wilson, D. J. 1990. Science, Community, and the Transformation of American Philosophy, 1860–1930. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Winston, K. 1988. ‘Is/Ought Redux: The Pragmatist Context of Lon Fuller’s Conception of Law’. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 8: 329–49.Google Scholar
Winston, K. 1999. ‘Three Models for the Study of Law’. In Witteveen, W. J. and van der Burg, W. (eds.). Rediscovering Fuller. Amsterdam University Press: 5177.Google Scholar
Winston, K. (ed.) 2001. The Principles of Social Order: Selected Essays of Lon L. Fuller. Revised ed. Hart Publishing.Google Scholar
Winston, K. 2005. ‘The Internal Morality of Chinese Legalism’. Singapore Journal of Legal Studies: 313–47.Google Scholar

References

Coleman, J. L. 1988. ‘Negative and Positive Positivism’. In Coleman, J.. Markets, Morals and the Law. Cambridge University Press: 327.Google Scholar
Coleman, J. L. 2001. The Practice of Principle: In Defense of a Pragmatist Approach to Legal Theory. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Coleman, J. L. and Simchen, O. 2003. ‘Law’. Legal Theory 1(1): 141.Google Scholar
Condren, C. 2014. The Status and Appraisal of Classic Texts. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Dewey, J. 1924. ‘Logical Method and Law’. Cornell Law Quarterly 10: 1727.Google Scholar
Dworkin, R. 1967. ‘The Model of Rules I’. University of Chicago Law Review 35(1): 1446.Google Scholar
Dworkin, R. 1977. The Philosophy of Law. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dworkin, R. 1978. Taking Rights Seriously. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Dworkin, R. 1986. Law’s Empire. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Dworkin, R. 2002. ‘Thirty Years On’. Harvard Law Review 115: 1655–87.Google Scholar
Dworkin, R. 2008. Justice in Robes. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Dworkin, R. 2011. Justice for Hedgehogs. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Gavison, R. 1987. ‘Comment’ [on Dworkin, ‘Legal Theory and the Problem of Sense’]. In Gavison, R. (ed.). Issues in Contemporary Legal Philosophy: The Influence of H.L.A. Hart. Clarendon Press: 2134.Google Scholar
Guest, S. 2012. Ronald Dworkin. 3rd ed. Stanford Law Books.Google Scholar
Harman, G. and Thomson, J. 1996. Moral Relativism and Moral Objectivity. Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Hart, H. L. A. 1955. ‘Theory and Definition in Jurisprudence’. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Suppl. 29: 259–64.Google Scholar
Hart, H. L. A. 1958. ‘Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals’, Harvard Law Review 71: 606–12.Google Scholar
Hart, H. L. A. 1977. ‘American Jurisprudence through English Eyes: The Nightmare and the Noble Dream’. Sibley Lecture Series. 33: 137–41. http://digitalcommons.law.uga.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1032&context=lectures_pre_arch_lectures_sibley.Google Scholar
Hart, H. L. A. 1982. ‘Legal Duty and Obligation’. In Hart, H. L. A.. Essays on Bentham. Oxford University Press: 147–53.Google Scholar
Hart, H. L. A. 1983. ‘Law in the Perspective of Philosophy’ in Hart, H.L.A.. Essays in Jurisprudence and Philosophy. Clarendon Press: 153–8.Google Scholar
Hart, H. L. A. 2012. The Concept of Law. 3rd ed. Introduction by Green, L., eds. Raz, J. and Bulloch, P.. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hart, H. M. and Sacks, A. M. 1994. The Legal Process: Basic Problems in the Making and Application of Law. Eds. Eskridge, W. N. and Frickey, P. P.. Foundation Press.Google Scholar
Leiter, B. 2009. ‘Explaining Theoretical Disagreement’. University of Chicago Law Review 76: 1215–50.Google Scholar
Liptak, A. 2013. ‘Ronald Dworkin, Scholar of the Law, Is Dead at 81: Dworkin Came to Oxford from the Yale Law School’. New York Times. www.nytimes.com/2013/02/15/us/ronald-dworkin-legal-philosopher-dies-at-81.html?pagewanted=all.Google Scholar
MacCormick, N. 2003. ‘Argumentation and Interpretation in Law’. Ratio Juris 16(4): 469–85.Google Scholar
Patterson, D. 1996. Law as Interpretation: The Jurisprudence of Ronald Dworkin. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Patterson, D. 2016. ‘Can We Please Stop Doing This? By the Way, Postema Was Right’. In Gizbert-Studnicki, T. (ed.). Metaphilosophy of Law. Hart Publishing: 4960.Google Scholar
Patterson, D. 2018. ‘Theoretical Disagreement, Legal Positivism and Interpretation’. Ratio Juris 31: 260–75.Google Scholar
Postema, G. J. 1987. ‘“Protestant” Interpretation and Social Practices’. Law and Philosophy 6: 283319.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Raz, J. 1983. ‘Postscript to Legal Principles and the Limits of Law’. In Cohen, M. (ed.). Ronald Dworkin and Contemporary Jurisprudence. Rowman & Allanheld: 84–5.Google Scholar
Raz, J. 1995. ‘The Relevance of Coherence’. In Raz, J.. Ethics in the Public Domain. Oxford University Press: 277325.Google Scholar
Raz, J. 2009. ‘Legal Positivism and the Sources of Law’. In Raz, J.. The Authority of Law. 2nd ed. Oxford University Press: 3752.Google Scholar
Schauer, F. 1985. ‘Easy Cases Interpretation Symposium: Philosophy of Language and Legal Interpretation’. Southern California Law Review 58: 399407.Google Scholar
Shapiro, S. J. 2007The “Hart-Dworkin” Debate: A Short Guide for the Perplexed’. Public Law and Legal Theory Working Paper 77(7). In Ripstein, A. (ed.). Ronald Dworkin. Cambridge University Press: 2255.Google Scholar
Stone, J. 1946. The Province and Function of Law. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Sugarman, D. 2005. ‘Hart Interviewed: H.L.A. Hart in Conversation with David Sugarman’. Journal of Law and Society 32(2): 267–93.Google Scholar
Ullian, J. S. and Quine, W. V. 1978. The Web of Belief. 2nd ed. McGraw-Hill Education.Google Scholar
Waismann, F. 1945/1951. ‘Verifiability’. In Flew, A. (ed.). Essays on Logic and Language I. Philosophical Library: 1130.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 2010. Philosophical Investigations. Trans. Anscombe, G. E. M., Hacker, P. M. S. and Schulte, J.. 4th ed. John Wiley & Sons.Google Scholar

References

Adler, M. 2009. ‘Social Facts, Constitutional Interpretation and the Rule of Recognition’. In ed. Adler, M. D. and Himma, K. E. (eds.). The Rule of Recognition and the U.S. Constitution. Oxford University Press: 193233.Google Scholar
Anscombe, E. 1958. ‘On Brute Facts’. Analysis 18(3): 6972.Google Scholar
Anscombe, E. 1963. Intention. 2nd ed. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Anscombe, E. 1981. ‘On the Source of Authority of the State’. Ethics, Religion and Politics: Collected Philosophical Papers of GEM Anscombe. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Aquinas, T. 2006. Summa Theologiae I-II. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Blackburn, S. 1998. Ruling Passions. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Chisholm, R. 1976. ‘Freedom and Action’. In Lehrer, K. (ed.). Freedom and Determinism. Random House: 1144.Google Scholar
Coleman, J, 2001. The Practice of Principles. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dancy, J. 2000. Practical Reality. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dickson, J. 2001. Evaluation and Legal Theory. Hart Publishing.Google Scholar
Davidson, D. 1963. ‘Actions, Reasons and Causes’. Journal of Philosophy 60(23): 685700.Google Scholar
Davidson, D. 1980. ‘Freedom to Act’. In Davidson, D.. Essays on Actions and Events. Clarendon Press: 6381.Google Scholar
Dworkin, R. 1986. Law’s Empire. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Endicott, T. 2001. ‘How to Speak the Truth’. American Journal of Jurisprudence 46: 229–48.Google Scholar
Finnis, J. 1987. ‘On Reason and Authority in Law’s Empire’. Law and Philosophy 6(3): 357–80.Google Scholar
Finnis, J. 1988. Moral Absolutes: Tradition, Revision, and Truth. Catholic University of America Press.Google Scholar
Finnis, J. 1998. Aquinas. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Finnis, J. 2003. ‘Law and What I Truly Should Decide’. American Journal of Jurisprudence 48: 107–29.Google Scholar
Finnis, J. 2011. Natural Law and Natural Rights. 2nd ed. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Gardner, J. 2001. ‘Legal Positivism: 5½ Myths’. American Journal of Jurisprudence 46: 199227.Google Scholar
Grisez, G. 1967. ‘The First Principles of Practical Reasons: A Commentary on the Summa Theologiae, 1–2, Question 94, Article 2’. Natural Law Forum 10: 168201.Google Scholar
Harman, G. 1986a. Change in View. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Harman, G. 1986b. ‘Willing and Intending’. In Grandy, R. and Warner, R. (eds.). Philosophical Grounds of Rationality. Oxford University Press: 363–80.Google Scholar
Hart, H. L. A. 1994. The Concept of Law. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Holton, R. 1998. ‘Positivism and the Internal Point of View’. Law and Philosophy 17: 597625.Google Scholar
Irwin, T. 1981. ‘Homonym in Aristotle’. The Review of Metaphysics 34(3): 523–44.Google Scholar
Kenny, A. 1979. Aristotle’s Theory of the Will. Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Moran, R. and Stone, M. 2009. ‘Anscombe on Expression of Intention’. In Sandis, C. (ed.). New Essays in the Explanation of Action. Palgrave MacMillan.Google Scholar
Murphy, M. 2006. Natural Law in Jurisprudence and Politics. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Patterson, D. 1999. ‘Explicating the Internal Point of View’. Southern Methodist University Law Review 52: 6774.Google Scholar
Perry, S. 1995. ‘Interpretation and Methodology in Legal Theory’. In Marmor, A. (ed.). Law and Interpretation. Clarendon Press: 97135.Google Scholar
Perry, S. 2000. ‘Holmes versus Hart: The Bad Man in Legal Theory’. In Burton, S. Jr. (ed.). The Path of Law and Its Influence: The Legacy of Oliver Wendell Holmes. Cambridge University Press: 158–96.Google Scholar
Perry, S. 2006. ‘Hart on Social Rules and the Foundations of Law: Liberating the Internal Point of View’. Fordham Law Review 75: 11711209.Google Scholar
Raz, J. 1999. Practical Reason and Norms. Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Rhonheimer, M. 2008. Perspective of the Acting Person: Essays in the Renewal of Thomistic Moral Philosophy. Catholic University of America Press.Google Scholar
Rodriguez-Blanco, V. 2007. ‘Is Finnis Wrong?’. Legal Theory 13: 257–83.Google Scholar
Rodriguez-Blanco, V. 2016a. Law and Authority under the Guise of the Good. Hart-Bloomsbury.Google Scholar
Rodriguez-Blanco, V. 2016b. ‘Action in Law’s Empire: Judging in the Deliberative Mode’. Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 29(2): 431–56.Google Scholar
Rodriguez-Blanco, V. and Zambrano, P. 2018. ‘One Myth of the Classical Law Theory: Reflecting on the “Thin” View of Legal Positivism’. Ratio Juris 31: 932.Google Scholar
Schauer, F. 1994. ‘Fuller’s Internal Point of View’. Law and Philosophy 13: 285312.Google Scholar
Shapiro, S. 2000. ‘The Bad Man and the Internal Point of View’. In Burton, S. Jr. (ed.). The Path of Law and Its Influence: The Legacy of Oliver Wendell Holmes. Cambridge University Press: 158–96.Google Scholar
Shapiro, S. 2006. ‘What Is the Internal Point of View?’. Fordham Law Review 75: 1157–70.Google Scholar
Smith, M. 1994. The Moral Problem. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Tollefsen, C. 2018. ‘Aquinas’s Four Orders, Normativity, and Human Nature’. Journal of Value Inquiry 52(3): 243–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vogler, C. 2001. ‘Anscombe on Practical Inference’. In Millgram, E. (ed.). Varieties of Practical Reasoning. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Vogler, C. 2007. ‘Modern Moral Philosophy Again: Isolating the Promulgation Problem’. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society: 347–62.Google Scholar
Wallace, R. J. 2014. ‘Practical Reason’. In Zalta, E. N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/practical-reason/.Google Scholar
Zambrano, P. 2015. ‘Fundamental Principles, Realist Semantics and Human Action’. Rechtstheorie: 323–45.Google Scholar
Zipursky, B. 2006. ‘Legal Obligations and the Internal Aspect of Rules’. Fordham Law Review 75: 1229–53.Google Scholar

References

Alexy, R. 2002a. The Argument from Injustice. Trans. Paulson, S. and Paulson, B.. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Alexy, R. 2002b. A Theory of Constitutional Rights. Trans. Rivers, J.. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Alexy, R. 2007. ‘An Answer to Joseph Raz’. In Pavlakos, G. (ed.). Law, Rights and Discourse. Hart: 3755.Google Scholar
Alexy, R. 2008. ‘On the Concept and the Nature of Law’. Ratio Juris 21: 281–99.Google Scholar
Alexy, R. 2010. ‘The Dual Nature of Law’. Ratio Juris 23: 167–82.Google Scholar
Alexy, R. 2012. ‘Law, Morality, and the Existence of Human Rights’. Ratio Juris 24: 214.Google Scholar
Alexy, R. 2013a. ‘Between Positivism and Non-positivism: A Third Reply to Bulygin’. In Ferrer Beltrán, J., Moreso, J. J. and Papayannis, D. M. (eds.). Neutrality and Theory of Law. Springer: 225–38.Google Scholar
Alexy, R. 2013b. ‘Some Reflections on the Ideal Dimension of Law and on the Legal Philosophy of John Finnis’. American Journal of Jurisprudence 58: 97110.Google Scholar
Alexy, R. 2015. ‘Legal Certainty and Correctness’. Ratio Juris 28: 441–51.Google Scholar
Allan, T. R. S. 2017. ‘In Defence of Radbruch’s Formula: Injustice, Interpretation, and Invalidity’. In Borowski, M., Paulson, S. and Sieckmann, J. (eds.). Rechtsphilosophie und Grundrechtstheorie. Mohr Siebeck: 87104.Google Scholar
Bix, B. 2006. ‘Robert Alexy’s Radbruch Formula and the Nature of Law’. Rechtstheorie 37: 139–49.Google Scholar
Bulygin, E. 2013. ‘Alexy between Positivism and Non-positivism’. In Ferrer Beltrán, J., Moreso, J. J. and Papayannis, D. M. (eds.). Neutrality and Theory of Law. Springer: 4959.Google Scholar
Dworkin, R. 1978. Taking Rights Seriously. 2nd ed. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Dworkin, R. 1986. Law’s Empire. Fontana Press.Google Scholar
Finnis, J. 1980. Natural Law and Natural Rights. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Finnis, J. 2014. ‘Law as Fact and as Reason for Action: A Response to Robert Alexy on Law’s Ideal Dimension’. American Journal of Jurisprudence 59: 85109.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
García Figueroa, A. 1998. Principios y positivismo jurídico. Centro de estudios políticos y constitucionales.Google Scholar
Gardner, J. 2012. ‘Legal Positivism: 5½ Myths’. In Gardner, J.. Law as a Leap of Faith. Oxford University Press: 1953.Google Scholar
Habermas, J. 1994. Faktizität und Geltung. 4th ed. Suhrkamp.Google Scholar
Hart, H. L. A. 1983. ‘Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals’. In Hart, H. L. A.. Essays in Jurisprudence and Philosophy. Clarendon Press: 4987.Google Scholar
Hart, H. L. A. 1994, The Concept of Law. 2nd ed. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Kelsen, H. 1960. Reine Rechtslehre. Deuticke.Google Scholar
MacCormick, N. 2007. ‘Why Law Makes No Claims’. In Pavlakos, G. (ed.). Law, Rights, and Discourse. Hart: 5967.Google Scholar
Marmor, A. 2001. Positive Law and Objective Values. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Paulson, S. 2012. ‘Justified Normativity’. In Klatt, M. (ed.). The Institutionalization of Reason. Oxford University Press: 61111.Google Scholar
Paulson, S. 2017. ‘The Makings of a Radical Norm Theory: Hans Kelsen’s Theory of the Sanction-Norm as Empowering Norm’. In Borowski, M., Paulson, S. and Sieckmann, J. (eds.). Rechtsphilosophie und Grundrechtstheorie. Mohr Siebeck: 589630.Google Scholar
Radbruch, G. 1946. ‘Gesetzliches Recht und übergesetzliches Unrecht’. Süddeutsche Juristenzeitung: 105–8.Google Scholar
Raz, J. 1999. Practical Reason and Norms. 3rd ed. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Raz, J. 2007. ‘The Argument from Injustice, or How Not to Reply to Legal Positivism’. In Pavlakos, G. (ed.). Law, Rights, and Discourse. Hart: 1735.Google Scholar
Sieckmann, J. 1990. Regelmodelle und Prinzipienmodelle des Rechtsystems. Nomos.Google Scholar
Sieckmann, J. 2012. The Logic of Autonomy. Hart.Google Scholar
Waldron, J. 1996. ‘Kant’s Legal Positivism’. Harvard Law Review 109: 1535–66.Google Scholar
Waldron, J. 2001. ‘Normative (or Ethical) Positivism’. In Coleman, J. (ed.). Hart’s Postscript: Essays on the Postscript to the Concept of Law. Oxford University Press: 410–33.Google Scholar

References

Bix, B. 2014. ‘When Law Becomes Morality: Comments on Mark Greenberg’s Moral Impact Theory of Law’. https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=2434075.Google Scholar
Coleman, J. 2001. The Practice of Principle. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dworkin, R. 1977. Taking Rights Seriously. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Fuller, L. 1969. The Morality of Law. Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Greenberg, M. 2004. ‘How Facts Make Law’. Legal Theory 10: 157–98.Google Scholar
Greenberg, M. 2006. ‘Hartian Positivism and Normative Facts: How Facts Make Law II’. In Hershovitz, S. (ed.). Exploring Law’s Empire. Oxford University Press: 265–90.Google Scholar
Greenberg, M. 2011. ‘The Standard Picture and Its Discontents’. In Green, L. and Leiter, B. (eds.). Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Law, vol. 1. Oxford University Press: 39106.Google Scholar
Greenberg, M. 2014. ‘The Moral Impact Theory of Law’. Yale Law Journal 123: 12881342.Google Scholar
Greenberg, M. 2017. ‘The Moral Impact Theory, the Dependence View, and Natural Law’. In Duke, G. and George, R. (eds.). Cambridge Companion to Natural Law Jurisprudence. Cambridge University Press: 275313.Google Scholar
Hart, H. L. A. 1994. The Concept of Law. 2nd ed. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hershovitz, S. 2015. ‘The End of Jurisprudence’. Yale Law Journal 124: 11601204.Google Scholar
Hohfeld, W. 1978. Fundamental Legal Conceptions. Ed. Corbin, A.. Greenwood Press.Google Scholar
Leiter, B. 2009. ‘Explaining Theoretical Disagreement’. University of Chicago Law Review 76: 1215–50.Google Scholar
Leiter, B. 2014. ‘Some Questions and Doubts about Greenberg’s “Moral Impact Theory of Law”’. https://leiterreports.typepad.com/brianleiterlaw/2014/05/some-questions-and-doubts-about-greenbergs-moral-impact-theory-of-law.html.Google Scholar
Levenbook, B. B. 2000. ‘The Meaning of a Precedent’. Legal Theory 6: 185240.Google Scholar
Levenbook, B. B. 2013. ‘How to Hold the Social Fact Thesis: A Reply to Greenberg and Toh’. In Green, L. and Leiter, B. (eds.). Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Law, vol. 2. Oxford University Press: 75102.Google Scholar
Levenbook, B. B. 2015. ‘Dworkin’s Theoretical Disagreement Argument’. Philosophy Compass 10: 19.Google Scholar
Lyons, D. 1973. ‘On Formal Justice’. Cornell Law Review 58: 833–61.Google Scholar
Nozick, R. 1974. Anarchy, State and Utopia. Basic Books.Google Scholar
Raz, J. 1979. ‘Legal Positivism and the Source of Law’. In Raz, J.. The Authority of Law. Oxford University Press: 3752.Google Scholar
Raz, J. 2009a. ‘On the Nature of Law’. In Raz, J.. Between Authority and Interpretation. Oxford University Press: 91125.Google Scholar
Raz, J. 2009b. ‘Intention in Interpretation’. In Raz, J.. Between Authority and Interpretation. Oxford University Press: 265–98.Google Scholar
Reynolds, A. 2016. ‘North Carolina Is No Longer Classified as a Democracy’. New Observer. www.newsobserver.com/opinion/op-ed/article122593759.html.Google Scholar
Reynolds, A. 2018. ‘North Carolina’s Democracy Was Bad at the Start of 2017. A Year Later It’s Much Worse’. New Observer. www.newsobserver.com/opinion/op-ed/article198165644.html.Google Scholar
Schauer, F. 1991. Playing by the Rules. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sellars, W. 1991. ‘Reply to Aune’. Wilfrid F. Sellars Papers. Archives of Scientific Philosophy, Archives and Special Collections, University of Pittsburgh Library System: 119.Google Scholar
Shapiro, S. 2007. ‘The “Hart-Dworkin” Debate: A Short Guide for the Perplexed’. In Ripstein, A. (ed.). Ronald Dworkin. Cambridge University Press: 2255.Google Scholar
Shapiro, S. 2011. Legality. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Simmons, A. J. 2001. Justification and Legitimacy: Essays on Rights and Obligations. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar

References

Alexy, R. 2002. The Argument from Injustice: A Reply to Legal Positivism. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Austin, J. 1885. Lectures on Jurisprudence or the Philosophy of Positive Law. The LawBook Exchange LTD.Google Scholar
Buckland, W. W. 1932. A Text-Book of Roman Law: From Augustus to Justinian. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Dworkin, R. 1981. Taking Rights Seriously. Duckworth.Google Scholar
Dworkin, R. 1986. Law’s Empire. Fontana.Google Scholar
Dyzenhaus, D. 2008. ‘The Case of the Grudge Informer Revisited’. New York University Law Review 83: 1000–34.Google Scholar
Dyzenhaus, D. 2010. Hard Cases in Wicked Legal Systems: Pathologies of Legality. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Fuller, L. L. 1940. The Law in Quest of Itself. Beacon Press.Google Scholar
Fuller, L. L. 1956. ‘Human Purpose and Natural Law’. Journal of Philosophy 53: 697705.Google Scholar
Fuller, L. L. 1958. ‘Positivism and Fidelity to Law: A Reply to Professor Hart’. Harvard Law Review 71: 630–72.Google Scholar
Gardner, J. 2012. Law as a Leap of Faith. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hart, H. L. A. 1982. Essays on Bentham: Jurisprudence and Political Theory. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Hart, H. L. A. 1983. ‘Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals’. In Hart, H. L. A.. Essays in Jurisprudence and Philosophy. Clarendon Press: 4987.Google Scholar
Hart, H. L. A. 1994. The Concept of Law. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Hobbes, T. 1997. Leviathan. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kelsen, H. 1968. Die philosophischen Grundlagen der Naturrechtslehre und des Rechtspositivismus. In Klecatsky, H., Marcic, R. and Schambeck, H. (eds.). Die Wiener rechtstheoretische Schule: Hans Kelsen, Adolf Merkl, Alfred Verdross. Europa Verlag.Google Scholar
Mertens, T. 2002. ‘Radbruch and Hart on Grudge Informer: A Reconsideration’. Ratio Juris 15: 186205.Google Scholar
Nino, C. 1996. Radical Evil on Trial. Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Pappe, H. O. 1960. ‘On the Validity of Judicial Decisions in the Nazi Era’. Modern Law Review 23: 260–74.Google Scholar
Radbruch, G. 1950. Legal Philosophy. In Patterson, E. W. (ed.). The Legal Philosophies of Lask, Radbruch, and Dabin. Harvard University Press: 43224.Google Scholar
Radbruch, R. 1973. ‘Gesetzliches Unrecht und Übergesetzliches Recht’. In Radbruch, G., Rechtsphilosophie. K.F. Koehler Verlag: 339–50.Google Scholar
Radbruch, G. 2006. ‘Statutory Lawlessness and Supra-Statutory Law’. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 26: 111.Google Scholar
Raz, J. 1983. The Authority of Law: Essays on Law and Morality. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Raz, J. 1994. ‘Authority, Law, and Morality’. In Raz, J., Ethics in the Public Domain: Essays in the Morality of Law and Politics. Oxford University Press: 194221.Google Scholar
Toh, K. 2005. ‘Hart’s Expressivism and His Benthamite Project’. Legal Theory 11(2): 75123.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Critique
  • Edited by Torben Spaak, Stockholms Universitet, Patricia Mindus, Uppsala Universitet, Sweden
  • Book: The Cambridge Companion to Legal Positivism
  • Online publication: 21 January 2021
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Critique
  • Edited by Torben Spaak, Stockholms Universitet, Patricia Mindus, Uppsala Universitet, Sweden
  • Book: The Cambridge Companion to Legal Positivism
  • Online publication: 21 January 2021
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Critique
  • Edited by Torben Spaak, Stockholms Universitet, Patricia Mindus, Uppsala Universitet, Sweden
  • Book: The Cambridge Companion to Legal Positivism
  • Online publication: 21 January 2021
Available formats
×