Published online by Cambridge University Press: 17 October 2023
Introduction
Major interpreters of David Ricardo assess his contribution to political economy in vastly different terms. Karl Marx praises Ricardo's ‘scientific impartiality and love of truth’ (Marx 1954, p. 412) and the ‘honesty which so essentially distinguishes him from the vulgar economists’ (Marx 1959, p. 555; original emphasis). William Stanley Jevons is one in a row of critics who contended that the doctrine of the classical authors and especially Ricardo ‘is radically fallacious; it involves the attempt to determine two unknown quantities from one equation’ (Jevons [1871] 1965, p. 258; see also 258–59): profits and the level of output, given the real wage rate. Léon Walras reiterates the criticism: ‘In the language of mathematics one equation cannot be used to determine two unknowns’ (Walras [1874–77] 1954, §368), while Joseph A. Schumpeter stokes it up: according to him Ricardo's ‘fundamental problem’ was that he ‘wanted to solve in terms of an equation between four variables: net output equals rent plus profits plus wages’ (Schumpeter 1954, p. 569). Schumpeter also accuses Ricardo of ‘piling a heavy load of practical conclusions upon a tenuous groundwork’ (1954, p. 1171). The ‘Ricardian vice’ is said to consist in drawing bold policy conclusions from oversimplified and arbitrarily closed models of the economy. Knut Wicksell instead defends Ricardo against this kind of criticism: ‘the way in which Ricardo develops his argument […] is a model of strictly logical reasoning about a subject which seems, at first glance, to admit of so little precision’. And: ‘Ricardo's theory of value is, one finds, developed with a high degree of consistency and strictness’ (Wicksell [1893] 1954, pp. 34 and 40). He adds
Since, according to Ricardo, wages represent a magnitude fixed from the beginning, and since – as he later shows – the level of rent is also determined by independent causes, the cause of capital profit is already settled. It is neither possible nor necessary to explain capital profit in other ways, if the other assumptions are sound. (ibid., pp. 36–37)
Interestingly, a few years earlier Alfred Marshall dubs Ricardo the head of the ‘brilliant school of deductive reasoning’ (Marshall 1890, p. 629), and explains: ‘His strong constructive originality is the mark of the highest genius in all nations. […] Ricardo's power of threading his way without slip through intricate paths to new and unexpected results has never been surpassed’ (ibid, p. 629, n. 1).
To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.
Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.
Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.
To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.
To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.