Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-gbm5v Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-22T21:57:19.940Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

TEMPORAL INTERPRETATION OF MONADIC INTUITIONISTIC QUANTIFIERS

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 December 2021

GURAM BEZHANISHVILI
Affiliation:
DEPARTMENT OF MATHEMATICAL SCIENCES NEW MEXICO STATE UNIVERSITY LAS CRUCES, NM 88003, USA E-mail: [email protected]
LUCA CARAI*
Affiliation:
DIPARTIMENTO DI MATEMATICA UNIVERSITÀ DEGLI STUDI DI SALERNO FISCIANO 84084, ITALY
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

We show that monadic intuitionistic quantifiers admit the following temporal interpretation: “always in the future” (for $\forall $ ) and “sometime in the past” (for $\exists $ ). It is well known that Prior’s intuitionistic modal logic ${\sf MIPC}$ axiomatizes the monadic fragment of the intuitionistic predicate logic, and that ${\sf MIPC}$ is translated fully and faithfully into the monadic fragment ${\sf MS4}$ of the predicate ${\sf S4}$ via the Gödel translation. To realize the temporal interpretation mentioned above, we introduce a new tense extension ${\sf TS4}$ of ${\sf S4}$ and provide a full and faithful translation of ${\sf MIPC}$ into ${\sf TS4}$ . We compare this new translation of ${\sf MIPC}$ with the Gödel translation by showing that both ${\sf TS4}$ and ${\sf MS4}$ can be translated fully and faithfully into a tense extension of ${\sf MS4}$ , which we denote by ${\sf MS4.t}$ . This is done by utilizing the relational semantics for these logics. As a result, we arrive at the diagram of full and faithful translations shown in Figure 1 which is commutative up to logical equivalence. We prove the finite model property (fmp) for ${\sf MS4.t}$ using algebraic semantics, and show that the fmp for the other logics involved can be derived as a consequence of the fullness and faithfulness of the translations considered.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2021. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Association for Symbolic Logic

1 Introduction

It is well known that, unlike classical quantifiers, the interpretation of intuitionistic quantifiers is non-symmetric in that $\forall x A$ is true at a world w iff A is true at every object a in the domain $D_v$ of every world $v$ accessible from $w$ , while $\exists x A$ is true at $w$ iff A is true at some object a in the domain $D_w$ of $w$ . This non-symmetry is also evident in the Gödel translation of the intuitionistic predicate calculus ${\sf IQC}$ into the predicate ${\sf S4}$ , denoted ${\sf QS4}$ , since $\forall xA$ is translated as $\Box \forall x A^t$ while $\exists x A$ as $\exists x A^t$ , where $A^t$ is the translation of A.

Fig. 1 Diagram of translations.

Our aim is to provide a more symmetric temporal interpretation of intuitionistic quantifiers as “always in the future” (for $\forall $ ) and “sometime in the past” (for $\exists $ ). In this paper we restrict our attention to monadic quantifiers (that quantify over one fixed variable), but in Section 7 we discuss the connection to the full predicate case, which is treated in detail in [Reference Bezhanishvili, Carai, Olivetti, Verbrugge, Negri and Sandu4]. One of the main reasons to treat the monadic case separately is because it gives rise to a new temporal system ${\sf TS4}$ (see below).

It is well known that the monadic fragment of ${\sf IQC}$ is axiomatized by Prior’s monadic intuitionistic propositional calculus ${\sf MIPC}$ [Reference Bull8, Reference Ono and Suzuki25]. The monadic fragment of ${\sf QS4}$ was studied by Fischer-Servi [Reference Fischer-Servi14] who showed that the Gödel translation of ${\sf IQC}$ into ${\sf QS4}$ restricts to the monadic case. We denote the monadic fragment of ${\sf QS4}$ by ${\sf MS4}$ . One of our main contributions is to introduce a tense counterpart of ${\sf MS4}$ , denoted by ${\sf TS4}$ , and prove that a modification of the Gödel translation embeds ${\sf MIPC}$ into ${\sf TS4}$ fully and faithfully. This allows us to give the desired temporal interpretation of monadic intuitionistic quantifiers as “always in the future” (for $\forall $ ) and “sometime in the past” (for $\exists $ ).

While ${\sf MS4}$ and ${\sf TS4}$ are not comparable, we introduce a common extension, which we denote by ${\sf MS4.t}$ . The system ${\sf MS4.t}$ can be thought of as a tense extension of ${\sf MS4}$ . We prove that there exist full and faithful translations of ${\sf MIPC}$ , ${\sf MS4}$ , and ${\sf TS4}$ into ${\sf MS4.t}$ , yielding the diagram in Figure 1. The Gödel translation is denoted by $(\:)^t$ , our new translation by $(\:)^\natural $ , and the three translations into ${\sf MS4.t}$ by $(\:)^\# $ , $(\:)^\flat$ , and $(\:)^\dagger $ , respectively.

We prove these results by employing relational semantics. In addition, we utilize algebraic semantics to prove that ${\sf MS4.t}$ has the fmp. It is then an easy consequence of the fullness and faithfulness of the translations considered that the other systems also have the fmp. That ${\sf MIPC}$ has the fmp was proved in [Reference Bull7], but the proof contained a gap, which was corrected in [Reference Fischer-Servi15, Reference Ono23]. The fmp for ${\sf MS4}$ follows from the results in [Reference Gabbay and Shehtman17, Sec. 12]. An advantage of our approach is in that it provides a uniform means for proving the fmp for all four systems in Figure 1.

In [Reference Bezhanishvili, Carai, Olivetti, Verbrugge, Negri and Sandu4] we extended the translation of ${\sf MIPC}$ into ${\sf MS4.t}$ to the predicate setting.Footnote 1 We showed that the same interpretation of intuitionistic quantifiers can be realized via a full and faithful translation of ${\sf IQC}$ into a version of predicate ${\sf S4.t}$ that can be thought of as a predicate analogue of ${\sf MS4.t}$ . We conclude this paper by comparing the translations investigated here with those studied in [Reference Bezhanishvili, Carai, Olivetti, Verbrugge, Negri and Sandu4].

2 Logics of interest

In this section we present our four main logics of interest (see Figure 1). We start by recalling the monadic intuitionistic propositional calculus ${\sf MIPC}$ . This system was introduced by Prior [Reference Prior26, p. 38] and it was shown by Bull [Reference Bull8] that ${\sf MIPC}$ axiomatizes the monadic fragment of the intuitionistic predicate calculus ${\sf IQC}$ .Footnote 2 For this reason we denote the modalities of ${\sf MIPC}$ by $\forall $ and $\exists $ . Let $\mathcal L$ be the propositional language and let $\mathcal L_{\forall \exists }$ be the extension of $\mathcal L$ with two modalities $\forall $ and $\exists $ .

Definition 2.1. The monadic intuitionistic propositional calculus ${\sf MIPC}$ is the intuitionistic modal logic in the propositional modal language $\mathcal L_{\forall \exists }$ containing

  1. 1. all theorems of the intuitionistic propositional calculus ${\sf IPC}$ ;

  2. 2. the ${\sf S4}$ -axioms for $\forall $ :

    1. (a) $\forall (p\land q)\leftrightarrow (\forall p\land \forall q)$ ,

    2. (b) $\forall p \rightarrow p$ ,

    3. (c) $\forall p \rightarrow \forall \forall p$ ;

  3. 3. the ${\sf S5}$ -axioms for $\exists $ :

    1. (a) $\exists (p\vee q)\leftrightarrow (\exists p\vee \exists q)$ ,

    2. (b) $p \rightarrow \exists p$ ,

    3. (c) $\exists \exists p \rightarrow \exists p$ ,

    4. (d) $(\exists p \land \exists q) \rightarrow \exists (\exists p \land q)$ ;

  4. 4. the axioms connecting $\forall $ and $\exists $ :

    1. (a) $\exists \forall p\leftrightarrow \forall p$ ,

    2. (b) $\exists p \leftrightarrow \forall \exists p$ ;

and closed under the rules of modus ponens, substitution, and necessitation $(\varphi / \forall \varphi )$ .

Remark 2.2. There are several equivalent axiomatizations of ${\sf MIPC}$ (see, e.g., [Reference Bezhanishvili2, Lemma 2]).

We next recall the monadic extension of ${\sf S4}$ studied by Fischer-Servi [Reference Fischer-Servi14] who showed that it axiomatizes the monadic fragment of the predicate ${\sf S4}$ . Let $\mathcal L_{\Box \forall }$ be the propositional bimodal language with two modal operators $\Box $ and $\forall $ . As usual, $\Diamond $ is an abbreviation for $\neg \Box \neg $ and $\exists $ is an abbreviation for $\neg \forall \neg $ .

Definition 2.3. The monadic $\sf S4$ , denoted ${\sf MS4}$ , is the smallest bimodal logic containing all theorems of the classical propositional calculus ${\sf CPC}$ , the $\sf S4$ -axioms for $\Box $ , the $\sf S5$ -axioms for $\forall $ , the left commutativity axiom

$$ \begin{align*} \Box \forall p \to \forall \Box p, \end{align*} $$

and closed under modus ponens, substitution, $\Box $ -necessitation, and $\forall $ -necessitation.

Remark 2.4. Recalling the definition of fusion of two logics (see [Reference Gabbay, Kurucz, Wolter and Zakharyaschev16]), ${\sf MS4}$ is obtained from the fusion ${\sf S4}\otimes {\sf S5}$ by adding the left commutativity axiom $\Box \forall p \rightarrow \forall \Box p$ which is the monadic version of the converse Barcan formula. The monadic version of the Barcan formula is the right commutativity axiom $\forall \Box p \rightarrow \Box \forall p$ . Adding it to ${\sf MS4}$ yields the product logic $\sf S4 \times \sf S5$ ; see [Reference Gabbay, Kurucz, Wolter and Zakharyaschev16, Chap. 5] for details.

The following lemma will be useful in Section 3.

Lemma 2.5. An equivalent axiomatization of ${\sf MS4}$ is obtained by replacing the left commutativity axiom $\Box \forall p \to \forall \Box p$ by $\exists \Box p \to \Box \exists p$ .

Proof. We show that ${\sf MS4}\vdash \exists \Box p \to \Box \exists p$ . That $\exists \Box p \to \Box \exists p$ together with the other axioms of ${\sf MS4}$ implies $\Box \forall p \to \forall \Box p$ is proved similarly. Since $\forall $ is an ${\sf S5}$ -modality, $\Box \exists p \to \Box \forall \exists p$ is a theorem of ${\sf MS4}$ . By the left commutativity axiom, $\Box \forall \exists p \to \forall \Box \exists p$ is also a theorem of ${\sf MS4}$ . So ${\sf MS4}\vdash \Box \exists p \to \forall \Box \exists p$ , and hence ${\sf MS4}\vdash \exists \Box \exists p \to \exists \forall \Box \exists p$ . But $\exists \Box p \to \exists \Box \exists p$ , $\exists \forall \Box \exists p \to \forall \Box \exists p$ , and $\forall \Box \exists p \to \Box \exists p$ are all theorems of ${\sf MS4}$ because $\forall $ is an ${\sf S5}$ -modality. Thus, ${\sf MS4}\vdash \exists \Box p \to \Box \exists p$ , concluding the proof.

To introduce our main tense logic ${\sf TS4}$ , we first need to recall the tense logic ${\sf S4.t}$ . Let $\mathcal L_T$ be the propositional tense language with two modalities ${[F]}$ and ${[P]}$ . As usual, ${[F]}$ is interpreted as “always in the future” and ${[P]}$ as “always in the past.” We use the following standard abbreviations: ${\langle F \rangle }$ for $\neg {[F]} \neg $ and ${\langle P \rangle }$ for $\neg {[P]} \neg $ . Then ${\langle F \rangle }$ is interpreted as “sometime in the future” and ${\langle P \rangle }$ as “sometime in the past.”

Definition 2.6. Let ${\sf S4.t}$ be the smallest bimodal logic containing all theorems of the classical propositional calculus ${\sf CPC}$ , the ${\sf S4}$ -axioms for ${[F]}$ and ${[P]}$ , the tense axioms

$$ \begin{align*} \begin{array}{c} p \to {[P]} {\langle F \rangle} p, \\ p \to {[F]} {\langle P \rangle} p, \end{array} \end{align*} $$

and closed under modus ponens, substitution, ${[F]}$ -necessitation, and ${[P]}$ -necessitation.

Remark 2.7. The system ${\sf S4.t}$ is the extension of the least tense logic $\sf K.t$ in which both tense modalities satisfy the ${\sf S4}$ -axioms. It was studied by several authors. Esakia [Reference Esakia10] showed that the Gödel translation can be extended to embed the Heyting–Brouwer logic $\sf HB$ of Rauszer [Reference Rauszer28] into ${\sf S4.t}$ fully and faithfully. The language of $\sf HB$ is obtained by enriching the language of $\sf IPC$ by an additional connective of coimplication, and the logic $\sf HB$ is the extension of $\sf IPC$ by the axioms for coimplication, which are dual to the axioms for implication. Wolter [Reference Wolter31] extended the celebrated Blok–Esakia theorem to this setting.

We are ready to define ${\sf TS4}$ by combining ${\sf S4}$ and ${\sf S4.t}$ . In Section 4 we will translate ${\sf MIPC}$ into ${\sf TS4}$ fully and faithfully. We will use ${\sf S4}$ to translate intuitionistic connectives and ${\sf S4.t}$ to translate monadic intuitionistic quantifiers. Let $\mathcal {ML}$ be the multimodal propositional language with three modalities $\Box $ , ${[F]}$ , and ${[P]}$ . We use $\Diamond $ , ${\langle F \rangle }$ , and ${\langle P \rangle }$ as usual abbreviations.

Definition 2.8. The logic ${\sf TS4}$ is the least multimodal logic containing all theorems of the classical propositional calculus ${\sf CPC}$ , the ${\sf S4}$ -axioms for $\Box $ , ${[F]}$ , and ${[P]}$ , the tense axioms for ${[F]}$ and ${[P]}$ , the connecting axioms

$$ \begin{align*} \begin{array}{l} \Diamond p \to {\langle F \rangle} p, \\ {\langle F \rangle} p \to \Diamond( {\langle F \rangle} p \land {\langle P \rangle} p), \end{array} \end{align*} $$

and closed under modus ponens, substitution, and three necessitation rules (for $\Box $ , ${[F]}$ , and ${[P]}$ ).

Our final logic of interest is the monadic tense logic ${\sf MS4.t}$ which is obtained by combining ${\sf MS4}$ and ${\sf S4.t}$ . As we will see, both ${\sf MS4}$ and ${\sf TS4}$ translate fully and faithfully into ${\sf MS4.t}$ . In order to avoid confusion between the tense modalities of ${\sf TS4}$ and ${\sf MS4.t}$ , we denote the tense modalities of ${\sf MS4.t}$ by $\Box _F$ and $\Box _P$ . Let $\mathcal L_{T\forall }$ be the propositional language with the tense modalities $\Box _F$ and $\Box _P$ , and the monadic modality $\forall $ .

Definition 2.9. The tense ${\sf MS4}$ , denoted ${\sf MS4.t}$ , is the least multimodal logic containing all theorems of the classical propositional calculus ${\sf CPC}$ , the ${\sf S4.t}$ -axioms for $\Box _F$ and $\Box _P$ , the ${\sf S5}$ -axioms for $\forall $ , the left commutativity axiom

$$ \begin{align*} \Box_F \forall p \to \forall \Box_F p, \end{align*} $$

and closed under modus ponens, substitution, and the necessitation rules (for $\Box _F$ , $\Box _P$ , and $\forall $ ).

Remark 2.10. We can think of ${\sf MS4.t}$ as a tense extension of ${\sf MS4}$ . It is worth stressing that ${\sf MS4.t}$ is not the monadic fragment of the standard predicate extension ${\sf QS4.t}$ of ${\sf S4.t}$ . To see this, it is well known that the Barcan formula $\forall x \Box _F \varphi \to \Box _F \forall x \varphi $ and the converse Barcan formula $\Box _F \forall x \varphi \to \forall x \Box _F \varphi $ are both theorems of any tense predicate logic containing the standard axioms of first-order logic. Therefore, both are theorems of ${\sf QS4.t}$ . Thus, the monadic fragment of ${\sf QS4.t}$ contains both the left commutativity axiom $\Box _F \forall p \to \forall \Box _F p$ and the right commutativity axiom $\forall \Box _F p \to \Box _F \forall p$ . On the other hand, it is easy to see (e.g., using the Kripke semantics for ${\sf MS4.t}$ which we will define in the next section) that, while ${\sf MS4.t}$ contains the left commutativity axiom, the right commutativity axiom is not provable in ${\sf MS4.t}$ .

3 Relational semantics

In this section we investigate the relational semantics for ${\sf MIPC}$ , ${\sf MS4}$ , ${\sf TS4}$ , and ${\sf MS4.t}$ . The relational semantics for ${\sf MIPC}$ and ${\sf MS4}$ have already been studied in the literature, and the relational semantics for ${\sf TS4}$ and ${\sf MS4.t}$ are obtained by a straightforward adaptation.

Definition 3.1. Let R be a quasi-order (reflexive and transitive relation) on a set X. As usual, for $x\in X$ , we write

$$ \begin{align*} R[x]=\{y\in X\mid xRy\} \mbox{ and } R^{-1}[x]=\{y\in X\mid yRx\}, \end{align*} $$

and for $A\subseteq X$ , we write

$$ \begin{align*} R[A]=\bigcup\{R[x]\mid x\in A\} \mbox{ and } R^{-1}[A]=\bigcup\{R^{-1}[x]\mid x\in A\}. \end{align*} $$

We say that $A \subseteq X$ is an R-upset if $R[A]=A$ and that it is an R-downset if $R^{-1}[A]=A$ .

We first describe the relational semantics for ${\sf MIPC}$ . There are several such (see, e.g., [Reference Bezhanishvili3]), but we concentrate on the one introduced by Ono [Reference Ono23].

Definition 3.2. An ${\sf MIPC}$ -frame is a triple $\mathfrak F=(X,R,Q)$ where X is a set, R is a partial order, Q is a quasi-order, and the following two conditions are satisfied:

  1. (O1) $R \subseteq Q$ ,

  2. (O2) $x Q y \Rightarrow (\exists z)(x R z \; \& \; z E_Q y)$ (see Figure 2).

Here $E_Q$ is the equivalence relation defined by $x E_Q y$ iff $x Q y$ and $y Q x$ .

Remark 3.3. If U is an R-upset of an ${\sf MIPC}$ -frame $\mathfrak {F}$ , then Condition (O2) implies that $E_Q[U]=Q[U]$ . This motivates our interpretation of $\exists $ as “sometime in the past.” Indeed, taking $Q[U]$ is the standard way to associate an operator on $\wp (X)$ to the tense modality “sometime in the past” (see, e.g., [Reference Thomason30, p. 151]).

Fig. 2 Condition (O2).

Definition 3.4. A valuation on an ${\sf MIPC}$ -frame $\mathfrak F=(X,R,Q)$ is a map $v$ associating an R-upset of $\mathfrak F$ to any propositional letter of $\mathcal L_{\forall \exists }$ . The connectives $\wedge ,\vee ,\to ,\neg $ are then interpreted as in intuitionistic Kripke frames, and $\forall ,\exists $ are interpreted as

$$ \begin{align*} \begin{array}{l c l} x \vDash_v \forall \varphi & \text{ iff } & (\forall y \in X)(x Q y \Rightarrow y \vDash_v \varphi ), \\ x \vDash_v \exists \varphi & \text{ iff } & (\exists y \in X)(x E_Q y \;\& \; y \vDash_v \varphi ). \end{array} \end{align*} $$

As usual, we say that $\varphi $ is valid in $\mathfrak F$ , and write $\mathfrak F \vDash \varphi $ , if $x \vDash _v \varphi $ for every valuation $v$ and every $x \in X$ .

It is well known that ${\sf MIPC}$ is a canonical logic (see, e.g., [Reference Bezhanishvili3, Sec. 6]). Thus, we have:

Theorem 3.5. ${\sf MIPC}$ is a canonical logic, and hence it is sound and complete with respect to its relational semantics. Therefore,

$$ \begin{align*} {\sf MIPC} \vdash \varphi \ \mbox{ iff } \ \mathfrak F \vDash \varphi \mbox{ for every}\ {\sf MIPC}\mbox{-frame } \mathfrak F. \end{align*} $$

Remark 3.6. In addition, ${\sf MIPC}$ has the fmp [Reference Bull7, Reference Fischer-Servi15, Reference Ono23] and hence is decidable. As we will see in Section 6, the fmp of ${\sf MIPC}$ can be derived from the fmp of ${\sf MS4.t}$ .

The relational semantics for ${\sf MS4}$ was introduced by Esakia [Reference Esakia12].

Definition 3.7. An ${\sf MS4}$ -frame is a triple $\mathfrak F=(X,R,E)$ where X is a set, R is a quasi-order, E is an equivalence relation, and the following commutativity condition is satisfied (see Figure 3 ):

(E) $$ \begin{align} (\forall x,y,z \in X)(x E y \; \& \; y R z) \Rightarrow (\exists u \in X)(x R u \; \& \; u E z). \end{align} $$

Fig. 3 Condition (E).

Definition 3.8. A valuation on an ${\sf MS4}$ -frame $\mathfrak F=(X,R,E)$ is a map $v$ associating a subset of X to each propositional letter of $\mathcal L_{\Box \forall }$ . The Boolean connectives are interpreted as usual, and

$$ \begin{align*} \begin{array}{l c l} x \vDash_v \Box \varphi & \text{ iff } & (\forall y \in X) (x R y \, \Rightarrow \, y \vDash_v \varphi ), \\ x \vDash_v \forall \varphi & \text{ iff } & (\forall y \in X) (x E y \, \Rightarrow \, y \vDash_v \varphi ). \end{array} \end{align*} $$

By Lemma 2.5, in the axiomatization of ${\sf MS4}$ , the left commutativity axiom $\Box \forall p \to \forall \Box p$ can be replaced by $\exists \Box p \to \Box \exists p$ . Therefore, ${\sf MS4}$ can be axiomatized by Sahlqvist formulas (see, e.g., [Reference Blackburn, de Rijke and Venema5, Sec. 3.6]). Thus, by the Sahlqvist completeness theorem (see, e.g., [Reference Blackburn, de Rijke and Venema5, Theorem 4.42]), it is sound and complete with respect to its relational semantics:

Theorem 3.9. ${\sf MS4}$ is a Sahlqvist logic, and hence it is sound and complete with respect to its relational semantics. Therefore,

$$ \begin{align*} {\sf MS4} \vdash \varphi \ \mbox{ iff } \ \mathfrak F \vDash \varphi \mbox{ for every}\ {\sf MS4}\mbox{-frame}\ \mathfrak F. \end{align*} $$

Remark 3.10. In addition, ${\sf MS4}$ has the fmp and is decidable. This can be derived from the results in [Reference Gabbay and Shehtman17, Sec. 12] (see also [Reference Gabbay, Kurucz, Wolter and Zakharyaschev16, Theorems 6.52 and 9.12]). As we will see in Section 6, the fmp of ${\sf MS4}$ can also be derived from the fmp of ${\sf MS4.t}$ .

We next recall the relational semantics for ${\sf S4.t}$ .

Definition 3.11. An ${\sf S4.t}$ -frame is a pair $\mathfrak {F}=(X,Q)$ where X is a set and Q is a quasi-order on X.

Remark 3.12. While ${\sf S4.t}$ -frames coincide with ${\sf S4}$ -frames, the difference is in the interpretation of the modalities as we use Q to interpret ${[F]}$ and its inverse relation to interpret ${[P]}$ .

Definition 3.13. A valuation on an ${\sf S4.t}$ -frame $\mathfrak F=(X,Q)$ is a map $v$ associating a subset of X to each propositional letter of $\mathcal L_T$ . The Boolean connectives are interpreted as usual, and the tense modalities are interpreted as

$$ \begin{align*} \begin{array}{l c l} x \vDash_v {[F]} \varphi & \text{ iff } & (\forall y \in X) (x Q y \, \Rightarrow \, y \vDash_v \varphi ), \\ x \vDash_v {[P]} \varphi & \text{ iff } & (\forall y \in X) (y Q x \, \Rightarrow \, y \vDash_v \varphi ). \end{array} \end{align*} $$

Remark 3.14. It is straightforward to see that all the axioms of ${\sf S4.t}$ are Sahlqvist formulas. Therefore, ${\sf S4.t}$ is a Sahlqvist logic, and hence it is sound and complete with respect to its relational semantics. That ${\sf S4.t}$ has the fmp follows from [Reference Segerberg29, pp. 313–314] (see also [Reference Goldblatt18, p. 44] and Remark 6.18(3)).

We now introduce the relational semantics for ${\sf TS4}$ .

Definition 3.15. A ${\sf TS4}$ -frame is a triple $\mathfrak F=(X,R,Q)$ where X is a set and $R,Q$ are quasi-orders on X satisfying Conditions (O1) and (O2).

It follows that ${\sf TS4}$ -frames are a version of ${\sf MIPC}$ -frames, where the relation R is a quasi-order. We interpret $\Box $ using R, and ${[F]}$ , ${[P]}$ using Q and its inverse .

Definition 3.16. A valuation on a ${\sf TS4}$ -frame $\mathfrak F=(X,R,Q)$ is a map $v$ associating a subset of X to each propositional letter of $\mathcal {ML}$ . The Boolean connectives are interpreted as usual, and the modalities $\Box $ , ${[F]}$ , and ${[P]}$ are interpreted as

$$ \begin{align*} \begin{array}{l c l} x \vDash_v \Box \varphi & \text{ iff } & (\forall y \in X) (x R y \Rightarrow y \vDash_v \varphi ), \\ x \vDash_v {[F]} \varphi & \text{ iff } & (\forall y \in X) (x Q y \Rightarrow y \vDash_v \varphi ), \\ x \vDash_v {[P]} \varphi & \text{ iff } & (\forall y \in X) (y Q x \Rightarrow y \vDash_v \varphi ). \end{array} \end{align*} $$

Consequently,

$$ \begin{align*} \begin{array}{l c l} x \vDash_v \Diamond \varphi & \text{ iff } & (\exists y \in X) (x R y \; \& \; y \vDash_v \varphi ),\\ x \vDash_v {\langle F \rangle} \varphi & \text{ iff } & (\exists y \in X) (x Q y \; \& \; y \vDash_v \varphi ),\\ x \vDash_v {\langle P \rangle} \varphi & \text{ iff } & (\exists y \in X) (y Q x \; \& \; y \vDash_v \varphi ). \end{array} \end{align*} $$

Remark 3.17. It is straightforward to check that if $(X,R,Q)$ is a ${\sf TS4}$ -frame, then $(X,R,E_Q)$ is an ${\sf MS4}$ -frame, and that if $(X,R,E)$ is an ${\sf MS4}$ -frame, then $(X,R,Q_E)$ is a ${\sf TS4}$ -frame, where $Q_E$ is defined by

$$ \begin{align*} x Q_E y \mbox{ iff } (\exists z \in X )(xRz \ \& \ zEy). \end{align*} $$

If $(X,R,Q)$ is a ${\sf TS4}$ -frame, by definition we have that

$$ \begin{align*} x Q y \mbox{ iff } (\exists z \in X) (x R z \ \& \ z E_Q y). \end{align*} $$

Thus, $Q=Q_{E_Q}$ . On the other hand, there exist ${\sf MS4}$ -frames $(X,R,E)$ such that $E\ne E_{Q_E}$ (see [Reference Bezhanishvili3, p. 24]). Therefore, this correspondence is not a bijection.

Since all ${\sf TS4}$ -axioms are Sahlqvist formulas, we have:

Theorem 3.18. ${\sf TS4}$ is a Sahlqvist logic, and hence it is sound and complete with respect to its relational semantics. Therefore,

$$ \begin{align*} {\sf TS4} \vdash \varphi \ \mbox{ iff } \ \mathfrak F \vDash \varphi \mbox{ for every}\ {\sf TS4}\mbox{-frame}\ \mathfrak F. \end{align*} $$

Remark 3.19. In Section 6 we will see that ${\sf TS4}$ has the fmp and hence is decidable.

Finally, we introduce the relational semantics for ${\sf MS4.t}$ . As with $\sf S4$ and $\sf S4.t$ , we have that ${\sf MS4.t}$ -frames are simply ${\sf MS4}$ -frames, the difference is in interpreting tense modalities.

Definition 3.20. A valuation on an ${\sf MS4.t}$ -frame $\mathfrak F=(X,R,E)$ is a map $v$ associating a subset of X to each propositional letter of $\mathcal L_{T\forall }$ . The Boolean connectives are interpreted as usual, and

$$ \begin{align*} \begin{array}{l c l} \mathfrak{F}, x \vDash_v \Box_F \varphi & \text{ iff } & (\forall y \in X) (x R y \Rightarrow y \vDash_v \varphi ), \\ \mathfrak{F}, x \vDash_v \Box_P \varphi & \text{ iff } & (\forall y \in X) (y R x \Rightarrow y \vDash_v \varphi ), \\ \mathfrak{F}, x \vDash_v \forall \varphi & \text{ iff } & (\forall y \in X) (x E y \Rightarrow y \vDash_v \varphi). \end{array} \end{align*} $$

Since both ${\sf MS4}$ and ${\sf S4.t}$ are Sahlqvist logics, so is ${\sf MS4.t}$ . Thus, we have:

Theorem 3.21. ${\sf MS4.t}$ is a Sahlqvist logic, and hence it is sound and complete with respect to its relational semantics. Therefore,

$$ \begin{align*} {\sf MS4.t} \vdash \varphi \ \mbox{ iff } \ \mathfrak F \vDash \varphi \mbox{ for every}\ {\sf MS4.t}\mbox{-frame}\ \mathfrak F. \end{align*} $$

In Section 6 we will prove that ${\sf MS4.t}$ has the fmp and hence is decidable.

4 The four translations

In this section we define the translations of Figure 1 and show that they are full and faithful by using relational semantics. We start by recalling that the Gödel translation of ${\sf MIPC}$ into ${\sf MS4}$ is defined by

$$ \begin{align*} \bot^t &= \bot,\\ p^t &= \Box p \quad \mbox{for each propositional letter } p, \\ (\varphi \land \psi)^t &= \varphi^t \land \psi^t, \\ (\varphi \lor \psi)^t &= \varphi^t \lor \psi^t, \\ (\varphi \to \psi)^t &= \Box (\neg \varphi^t \lor \psi^t), \\ (\forall \varphi)^t &= \Box \forall \varphi^t, \\ (\exists \varphi)^t &= \exists \varphi^t. \end{align*} $$

Definition 4.1. The translation $(-)^\natural : {\sf MIPC} \to {\sf TS4}$ is defined as $(-)^t$ on propositional letters, $\bot $ , $\wedge $ , $\vee $ , and $\to $ ; and for $\forall $ and $\exists $ we set:

$$ \begin{align*} (\forall \varphi)^\natural &= {[F]} \varphi^\natural,\\ (\exists \varphi)^\natural &= {\langle P \rangle} \varphi^\natural. \end{align*} $$

Remark 4.2. Thus, $(-)^\natural $ realizes the desired temporal interpretation of the intuitionistic monadic quantifiers: $\forall $ as “always in the future” and $\exists $ as “sometime in the past.”

Definition 4.3. The translation $(-)^\dagger : {\sf TS4} \to {\sf MS4.t}$ is defined by

$$ \begin{align*} p^\dagger &=p \quad \mbox{ for each propositional letter}\ p,\\ (\varphi \circ \psi)^\dagger &= \varphi^\dagger \circ \psi^\dagger \quad \mbox{for } \circ= \wedge, \vee,\\ (\neg \varphi)^\dagger & =\neg \varphi^\dagger,\\ (\Box \varphi)^\dagger &=\Box_F \varphi^\dagger,\\ ({[F]} \varphi)^\dagger &=\Box_F \forall \varphi^\dagger,\\ ({[P]} \varphi)^\dagger &=\forall \Box_P \varphi^\dagger. \end{align*} $$

Remark 4.4.

  1. 1. The translation $(-)^\dagger : {\sf TS4} \to {\sf MS4.t}$ is suggested by the correspondence between ${\sf TS4}$ -frames and ${\sf MS4}$ -frames described in Remark 3.17. Each ${\sf MS4.t}$ -frame $\mathfrak {F}=(X,R,E)$ is an ${\sf MS4}$ -frame, the relation $Q_E$ on the corresponding ${\sf TS4}$ -frame is the composition of R and E, and the inverse relation is the composition of E and . Therefore, the modalities ${[F]}$ and ${[P]}$ are translated as $\Box _F \forall $ and $\forall \Box _P$ , respectively. Notice that, since ${\sf MS4}$ lacks a modality corresponding to the relation , we are not able to translate ${\sf TS4}$ into ${\sf MS4}$ .

  2. 2. It is natural to consider a modification of $(-)^\dagger :{\sf TS4} \to {\sf MS4.t}$ where ${[P]}$ is translated as $\Box _P \forall $ . However, such a modification does not result in a faithful translation. Nevertheless, as we will see in Section 5, its composition with $(-)^\natural :{\sf MIPC} \to {\sf TS4}$ is full and faithful.

The translation of ${\sf MS4}$ into ${\sf MS4.t}$ reflects that ${\sf MS4.t}$ is a tense extension of ${\sf MS4}$ .

Definition 4.5. The translation $(-)^\# : {\sf MS4} \to {\sf MS4.t}$ replaces in each formula $\varphi $ of $\mathcal {L}_{\Box \forall }$ every occurrence of $\Box $ with $\Box _F$ .

We show that these four translations are full and faithful by using relational semantics. For this we first need to generalize the well-known notion of the skeleton of an ${\sf S4}$ -frame (see, e.g., [Reference Chagrov and Zakharyaschev9, Sec. 3.9]).

Definition 4.6.

  1. 1. If R is a quasi-order on a set X, we define $\sim $ to be the equivalence relation on X given by

    $$ \begin{align*} x \sim y \mbox{ iff } xRy \mbox{ and } yRx. \end{align*} $$
    We let $X'$ be the set of equivalence classes of $\sim $ , and define $R'$ on $X'$ by
    $$ \begin{align*} [x] R' [y] \mbox{ iff } xRy. \end{align*} $$
  2. 2. Let $\mathfrak F=(X,R,E)$ be an ${\sf MS4}$ -frame. Recall that $Q_E$ is defined on X by $x Q_E y$ iff $(\exists z \in X )(xRz \ \& \ zEy)$ (see Remark 3.17). Define $Q'$ on $X'$ by

    $$ \begin{align*} [x] Q' [y] \mbox{ iff } xQ_Ey. \end{align*} $$
    We call $\mathfrak {F}^t=(X',R',Q')$ the skeleton of the ${\sf MS4}$ -frame $\mathfrak {F}$ .
  3. 3. Let $\mathfrak F=(X,R,Q)$ be a ${\sf TS4}$ -frame. Define $Q'$ on $X'$ by

    $$ \begin{align*} [x] Q' [y] \mbox{ iff } xQy. \end{align*} $$
    We call $\mathfrak {F}^\natural =(X',R',Q')$ the skeleton of the ${\sf TS4}$ -frame $\mathfrak {F}$ .
  4. 4. For an ${\sf MS4.t}$ -frame $\mathfrak F=(X,R,E)$ let $\mathfrak {F}^\dagger = (X,R,Q_E)$ where $Q_E$ is defined as in (2).

Remark 4.7. If a ${\sf TS4}$ -frame $\mathfrak {F}=(X,R,Q)$ is such that R is a partial order, then $\mathfrak {F}$ is isomorphic to its skeleton $\mathfrak {F}^\natural $ . However, we cannot always recover an ${\sf MS4}$ -frame $\mathfrak {F}=(X,R,E)$ from its skeleton $\mathfrak {F}^t$ even if R is a partial order. Indeed, it is not always the case that $E=E_{Q_E}$ . Nonetheless, if $\mathfrak {F}$ is canonical (and in particular finite) and R is a partial order, then $E=E_{Q_E}$ ; see [Reference Bezhanishvili3, Sec. 2] for details.

Proposition 4.8.

  1. 1. If $\mathfrak F$ is an ${\sf MS4}$ -frame, then $\mathfrak {F}^t$ is an ${\sf MIPC}$ -frame.

  2. 2. If $\mathfrak F$ is a ${\sf TS4}$ -frame, then $\mathfrak {F}^\natural $ is an ${\sf MIPC}$ -frame.

  3. 3. If $\mathfrak F$ is an ${\sf MS4.t}$ -frame, then $\mathfrak {F}^\dagger $ is a ${\sf TS4}$ -frame.

Proof. (1). It is well known that $(X',R')$ is an intuitionistic Kripke frame. That $Q'$ is well defined follows from Condition (E). Showing that $Q'$ is a quasi-order and that (O1), (O2) hold in $\mathfrak {F}^t$ is straightforward.

(2). We have that $Q'$ is well defined on $X'$ because $R \subseteq Q$ in $\mathfrak {F}$ . Showing that $Q'$ is a quasi-order and that (O1), (O2) hold in $\mathfrak {F}^\natural $ is straightforward.

(3). Since ${\sf MS4.t}$ -frames coincide with ${\sf MS4}$ -frames, it follows from Remark 3.17 that $\mathfrak {F}^\dagger $ is a ${\sf TS4}$ -frame.

It is well known that an ${\sf S4}$ -frame validates the Gödel translation of an intuitionistic formula $\varphi $ iff its skeleton validates $\varphi $ (see, e.g., [Reference Chagrov and Zakharyaschev9, Corollary 3.82]). We will prove in Proposition 4.11 that analogous results hold for the four translations defined in this section. For this we need the following technical lemma.

Lemma 4.9. For any formula $\chi $ of $\mathcal L_{\forall \exists }$ , we have

$$ \begin{align*} {\sf MS4} \vdash \chi^t \to \Box \chi^t. \end{align*} $$

Consequently, if $\mathfrak {F}=(X,R,E)$ is an ${\sf MS4}$ -frame and $v$ a valuation on $\mathfrak {F}$ , then the set of points $x\in X$ such that $\mathfrak {F}, x \vDash _v \chi ^t$ forms an R-upset of $\mathfrak {F}$ .

Proof. We prove that ${\sf MS4} \vdash \chi ^t \to \Box \chi ^t$ by induction on the complexity of $\chi $ . This is obvious when $\chi =\bot $ . The cases when $\chi $ is p, $\varphi \to \psi $ , or $\forall \varphi $ follow from the axiom $\Box \varphi \to \Box \Box \varphi $ . We next consider the cases when $\chi $ is $\varphi \wedge \psi $ or $\varphi \vee \psi $ . Suppose that the claim is true for $\varphi $ and $\psi $ , so $\varphi ^t \to \Box \varphi ^t$ and $\psi ^t \to \Box \psi ^t$ are theorems of ${\sf MS4}$ . Then $\varphi ^t \wedge \psi ^t \to \Box (\varphi ^t \wedge \psi ^t)$ and $\varphi ^t \vee \psi ^t \to \Box (\varphi ^t \vee \psi ^t)$ are also theorems of ${\sf MS4}$ . Finally, if $\chi $ is $\exists \varphi $ and ${\sf MS4} \vdash \varphi ^t\to \Box \varphi ^t$ , then ${\sf MS4} \vdash \exists \varphi ^t \to \exists \Box \varphi ^t$ . Therefore, since ${\sf MS4} \vdash \exists \Box \varphi ^t \to \Box \exists \varphi ^t$ by Lemma 2.5, we conclude that ${\sf MS4} \vdash \exists \varphi ^t \to \Box \exists \varphi ^t$ .

Let $\mathfrak {F}=(X,R,E)$ be an ${\sf MS4}$ -frame, $v$ a valuation of $\mathfrak {F}$ , and $x\in X$ . Since ${\sf MS4} \vdash \chi ^t \to \Box \chi ^t$ , if $\mathfrak {F}, x \vDash _v \chi ^t$ , then $\mathfrak {F}, x \vDash _v \Box \chi ^t$ . Therefore, for each y such that $xRy$ we have $\mathfrak {F}, y \vDash _v \chi ^t$ . Thus, $\{ x \in X \mid \mathfrak {F}, x \vDash _v \chi ^t \}$ is an R-upset.

The next result generalizes to our setting a well-known correspondence result [Reference Chagrov and Zakharyaschev9, Lemma 3.81] between ${\sf IPC}$ -models and ${\sf S4}$ -models.

Proposition 4.10.

  1. 1. For each valuation $v$ on an ${\sf MS4}$ -frame $\mathfrak {F}$ there is a valuation $v'$ on $\mathfrak {F}^t$ such that for each $x\in \mathfrak F$ and $\mathcal {L}_{\forall \exists }$ -formula $\varphi $ , we have

    $$ \begin{align*} \mathfrak{F}^t, [x] \vDash_{v'} \varphi \ \mbox{ iff } \ \mathfrak{F}, x \vDash_v \varphi^t. \end{align*} $$
  2. 2. For each valuation $v$ on a ${\sf TS4}$ -frame $\mathfrak {F}$ there is a valuation $v'$ on $\mathfrak {F}^\natural $ such that for each $x \in \mathfrak {F}$ and $\mathcal {L}_{\forall \exists }$ -formula $\varphi $ , we have

    $$ \begin{align*} \mathfrak{F^\natural}, [x] \vDash_{v'} \varphi \ \mbox{ iff } \ \mathfrak{F},x \vDash_{v} \varphi^\natural. \end{align*} $$
  3. 3. Each valuation $v$ on an ${\sf MS4.t}$ -frame $\mathfrak {F}$ is also a valuation on $\mathfrak {F}^\dagger $ and for each $x \in \mathfrak {F}$ and $\mathcal {ML}$ -formula $\varphi $ , we have

    $$ \begin{align*} \mathfrak{F^\dagger}, x \vDash_v \varphi \ \mbox{ iff } \ \mathfrak{F},x \vDash_v \varphi^\dagger. \end{align*} $$
  4. 4. Each valuation $v$ on an ${\sf MS4.t}$ -frame $\mathfrak {F}$ is also a valuation on $\mathfrak {F}$ as an ${\sf MS4}$ -frame and for each $x \in \mathfrak {F}$ and $\mathcal L_{\Box \forall }$ -formula $\varphi $ , we have

    $$ \begin{align*} \mathfrak{F}, x \vDash_v \varphi \ \mbox{ iff } \ \mathfrak{F},x \vDash_v \varphi^\#. \end{align*} $$

Proof. (1). Define $v'$ on $\mathfrak {F}^t$ by $v'(p)=\{ [x] \in X' \mid R[x] \subseteq v(p)\}$ . It is easy to see that $v'$ is well defined. We show that $\mathfrak {F}^t, [x] \vDash _{v'} \varphi $ iff $\mathfrak {F},x \vDash _v \varphi ^t$ by induction on the complexity of $\varphi $ . Since $v'(p)= \{ [x] \mid \mathfrak {F},x \vDash _v \Box p \}$ , the claim is obvious when $\varphi $ is a propositional letter. We prove the claim for $\varphi $ of the form $\forall \psi $ and $\exists \psi $ since the other cases are well known (see, e.g., [Reference Chagrov and Zakharyaschev9, Lemma 3.81]). Suppose $\varphi =\forall \psi $ . By the definition of $Q'$ and induction hypothesis, we have

$$ \begin{align*} \mathfrak{F}^t, [x] \vDash_{v'} \forall \psi &\mbox{ iff } (\forall [y] \in X')([x]Q'[y] \, \Rightarrow \, \mathfrak{F}^t, [y] \vDash_{v'} \psi)\\ &\mbox{ iff } (\forall y \in X)(xQ_Ey \, \Rightarrow \, \mathfrak{F}^t, [y] \vDash_{v'} \psi)\\ &\mbox{ iff } (\forall y \in X)(xQ_Ey \, \Rightarrow \, \mathfrak{F}, y \vDash_v \psi^t). \end{align*} $$

On the other hand,

$$ \begin{align*} \mathfrak{F}, x \vDash_v (\forall \psi)^t &\mbox{ iff } \mathfrak{F}, x \vDash_v \Box \forall \psi^t\\ &\mbox{ iff } (\forall z \in X)(xRz \, \Rightarrow \, (\forall y \in X)(zEy \, \Rightarrow \, \mathfrak{F}, y \vDash_v \psi^t))\\ &\mbox{ iff } (\forall y \in X)(xQ_Ey \, \Rightarrow \, \mathfrak{F}, y \vDash_v \psi^t). \end{align*} $$

Thus, $\mathfrak {F}^t, [x] \vDash _{v'} \forall \psi $ iff $\mathfrak {F}, x \vDash _v (\forall \psi )^t$ .

Suppose $\varphi =\exists \psi $ . As noted in Remark 3.3, $Q'$ and $E_{Q'}$ coincide on $R'$ -upsets, and it is straightforward to see by induction that the set $\{ [y] \mid \mathfrak {F}^t, [y] \vDash _{v'} \psi \}$ is an $R'$ -upset. Therefore, by the induction hypothesis,

$$ \begin{align*} \mathfrak{F}^t, [x] \vDash_{v'} \exists \psi &\mbox{ iff } (\exists [y] \in X')([x]E_{Q'}[y] \; \& \; \mathfrak{F}^t, [y] \vDash_{v'} \psi)\\ &\mbox{ iff } [x] \in E_{Q'}[\{ [y] \mid \mathfrak{F}^t, [y] \vDash_{v'} \psi \}]\\ &\mbox{ iff } [x] \in Q'[\{ [y] \mid \mathfrak{F}^t, [y] \vDash_{v'} \psi \}]\\ &\mbox{ iff } x \in Q_E[\{ y \mid \mathfrak{F}^t, [y] \vDash_{v'} \psi \}]\\ &\mbox{ iff } x \in Q_E[\{ y \mid \mathfrak{F}, y \vDash_v \psi^t \}]. \end{align*} $$

On the other hand, since $\{ y \mid \mathfrak {F}, y \vDash _v \psi ^t \}$ is an R-upset (see Lemma 4.9), and E and $Q_E$ coincide on R-upsets, we have

$$ \begin{align*} \mathfrak{F}, x \vDash_v (\exists \psi)^t &\mbox{ iff } \mathfrak{F}, x \vDash_v \exists \psi^t \\ &\mbox{ iff } (\exists y \in X)(xEy \; \& \; \mathfrak{F}, y \vDash_v \psi^t)\\ &\mbox{ iff } x \in E[\{ y \mid \mathfrak{F}, y \vDash_v \psi^t \}]\\ &\mbox{ iff } x \in Q_E[\{ y \mid \mathfrak{F}, y \vDash_v \psi^t \}]. \end{align*} $$

Thus, $\mathfrak {F}^t, [x] \vDash _{v'} \exists \psi $ iff $\mathfrak {F}, x \vDash _v (\exists \psi )^t$ .

(2). As in (1) we define $v'$ by $v'(p)=\{ [x] \in X' \mid R[x] \subseteq v(p)\}$ . We show that $\mathfrak {F^\natural }, [x] \vDash _{v'} \varphi $ iff $\mathfrak {F},x \vDash _{v} \varphi ^\natural $ by induction on the complexity of $\varphi $ . It is sufficient to only consider the cases when $\varphi $ is of the form $\forall \psi $ or $\exists \psi $ . Suppose $\varphi =\forall \psi $ . Then by the definition of $Q'$ and induction hypothesis,

$$ \begin{align*} \mathfrak{F}^\natural, [x] \vDash_{v'} \forall \psi &\mbox{ iff } (\forall [y] \in X')([x]Q'[y] \, \Rightarrow \, \mathfrak{F}^\natural, [y] \vDash_{v'} \psi)\\ &\mbox{ iff } (\forall y \in X)(xQy \, \Rightarrow \, \mathfrak{F}^\natural, [y] \vDash_{v'} \psi) \\ &\mbox{ iff } (\forall y \in X)(xQy \, \Rightarrow \, \mathfrak{F}, y \vDash_v \psi^\natural) \\ &\mbox{ iff } \mathfrak{F}, x \vDash_v {[F]} \psi^\natural \\ &\mbox{ iff } \mathfrak{F}, x \vDash_v (\forall \psi)^\natural. \end{align*} $$

Suppose $\varphi =\exists \psi $ . As noted in Remark 3.3, $Q'$ and $E_{Q'}$ coincide on $R'$ -upsets. Since the set $\{ [y] \mid \mathfrak {F}^\natural , [y] \vDash _{v'} \psi \}$ is an $R'$ -upset, by the induction hypothesis, we have

$$ \begin{align*} \mathfrak{F}^\natural, [x] \vDash_{v'} \exists \psi &\mbox{ iff } (\exists [y] \in X')([x]E_{Q'}[y] \; \& \; \mathfrak{F}^\natural, [y] \vDash_{v'} \psi)\\ &\mbox{ iff } [x] \in E_{Q'}[\{ [y] \mid \mathfrak{F}^\natural, [y] \vDash_{v'} \psi \}]\\ &\mbox{ iff } [x] \in Q'[\{ [y] \mid \mathfrak{F}^\natural, [y] \vDash_{v'} \psi \}]\\ &\mbox{ iff } x \in Q[\{ y \mid \mathfrak{F}^\natural, [y] \vDash_{v'} \psi \}]\\ &\mbox{ iff } x \in Q[\{ y \mid \mathfrak{F}, y \vDash_v \psi^\natural \}] \\ &\mbox{ iff } (\exists y \in X)(yQx \; \& \; \mathfrak{F}, y \vDash_v \psi^\natural) \\ &\mbox{ iff } \mathfrak{F}, x \vDash_v {\langle P \rangle} \psi^\natural \\ &\mbox{ iff } \mathfrak{F}, x \vDash_v (\exists \psi)^\natural. \end{align*} $$

(3). It is clear that if v is a valuation on $\mathfrak {F}$ , then v is also a valuation on $\mathfrak {F}^\dagger $ . We show that $\mathfrak {F}^\dagger , x \vDash _v \varphi $ iff $\mathfrak {F},x \vDash _v \varphi ^\dagger $ by induction on the complexity of $\varphi $ . The only nontrivial cases are when $\varphi $ is of the form $\Box \psi $ , ${[F]} \psi $ , and ${[P]} \psi $ . Suppose $\varphi =\Box \psi $ . Then, by the induction hypothesis,

$$ \begin{align*} \mathfrak{F}^\dagger, x \vDash_v \Box \psi &\mbox{ iff } (\forall y \in X)(xRy \, \Rightarrow \, \mathfrak{F}^\dagger, y \vDash_v \psi)\\ &\mbox{ iff } (\forall y \in X)(xRy \, \Rightarrow \, \mathfrak{F}, y \vDash_v \psi^\dagger) \\ &\mbox{ iff } \mathfrak{F}, x \vDash_v \Box_F \psi^\dagger\\ &\mbox{ iff } \mathfrak{F}, x \vDash_v (\Box \psi)^\dagger. \end{align*} $$

Suppose $\varphi ={[F]} \psi $ . Then, by the induction hypothesis,

$$ \begin{align*} \mathfrak{F}^\dagger, x \vDash_v {[F]} \psi &\mbox{ iff } (\forall y \in X)(x Q_E y \, \Rightarrow \, \mathfrak{F}^\dagger, y \vDash_v \psi)\\&\mbox{ iff } (\forall z \in X)(xRz \, \Rightarrow \, (\forall y \in X)(zEy \, \Rightarrow \, \mathfrak{F}^\dagger, y \vDash_v \psi))\\&\mbox{ iff } (\forall z \in X)(xRz \, \Rightarrow \, (\forall y \in X)(zEy \, \Rightarrow \, \mathfrak{F}, y \vDash_v \psi^\dagger)) \\&\mbox{ iff } (\forall z \in X)(xRz \, \Rightarrow \, \mathfrak{F}, z \vDash \forall \psi^\dagger)\\&\mbox{ iff } \mathfrak{F}, x \vDash_v \Box_F \forall \psi^\dagger\\&\mbox{ iff } \mathfrak{F}, x \vDash_v ({[F]} \psi)^\dagger. \end{align*} $$

Suppose $\varphi ={[P]} \psi $ . Then, by the induction hypothesis,

$$ \begin{align*} \mathfrak{F}^\dagger, x \vDash_v {[P]} \psi &\mbox{ iff } (\forall y \in X)(y Q_E x \, \Rightarrow \, \mathfrak{F}^\dagger, y \vDash_v \psi)\\&\mbox{ iff } (\forall y,z \in X)(yRz \ \& \ zEx \, \Rightarrow \, \mathfrak{F}^\dagger, y \vDash_v \psi)\\&\mbox{ iff } (\forall z \in X)(zEx \, \Rightarrow \, (\forall y \in X)(yRz \, \Rightarrow \, \mathfrak{F}^\dagger, y \vDash_v \psi))\\&\mbox{ iff } (\forall z \in X)(zEx \, \Rightarrow \, (\forall y \in X)(yRz \, \Rightarrow \, \mathfrak{F}, y \vDash_v \psi^\dagger)) \\&\mbox{ iff } (\forall z \in X)(xEz \, \Rightarrow \, \mathfrak{F}, z \vDash \Box_P \psi^\dagger)\\&\mbox{ iff } \mathfrak{F}, x \vDash_v \forall \Box_P \psi^\dagger\\&\mbox{ iff } \mathfrak{F}, x \vDash_v ({[P]} \psi)^\dagger. \end{align*} $$

(4). This is an immediate consequence of the definition of $(-)^\#$ and the relational semantics for ${\sf MS4}$ and ${\sf MS4.t}$ .

Proposition 4.11.

  1. 1. For each ${\sf MS4}$ -frame $\mathfrak {F}$ and $\mathcal {L}_{\forall \exists }$ -formula $\varphi $ , we have

    $$ \begin{align*} \mathfrak{F}^t \vDash \varphi \ \mbox{ iff } \ \mathfrak{F} \vDash \varphi^t. \end{align*} $$
  2. 2. For each ${\sf TS4}$ -frame $\mathfrak {F}$ and $\mathcal {L}_{\forall \exists }$ -formula $\varphi $ , we have

    $$ \begin{align*} \mathfrak{F}^\natural \vDash \varphi \ \mbox{ iff } \ \mathfrak{F} \vDash \varphi^\natural. \end{align*} $$
  3. 3. For each ${\sf MS4.t}$ -frame $\mathfrak {F}$ and $\mathcal {ML}$ -formula $\varphi $ , we have

    $$ \begin{align*} \mathfrak{F}^\dagger \vDash \varphi \ \mbox{ iff } \ \mathfrak{F} \vDash \varphi^\dagger. \end{align*} $$
  4. 4. For each ${\sf MS4.t}$ -frame $\mathfrak {F}$ and $\mathcal L_{\Box \forall }$ -formula $\varphi $ , we have

    $$ \begin{align*} \mathfrak{F} \vDash \varphi \ \mbox{ iff } \ \mathfrak{F} \vDash \varphi^\#. \end{align*} $$

Proof. We only prove (2) since the proofs of (1), (3), and (4) are similar. If $\mathfrak {F} \nvDash \varphi ^\natural $ , then there is a valuation $v$ on $\mathfrak {F}$ such that $\mathfrak {F}, x \nvDash _v \varphi ^\natural $ for some $x \in X$ . By Proposition 4.10(2), $v'$ is a valuation on $\mathfrak {F}^\natural $ such that $\mathfrak {F}^\natural , [x] \nvDash _{v'} \varphi $ . Therefore, $\mathfrak {F}^\natural \nvDash \varphi $ . If $\mathfrak {F}^\natural \nvDash \varphi $ , then there is a valuation $w$ on $\mathfrak {F}^\natural $ and $[x] \in X'$ such that $\mathfrak {F}^\natural , [x] \nvDash _w \varphi $ . Let $v$ be the valuation on $\mathfrak {F}$ given by $v(p)=\{x \mid [x] \in w(p)\}$ . Since $\mathfrak {F}^\natural $ is an ${\sf MIPC}$ -frame, $w(p)$ is an $R'$ -upset of $\mathfrak {F}^\natural $ for each p. So $v(p)$ is an R-upset of $\mathfrak {F}$ for each p. Therefore, $w=v'$ because

$$ \begin{align*} v'(p)=\{ [x] \in X' \mid R[x] \subseteq v(p) \}=\{ [x] \in X' \mid x \in v(p) \}=w(p). \end{align*} $$

Thus, $\mathfrak {F}^\natural , [x] \nvDash _{v'} \varphi $ . By Proposition 4.10(2), $\mathfrak {F}, x \nvDash _v \varphi ^\natural $ . Consequently, $\mathfrak {F} \nvDash \varphi ^\natural $ .

In order to show that the translations are full, we also need the following result, which generalizes to our setting a well-known fact that each ${\sf IPC}$ -frame is the skeleton of an ${\sf S4}$ -frame.

Proposition 4.12.

  1. 1. For each ${\sf MIPC}$ -frame $\mathfrak {G}$ there is an ${\sf MS4}$ -frame $\mathfrak {F}$ such that $\mathfrak {G}$ is isomorphic to $\mathfrak {F}^t$ .

  2. 2. Each ${\sf MIPC}$ -frame $\mathfrak {G}$ is also a ${\sf TS4}$ -frame and $\mathfrak {G}^\natural $ is isomorphic to $\mathfrak {G}$ .

  3. 3. For each ${\sf TS4}$ -frame $\mathfrak {G}$ there is an ${\sf MS4.t}$ -frame $\mathfrak {F}$ such that $\mathfrak {G}=\mathfrak {F}^\dagger $ .

Proof. (1). Let $\mathfrak {G}=(X,R,Q)$ be an ${\sf MIPC}$ -frame. We show that $\mathfrak {F}=(X,R,E_Q)$ is an ${\sf MS4}$ -frame. If $xE_Qy$ and $yRz$ , then by definition of $E_Q$ and Condition (O1), $xQy$ and $yQz$ . Since Q is transitive, $xQz$ . Condition (O2) then implies that there is $u \in X$ with $xRu$ and $u E_Q z$ . Thus, $\mathfrak F$ is an ${\sf MS4}$ -frame. Since R is a partial order, it is an immediate consequence of Definition 4.6(1) that $\sim $ is the identity relation. It follows from Condition (O2) that $Q=Q_{E_Q}$ . Hence, $\mathfrak {G}$ is isomorphic to $\mathfrak {F}^t$ .

(2). Let $\mathfrak {G}=(X,R,Q)$ be an ${\sf MIPC}$ -frame. It is clear from the definition of ${\sf TS4}$ -frames that $\mathfrak {G}$ is also a ${\sf TS4}$ -frame. Since R is a partial order, $\sim $ is the identity relation. Therefore, $\mathfrak {G}$ is isomorphic to $\mathfrak {G}^\natural $ .

(3). Let $\mathfrak {G}=(X,R,Q)$ be a ${\sf TS4}$ -frame. As we observed in Remark 3.17, $\mathfrak {F}=(X,R,E_Q)$ is an ${\sf MS4}$ -frame, and so an ${\sf MS4.t}$ -frame. By definition of ${\sf TS4}$ -frames we have that $Q=Q_{E_Q}$ , and hence $\mathfrak {G}=\mathfrak {F}^\dagger $ .

We are ready to prove the main result of this section that the four translations are full and faithful. That the Gödel translation of ${\sf MIPC}$ into ${\sf MS4}$ is full and faithful was first observed by Fischer-Servi [Reference Fischer-Servi14] using the translations of ${\sf MIPC}$ and ${\sf MS4}$ into ${\sf IQC}$ and ${\sf QS4}$ , respectively, and the predicate version of the Gödel translation. In [Reference Fischer-Servi15] she gave a different proof of this result, using that ${\sf MIPC}$ has the fmp. Our proof utilizes the relational semantics and generalizes the semantic proof that the Gödel translation of ${\sf IPC}$ into ${\sf S4}$ is full and faithful (see, e.g., [Reference Chagrov and Zakharyaschev9, Sec. 3.9]).

Theorem 4.13.

  1. 1. The Gödel translation $(-)^t$ of ${\sf MIPC}$ into ${\sf MS4}$ is full and faithful; that is,

    $$ \begin{align*} {\sf MIPC} \vdash\varphi \quad \mbox{ iff } \quad {\sf MS4} \vdash \varphi^t. \end{align*} $$
  2. 2. The translation $(-)^\natural $ of ${\sf MIPC}$ into ${\sf TS4}$ is full and faithful; that is,

    $$ \begin{align*} {\sf MIPC} \vdash\varphi \quad \mbox{ iff } \quad {\sf TS4} \vdash\varphi^\natural. \end{align*} $$
  3. 3. The translation $(-)^\dagger $ of ${\sf TS4}$ into ${\sf MS4.t}$ is full and faithful; that is,

    $$ \begin{align*} \begin{array}{l c l} {\sf TS4} \vdash \varphi & \mbox{ iff } & {\sf MS4.t} \vdash \varphi^\dagger. \end{array} \end{align*} $$
  4. 4. The translation $(-)^\#$ of ${\sf MS4}$ into ${\sf MS4.t}$ is full and faithful; that is,

    $$ \begin{align*} \begin{array}{l c l} {\sf MS4} \vdash \varphi & \mbox{ iff } & {\sf MS4.t} \vdash \varphi^\#. \end{array} \end{align*} $$

Proof. We prove (2). For faithfulness, suppose that ${\sf TS4} \nvdash \varphi ^\natural $ . By Theorem 3.18, there is a ${\sf TS4}$ -frame $\mathfrak {F}$ such that $\mathfrak {F} \nvDash \varphi ^\natural $ . By Propositions 4.8(2) and 4.11(2), $\mathfrak {F}^\natural $ is an ${\sf MIPC}$ -frame and $\mathfrak {F}^\natural \nvDash \varphi $ . Thus, by Theorem 3.5, ${\sf MIPC} \nvdash \varphi $ . For fullness, let ${\sf MIPC} \nvdash \varphi $ . Then there is an ${\sf MIPC}$ -frame $\mathfrak {G}$ such that $\mathfrak {G} \nvDash \varphi $ . By Proposition 4.12(2), there is a ${\sf TS4}$ -frame $\mathfrak{F}$ such that $\mathfrak {G}$ is isomorphic to $\mathfrak {F}^\natural $ . Therefore, $\mathfrak {F}^\natural \nvDash \varphi $ . Proposition 4.11(2) implies that $\mathfrak {F} \nvDash \varphi ^\natural $ . Thus, ${\sf TS4} \nvdash \varphi ^\natural $ .

The proofs of (1), (3), and (4) are obtained analogously using Theorems 3.5, 3.9, 3.18, and 3.21, and Propositions 4.8, 4.11, and 4.12.

5 Compositions of the translations

In this section we show that the translations introduced in the previous section form a commutative diagram up to logical equivalence.

We denote the composition of $(-)^\#$ and $(-)^t$ by $(-)^{t \#}$ , and the composition of $(-)^\dagger $ and $(-)^\natural $ by $(-)^{\natural \dagger }$ . Since we proved that all these four translations are full and faithful, we also have that $(-)^{t \#}$ and $(-)^{\natural \dagger }$ are full and faithful translations of ${\sf MIPC}$ into ${\sf MS4.t}$ . We have thus obtained the following diagram of full and faithful translations. We next show that this diagram is commutative up to logical equivalence in ${\sf MS4.t}$ .

Lemma 5.1. For each formula $\varphi $ of $\mathcal L_{\forall \exists }$ , we have

$$ \begin{align*} {\sf MS4.t} \vdash \varphi^{t \#} \leftrightarrow \Diamond_P \varphi^{t \#}. \end{align*} $$

Proof. By Lemma 4.9 and Theorem 4.13(4), ${\sf MS4.t} \vdash \varphi ^{t \#} \to \Box _F \varphi ^{t \#}$ . Therefore, ${\sf MS4.t} \vdash \Diamond _P \varphi ^{t \#} \to \Diamond _P \Box _F \varphi ^{t \#}$ . The tense axiom then gives ${\sf MS4.t} \vdash \Diamond _P \varphi ^{t \#} \to \varphi ^{t \#}$ . Thus, ${\sf MS4.t} \vdash \varphi ^{t \#} \leftrightarrow \Diamond _P \varphi ^{t \#}$ .

Theorem 5.2. For each $\mathcal L_{\forall \exists }$ -formula $\chi $ we have

$$ \begin{align*} {\sf MS4.t} \vdash \chi^{t \#} \leftrightarrow \chi^{\natural \dagger}. \end{align*} $$

Proof. The two compositions compare as follows:

$$ \begin{align*} &\bot^{t \#}=\bot && \bot^{\natural \dagger}=\bot \\ &p^{t \#}=\Box_F p && p^{\natural \dagger}=\Box_F p \\ &(\varphi \wedge \psi)^{t \#}= \varphi^{t \#} \wedge \psi^{t \#} \qquad && (\varphi \wedge \psi)^{\natural \dagger}= \varphi^{\natural \dagger} \wedge \psi^{\natural \dagger} \\ &(\varphi \vee \psi)^{t \#}= \varphi^{t \#} \vee \psi^{t \#} \qquad && (\varphi \vee \psi)^{\natural \dagger}= \varphi^{\natural \dagger} \vee \psi^{\natural \dagger} \\ &(\varphi \to \psi)^{t \#}= \Box_F(\neg \varphi^{t \#} \vee \psi^{t \#}) \qquad && (\varphi \to \psi)^{\natural \dagger}= \Box_F(\neg \varphi^{\natural \dagger} \vee \psi^{\natural \dagger}) \\ &(\forall \varphi)^{t \#}= \Box_F \forall \varphi^{t \#} && (\forall \varphi)^{\natural \dagger}= \Box_F \forall \varphi^{\natural \dagger} \\ &(\exists \varphi)^{t \#}= \exists \varphi^{t \#} && (\exists \varphi)^{\natural \dagger}= ({\langle P \rangle} \varphi^\natural)^\dagger= (\neg {[P]} \neg \varphi^\natural)^\dagger \\ & && \hphantom{(\exists \varphi)^{\natural \dagger}} = \neg \forall \Box_P \neg \varphi^{\natural \dagger}. \end{align*} $$

Thus, they are identical except the $\exists $ -clause. Therefore, to prove that ${\sf MS4.t} \vdash \chi ^{t \#} \leftrightarrow \chi ^{\natural \dagger }$ it is sufficient to prove that ${\sf MS4.t} \vdash \varphi ^{t \#} \leftrightarrow \varphi ^{\natural \dagger }$ implies ${\sf MS4.t} \vdash \exists \varphi ^{t \#} \leftrightarrow \neg \forall \Box _P \neg \varphi ^{\natural \dagger }$ . Since ${\sf MS4.t} \vdash \neg \forall \Box _P \neg \varphi ^{\natural \dagger } \leftrightarrow \exists \Diamond _P \varphi ^{\natural \dagger }$ , it is enough to prove that ${\sf MS4.t} \vdash \exists \varphi ^{t \#} \leftrightarrow \exists \Diamond _P \varphi ^{\natural \dagger }$ . From the assumption ${\sf MS4.t} \vdash \varphi ^{t \#} \leftrightarrow \varphi ^{\natural \dagger }$ it follows that ${\sf MS4.t} \vdash \exists \Diamond _P \varphi ^{t \#} \leftrightarrow \exists \Diamond _P \varphi ^{\natural \dagger }$ . By Lemma 5.1, ${\sf MS4.t} \vdash \varphi ^{t \#} \leftrightarrow \Diamond _P \varphi ^{t \#}$ and hence ${\sf MS4.t} \vdash \exists \varphi ^{t \#} \leftrightarrow \exists \Diamond _P \varphi ^{t \#}$ . Thus, ${\sf MS4.t} \vdash \exists \varphi ^{t \#} \leftrightarrow \exists \Diamond _P \varphi ^{\natural \dagger }$ .

As we pointed out in Remark 4.4(2), there is another natural translation of ${\sf MIPC}$ into ${\sf MS4.t}$ .

Definition 5.3. Let $(-)^\flat :{\sf MIPC} \to {\sf MS4.t}$ be the translation that differs from $(-)^{t \#}$ and $(-)^{\natural \dagger }$ only in the $\exists $ -clause:

$$ \begin{align*} &(\exists \varphi)^\flat= \Diamond_P \exists \varphi^\flat. \end{align*} $$

The translation $(-)^\flat $ provides a temporal interpretation of intuitionistic monadic quantifiers that is similar to the translation $(-)^\natural $ (see also Section 7).

Theorem 5.4. For each $\mathcal L_{\forall \exists }$ -formula $\chi $ we have

$$ \begin{align*} {\sf MS4.t} \vdash \chi^\flat \leftrightarrow \chi^{t \#}. \end{align*} $$

Consequently, the translation $(-)^\flat $ of ${\sf MIPC}$ into ${\sf MS4.t}$ is full and faithful.

Proof. The translations $(-)^\flat $ and $(-)^{t \#}$ are identical except the $\exists $ -clause. Therefore, to prove that ${\sf MS4.t} \vdash \chi ^\flat \leftrightarrow \chi ^{t \#}$ it is sufficient to prove that ${\sf MS4.t} \vdash \varphi ^\flat \leftrightarrow \varphi ^{t \#}$ implies ${\sf MS4.t} \vdash \Diamond _P \exists \varphi ^\flat \leftrightarrow \exists \varphi ^{t \#}$ . By Lemma 5.1, ${\sf MS4.t} \vdash (\exists \varphi )^{t \#} \leftrightarrow \Diamond _P (\exists \varphi )^{t \#}$ which means ${\sf MS4.t} \vdash \exists \varphi ^{t \#} \leftrightarrow \Diamond _P \exists \varphi ^{t \#}$ . From the assumption ${\sf MS4.t} \vdash \varphi ^\flat \leftrightarrow \varphi ^{t \#}$ it follows that ${\sf MS4.t} \vdash \Diamond _P \exists \varphi ^\flat \leftrightarrow \exists \varphi ^{t \#}$ . Since $(-)^{t \#}$ is full and faithful, we conclude that $(-)^\flat $ is full and faithful as well.

As a result, we obtain the following diagram of full and faithful translations that is commutative up to logical equivalence in ${\sf MS4.t}$ :

6 Finite model property

In this section we give a uniform proof of the fmp for the four logics studied in this paper. Our strategy is to first establish the fmp for ${\sf MS4.t}$ via algebraic methods, and then use the full and faithful translations to conclude that the other three logics also have the fmp.

The algebraic semantics for ${\sf MS4.t}$ is given by ${\sf MS4.t}$ -algebras. To define these algebras, we first recall the definition of ${\sf S4}$ -algebras, ${\sf S5}$ -algebras, and ${\sf S4.t}$ -algebras, which provide algebraic semantics for ${\sf S4}$ , ${\sf S5}$ , and ${\sf S4.t}$ , respectively. ${\sf S4}$ -algebras are known under various names. They were first introduced by McKinsey and Tarski [Reference McKinsey and Tarski22] under the name of closure algebras. Rasiowa and Sikorski [Reference Rasiowa and Sikorski27] call them topological Boolean algebras and Blok [Reference Blok6] calls them interior algebras. ${\sf S5}$ -algebras were first introduced by Halmos [Reference Halmos20] under the name of monadic algebras, and ${\sf S4.t}$ -algebras by Esakia [Reference Esakia11] under the name of ${\sf S4}^2$ -algebras.

Definition 6.1. Let B be a Boolean algebra.

  1. 1. A unary function $\Box :B\to B$ is an interior operator on B if

    $$ \begin{align*} \Box(a\wedge b) = \Box a \wedge \Box b, \qquad \Box 1 =1, \qquad \Box a \leq a, \qquad \Box a \leq \Box \Box a, \end{align*} $$
    for all $a,b \in B$ .
  2. 2. An ${\sf S4}$ -algebra is a pair $\mathfrak {B}=(B, \Box )$ where B is a Boolean algebra and $\Box $ is an interior operator on B.

  3. 3. An ${\sf S5}$ -algebra is an ${\sf S4}$ -algebra $\mathfrak {B}=(B, \forall )$ that in addition satisfies $a \leq \forall \exists a$ for all $a \in B$ , where $\exists $ denotes the dual operator $\neg \forall \neg $ .

  4. 4. An ${\sf S4.t}$ -algebra is a triple $\mathfrak {B}=(B, \Box _F, \Box _P)$ where B is a Boolean algebra and $\Box _F, \Box _P$ are interior operators on B such that

    (PF) $$ \begin{align} a \le \Box_P \Diamond_F a, \end{align} $$
    (FP) $$ \begin{align} a \le \Box_F \Diamond_P a, \end{align} $$
    for all $a \in B$ , where $\Diamond _F=\neg \Box _F \neg $ and $\Diamond _P=\neg \Box _P \neg $ .

${\sf MS4.t}$ -algebras are obtained by combining ${\sf S4.t}$ -algebras and ${\sf S5}$ -algebras.

Definition 6.2. An ${\sf MS4.t}$ -algebra is a tuple $\mathfrak B=(B, \Box _F, \Box _P, \forall )$ where

  1. 1. $(B, \Box _F, \Box _P)$ is an ${\sf S4.t}$ -algebra,

  2. 2. $(B, \forall )$ is an ${\sf S5}$ -algebra,

  3. 3. $\Box _F \forall a \leq \forall \Box _F a$ for each $a\in B$ .

Validity of $\mathcal L_{T\forall }$ -formulas in ${\sf MS4.t}$ -algebras is defined in the usual way (see, e.g., [Reference Chagrov and Zakharyaschev9, Reference Rasiowa and Sikorski27]). If a formula $\varphi $ is valid in an ${\sf MS4.t}$ -algebra $\mathfrak {B}$ , we write $\mathfrak B \vDash \varphi $ . The standard Lindenbaum–Tarski construction (see, e.g., [Reference Rasiowa and Sikorski27, Chap. VI]) yields the following:

Theorem 6.3. ${\sf MS4.t}$ is sound and complete with respect to its algebraic semantics. Therefore,

$$ \begin{align*} {\sf MS4.t} \vdash \varphi \ \mbox{ iff } \ \mathfrak B \vDash \varphi \mbox{ for every}\ {\sf MS4.t}\text{-}{algebra}\ \mathfrak B. \end{align*} $$

Definition 6.4. Let $\mathfrak B=(B, \Box _F, \Box _P, \forall )$ be an ${\sf MS4.t}$ -algebra. We define

  1. 1. $H_F:=\{a \in B \mid \Box _F a=a\}$ to be the set of $\Box _F$ -fixpoints,

  2. 2. $H_P:=\{a \in B \mid \Box _P a=a\}$ to be the set of $\Box _P$ -fixpoints,

  3. 3. $B_0:=\{a \in B \mid \forall a=a\}$ to be the set of $\forall $ -fixpoints.

Remark 6.5.

  1. 1. It is well known (see, e.g., [Reference Esakia13, Proposition 2.2.4]) that $H_F$ and $H_P$ with the restricted order from B are both Heyting algebras that are bounded sublattices of B. Moreover, it follows from Definition 6.1(4) that $H_F$ coincides with the set of $\Diamond _P$ -fixpoints and $H_P$ with the set of $\Diamond _F$ -fixpoints. Furthermore, $\neg $ maps $H_F$ to $H_P$ and vice versa. Indeed, if $a \in H_F$ , then $a = \Box _F a$ . By (PF), $\Diamond _P a = \Diamond _P \Box _F a \le a$ , so $\Diamond _P a = a$ , and hence $\Box _P \neg a =\neg \Diamond _P a= \neg a$ . Therefore, $\neg a \in H_P$ . Similarly, if $a \in H_P$ , then $\neg a \in H_F$ . Thus, $\neg $ is a dual isomorphism between $H_F$ and $H_P$ .

  2. 2. It is easy to see that $B_0$ is an ${\sf S4}$ -subalgebra of $(B, \Box _F)$ because the inequality $\Box _F \forall a \leq \forall \Box _F a$ , which corresponds to the left commutativity axiom, is equivalent to the equality $\forall \Box _F \forall a = \Box _F \forall a$ .

We now prove that ${\sf MS4.t}$ has the fmp. For this we must show that if ${\sf MS4.t}\not \vdash \varphi $ , then $\varphi $ is refuted on a finite ${\sf MS4.t}$ -algebra.

Definition 6.6. Let $\mathfrak {B}=(B, \Box _F, \Box _P, \forall )$ be an ${\sf MS4.t}$ -algebra and $S \subseteq B$ a finite subset. Then $(B, \forall )$ is an ${\sf S5}$ -algebra. Let $(B', \forall ')$ be the ${\sf S5}$ -subalgebra of $(B, \forall )$ generated by S. It is well known (see [Reference Bass1]) that $(B', \forall ')$ is finite. Define $\Box _F'$ and $\Box _P'$ on $B'$ by

$$ \begin{align*} \Box_F' a &= \bigvee \{ b \in B'\cap H_F \mid b \leq a \}, \\ \Box_P' a &= \bigvee \{ b \in B'\cap H_P \mid b \leq a \}. \end{align*} $$

We denote $(B', \Box _F', \Box _P', \forall ')$ by $\mathfrak {B}_S$ .

Lemma 6.7. $\mathfrak {B}_S$ is an ${\sf MS4.t}$ -algebra.

Proof. $(B',\forall ')$ is an ${\sf S5}$ -algebra by definition. Since $(B, \Box _F)$ and $(B, \Box _P)$ are both ${\sf S4}$ -algebras, a standard argument (see [Reference McKinsey and Tarski22, Lemma 4.14]) shows that $(B', \Box _F')$ and $(B', \Box _P')$ are also ${\sf S4}$ -algebras. We show that $(B', \Box _F', \Box _P')$ is an ${\sf S4.t}$ -algebra. As noted in Remark 6.5(1), $\neg $ is a dual isomorphism between the algebras $H_F$ and $H_P$ of $\Box _F$ -fixpoints and $\Box _P$ -fixpoints of $\mathfrak {B}$ . Therefore,

$$ \begin{align*} \Diamond_F' a := \neg \Box_F' \neg a & = \neg \bigvee \{ b \in B'\cap H_F \mid b \leq \neg a \} \\ & = \neg \bigvee \{ b \in B'\cap H_F \mid a \leq \neg b \} \\ & = \bigwedge \{ \neg b \mid b \in B'\cap H_F, \; a \leq \neg b \} \\ & = \bigwedge \{ c \in B' \cap H_P \mid a \leq c \}. \end{align*} $$

Since this meet is finite and $\Box _P$ commutes with finite meets, we obtain

$$ \begin{align*} \Box_P \Diamond_F' a & = \Box_P \left( \bigwedge \{ c \in B' \cap H_P \mid a \leq c \} \right) \\ & = \bigwedge \{ \Box_P c \mid c \in B' \cap H_P , \; a \leq c \} \\ & = \bigwedge \{ c \in B' \cap H_P \mid a \leq c \} \\ & = \Diamond_F' a. \end{align*} $$

Thus, $\Diamond _F' a \in B' \cap H_P $ which yields

$$ \begin{align*} \Box_P' \Diamond_F' a = \bigvee \{ b \in B' \cap H_P \mid b \leq \Diamond_F' a \} = \Diamond_F' a. \end{align*} $$

Similarly, we have that $\Diamond _P' a = \bigwedge \{ c \in B' \cap H_F \mid a \leq c \}$ from which we deduce that $\Box _F' \Diamond _P' a = \Diamond _P' a$ . This implies that $a \le \Box _P' \Diamond _F' a$ and $a \le \Box _F' \Diamond _P' a$ . Consequently, $(B, \Box _F', \Box _P')$ is an ${\sf S4.t}$ -algebra.

It remains to show that $\Box _F' \forall ' a \le \forall ' \Box _F' a$ holds in $\mathfrak {B}_S$ . For this it is sufficient to show that the set $B_0':=B' \cap B_0$ of the $\forall '$ -fixpoints of $B'$ is an ${\sf S4}$ -subalgebra of $(B', \Box _F')$ because then $\Box _F' \forall ' a=\forall ' \Box _F' \forall ' a \le \forall ' \Box _F' a$ . Suppose that $d \in B_0'$ . By definition, $\Box _F' d = \bigvee \{ b \in B'\cap H_F \mid b \leq d \}$ . Let $b \in B'\cap H_F$ . It follows from Lemma 2.5 that $\exists b = \exists \Box _F b =\Box _F \exists \Box _F b = \Box _F \exists b$ . Therefore, $\exists b \in B' \cap H_F$ . Moreover, $b \le \exists b$ and $b \le d$ imply $\exists b \le \exists d = d$ . Thus, $\Box _F' d = \bigvee \{ \exists b \mid b \in B'\cap H_F, \; b \leq d \}$ . Since $(B', \forall ')$ is an ${\sf S5}$ -algebra, $B_0'$ is the set of $\exists '$ -fixpoints of $B'$ and is closed under finite joins. Consequently, $\Box _F' d \in B_0'$ .

Theorem 6.8. ${\sf MS4.t}$ has the fmp.

Proof. By Theorem 6.3, it is sufficient to prove that each $\mathcal L_{T\forall }$ -formula $\varphi $ refuted on some ${\sf MS4.t}$ -algebra is also refuted on a finite ${\sf MS4.t}$ -algebra. Let $t(x_1, \ldots , x_n)$ be the term in the language of ${\sf MS4.t}$ -algebras that corresponds to $\varphi $ , and suppose there is an ${\sf MS4.t}$ -algebra $\mathfrak {B}=(B, \Box _F, \Box _P, \forall )$ and $a_1, \ldots , a_n \in B$ such that $t(a_1, \ldots , a_n) \neq 1$ in $\mathfrak {B}$ . Let

$$ \begin{align*} S=\{ t'(a_1, \ldots, a_n) \mid t' \mbox{ is a subterm of } t \}. \end{align*} $$

Then S is a finite subset of B. Therefore, by Lemma 6.7, $\mathfrak {B}_S=(B', \Box _F', \Box _P', \forall )$ is a finite ${\sf MS4.t}$ -algebra. It follows from the definition of $\Box _F'$ that, for each $b \in B'$ , if $\Box _F b \in B'$ , then $\Box _F' b= \Box _F b$ . Similarly, if $\Box _P b \in B'$ , then $\Box _P' b= \Box _P b$ . Thus, for each subterm $t'$ of t, the computation of $t'$ in $\mathfrak {B}_S$ is the same as that in $\mathfrak {B}$ . Consequently, $t(a_1, \ldots , a_n) \neq 1$ in $\mathfrak {B}_S$ , and we have found a finite ${\sf MS4.t}$ -algebra refuting $\varphi $ .

We conclude this section by showing that the fmp for ${\sf TS4}$ , ${\sf MS4}$ , and ${\sf MIPC}$ can be obtained as a consequence of Theorem 6.8 via the full and faithful translations into ${\sf MS4.t}$ described in Section 4. In order to do so, we state the fmp of ${\sf MS4.t}$ in terms of ${\sf MS4.t}$ -frames thanks to the correspondence between finite ${\sf MS4.t}$ -algebras and finite ${\sf MS4.t}$ -frames. In fact, we will obtain such a correspondence as a consequence of a representation result for ${\sf MS4.t}$ -algebras.

Definition 6.9. Let R be a quasi-order on a set X and $A \subseteq X$ . We define

$$ \begin{align*} \Box_R(A)=X\setminus R^{-1}[X\setminus A]. \end{align*} $$

If

is the inverse relation of R, we have

If E is an equivalence relation on X, we use the notation

$$ \begin{align*} \forall_E(A)=X\setminus E^{-1}[X\setminus A]=X\setminus E[X\setminus A]. \end{align*} $$

Proposition 6.10. For each ${\sf MS4.t}$ -frame $\mathfrak F=(X,R,E)$ we have that is an ${\sf MS4.t}$ -algebra.

Proof. Since R is a quasi-order, so is , and hence $(\wp (X),\Box _R)$ and are ${\sf S4}$ -algebras; and since E is an equivalence relation, $(\wp (X),\forall _E)$ is an ${\sf S5}$ -algebra (see [Reference Jónsson and Tarski21, Theorem 3.5]). In addition, the commutativity condition yields that $\Box _R \forall _E (A) \leq \forall _E \Box _R (A)$ for each $A \in \wp (X)$ . A standard argument (see [Reference Jónsson and Tarski21, Theorem 3.6]) gives that $\Box _R$ and satisfy (PF) and (FP). Therefore, $\mathfrak F^+$ is an ${\sf MS4.t}$ -algebra.

Remark 6.11. If $\mathfrak B=\mathfrak F^+$ , then the elements of $H_F$ and $H_P$ are, respectively, the R-upsets and R-downsets of $\mathfrak {F}$ , and the elements of $B_0$ are the E-saturated subsets of $\mathfrak {F}$ (that is, unions of E-equivalence classes).

We next prove that each ${\sf MS4.t}$ -algebra is represented as a subalgebra of $\mathfrak F^+$ for some ${\sf MS4.t}$ -frame $\mathfrak F$ .

Definition 6.12. Let $\mathfrak B=(B, \Box _F, \Box _P, \forall )$ be an ${\sf MS4.t}$ -algebra. The canonical frame of $\mathfrak B$ is the frame $\mathfrak B_+=(X_{\mathfrak B},R_{\mathfrak B},E_{\mathfrak B})$ where $X_{\mathfrak B}$ is the set of ultrafilters of B, $x R_{\mathfrak B} y$ iff $x\cap H_F \subseteq y$ iff $y\cap H_P \subseteq x$ , and $x E_{\mathfrak B} y$ iff $x\cap B_0 = y\cap B_0$ .

Lemma 6.13. If $\mathfrak B$ is an ${\sf MS4.t}$ -algebra, then $\mathfrak B_+$ is an ${\sf MS4.t}$ -frame.

Proof. Since $(B,\Box _F)$ is an ${\sf S4}$ -algebra, we have that $R_{\mathfrak B}$ is a quasi-order (see [Reference Jónsson and Tarski21, Theorem 3.14]); and since $(B,\forall )$ is an ${\sf S5}$ -algebra, $E_{\mathfrak B}$ is an equivalence relation (see [Reference Jónsson and Tarski21, Theorem 3.18]). It remains to show that Definition 3.7(E) is satisfied. Let $x,y,z \in X_{\mathfrak B}$ be such that $x E_{\mathfrak B} y$ and $y R_{\mathfrak B} z$ . This means that $x \cap B_0=y \cap B_0$ and $y \cap H_F \subseteq z$ . Let F be the filter of $\mathfrak B$ generated by $(x \cap H_F) \cup (z \cap B_0)$ . We show that F is proper. Otherwise, since $x \cap H_F$ and $z \cap B_0$ are closed under finite meets, there are $a \in x \cap H_F$ and $b \in z \cap B_0$ such that $a \land b =0$ . Therefore, $a \le \neg b$ . Thus, $a = \Box _F a \le \Box _F \neg b$ , so $\Box _F \neg b \in x$ . Since $B_0$ is an ${\sf S4}$ -subalgebra of $(B, \Box _F)$ (see Remark 6.5(2)) and $b \in B_0$ , we have $\Box _F \neg b \in B_0$ . This yields $\Box _F \neg b \in x \cap B_0=y \cap B_0$ , which implies $\Box _F \neg b \in y \cap H_F \subseteq z$ . Therefore, $\neg b \in z$ which contradicts $b \in z$ . Thus, F is proper, and so there is an ultrafilter u of B such that $F\subseteq u$ . Consequently, $x\cap H_F\subseteq u$ and $z\cap B_0\subseteq u\cap B_0$ . Since $z \cap B_0$ and $u \cap B_0$ are both ultrafilters of $B_0$ , we conclude that $z\cap B_0= u\cap B_0$ . Thus, there is $u\in X_{\mathfrak B}$ with $xR_{\mathfrak B}u$ and $uE_{\mathfrak B}z$ .

Definition 6.14. Let $\mathfrak {B}$ be an ${\sf MS4.t}$ -algebra. The Stone map $\beta :\mathfrak B\to (\mathfrak B_+)^+$ is defined by

$$ \begin{align*} \beta(a)=\{ x \in X_{\mathfrak B} \mid a \in x \}. \end{align*} $$

It follows from Jónsson-Tarski duality that $\beta$ is a 1-1 homomorphism of $\mathsf{MS4.t}$ -algebras, and that it is an isomorphism if $\mathfrak{B}$ is finite. Thus, we obtain the following representation theorem for ${\sf MS4.t}$ -algebras.

Theorem 6.15 (Representation theorem)

Let $\mathfrak {B}$ be an ${\sf MS4.t}$ -algebra.

  1. 1. $\mathfrak {B}$ is isomorphic to a subalgebra of $(\mathfrak B_+)^+$ .

  2. 2. When $\mathfrak {B}$ is finite, its embedding into $(\mathfrak B_+)^+$ is an isomorphism.

Remark 6.16. As usual, to recover the image of the embedding of $\mathfrak {B}$ into $(\mathfrak B_+)^+$ we need to endow $\mathfrak B_+$ with a Stone topology (see, e.g., [Reference Esakia13, Definition 3.3.3]). This leads to the notion of perfect ${\sf MS4.t}$ -frames and a duality between the categories of ${\sf MS4.t}$ -algebras and perfect ${\sf MS4.t}$ -frames.

Thanks to the representation theorem, the fmp of ${\sf MS4.t}$ can be equivalently stated as follows: if $\varphi $ is not a theorem of ${\sf MS4.t}$ , then it is refuted in a finite ${\sf MS4.t}$ -frame. We now obtain the fmp of ${\sf TS4}$ , ${\sf MS4}$ , and ${\sf MIPC}$ as a consequence of the fmp of ${\sf MS4.t}$ .

Theorem 6.17.

  1. 1. ${\sf TS4}$ has the fmp.

  2. 2. ${\sf MS4}$ has the fmp.

  3. 3. ${\sf MIPC}$ has the fmp.

Proof. (1). Suppose that ${\sf TS4} \nvdash \varphi $ . By Theorem 4.13(3), ${\sf MS4.t} \nvdash \varphi ^\dagger $ . Since ${\sf MS4.t}$ has the fmp, there is a finite ${\sf MS4.t}$ -frame $\mathfrak {F}$ such that $\mathfrak {F} \nvDash \varphi ^\dagger $ . By Proposition 4.11(3), $\mathfrak {F}^\dagger \nvDash \varphi $ . We have thus obtained a finite ${\sf TS4}$ -frame $\mathfrak {F}^\dagger $ refuting $\varphi $ .

(2). Similar to the proof of (1) but uses the translation $(-)^\# : {\sf MS4} \to {\sf MS4.t}$ instead of $(-)^\dagger $ .

(3). Similar to the proof of (1) but uses the composition $(-)^{t \#}: {\sf MIPC} \to {\sf MS4.t}$ instead of $(-)^\dagger $ . Alternatively, we can use the translation $(-)^{\natural \dagger }$ of ${\sf MIPC}$ into ${\sf MS4.t}$ .

Remark 6.18.

  1. 1. That ${\sf MIPC}$ has the fmp was first established by Bull [Reference Bull7] using algebraic semantics. His proof contained a gap, which was corrected independently by Fischer-Servi [Reference Fischer-Servi15] and Ono [Reference Ono23]. A semantic proof is given in [Reference Gabbay, Kurucz, Wolter and Zakharyaschev16], which is based on a technique developed by Grefe [Reference Grefe, Kracht, de Rijke, Wansing and Zakharyaschev19].

  2. 2. The fmp for ${\sf MS4}$ can be derived from the results in [Reference Gabbay and Shehtman17, Sec. 12] (see also [Reference Gabbay, Kurucz, Wolter and Zakharyaschev16, Theorems 6.52 and 9.12]). The proof given above is more direct.

  3. 3. The proof of the fmp for ${\sf MS4.t}$ contains the proof of the fmp for ${\sf S4.t}$ , but the latter is known (see [Reference Segerberg29, pp. 313–314] or [Reference Goldblatt18, p. 44]). In fact, ${\sf MS4.t}$ is a conservative extension of ${\sf S4.t}$ .

7 Connection with the full predicate case

In [Reference Bezhanishvili, Carai, Olivetti, Verbrugge, Negri and Sandu4] we studied a translation that is the predicate analogue of the translation $(-)^\flat: \mathsf{MIPC} \to \mathsf{MS4.t}$ . We proved that this translation embeds ${\sf IQC}$ fully and faithfully into a weakening of the tense predicate logic ${\sf QS4.t}$ . This weakening is necessary since ${\sf QS4.t}$ proves the Barcan formula for both $\Box _F$ and $\Box _P$ , so Kripke frames of ${\sf QS4.t}$ have constant domains, and hence they validate the translation of the constant domain axiom $\forall x(A\vee B)\to (A\vee \forall x B)$ , where x is not free in A. Since this is not provable in ${\sf IQC}$ , the translation cannot be full. Instead we considered the tense predicate logic ${\sf Q^\circ S4.t}$ in which the universal instantiation axiom $\forall x A \to A(y/x)$ is replaced by its weakened version $\forall y(\forall x A \to A(y/x))$ . The main result of [Reference Bezhanishvili, Carai, Olivetti, Verbrugge, Negri and Sandu4] proves that ${\sf IQC}$ translates fully and faithfully into ${\sf Q^\circ S4.t}$ (provided the translation is restricted to sentences).

It is natural to investigate the relationship between ${\sf MS4.t}$ and predicate extensions of ${\sf S4.t}$ . As we already pointed out in Remark 2.10, ${\sf MS4.t}$ is not the monadic fragment of ${\sf QS4.t}$ . In addition, ${\sf MS4.t}$ cannot be the monadic fragment of ${\sf Q^\circ S4.t}$ either since the formula $\forall x A \to A$ is not in general provable in ${\sf Q^\circ S4.t}$ , whereas $\forall \varphi \to \varphi $ is provable in ${\sf MS4.t}$ . On the other hand, call a formula $\varphi $ (in the language of ${\sf MS4.t}$ ) bounded if each occurrence of a propositional letter in $\varphi $ is under the scope of $\forall $ . Bounded formulas play the same role as sentences of ${\sf Q^\circ S4.t}$ containing only one fixed variable. It is quite plausible that for a bounded formula $\varphi $ we have ${\sf MS4.t}\vdash \varphi $ iff ${\sf Q^\circ S4.t}$ proves the translation of $\varphi $ where each occurrence of a propositional letter p is replaced with the unary predicate $P(x)$ and $\forall $ is replaced with $\forall x$ (for a similar translation of $\sf MIPC$ and its extensions into ${\sf IQC}$ and its extensions, see [Reference Ono24]). If true, this would yield that the monadic sentences provable in ${\sf Q^\circ S4.t}$ are exactly the bounded formulas $\varphi $ provable in ${\sf MS4.t}$ . It would also yield that restricting the translation ${\sf IQC} \to {\sf Q^\circ S4.t}$ of [Reference Bezhanishvili, Carai, Olivetti, Verbrugge, Negri and Sandu4] to the monadic setting gives the translation $(-)^\flat :{\sf MIPC} \to {\sf MS4.t}$ for bounded formulas.

It is natural to seek an axiomatization of the full monadic fragment of ${\sf Q^\circ S4.t}$ . Note that in this fragment $\forall $ does not behave like an ${\sf S5}$ -modality. For example, $\forall \varphi \to \varphi $ is not in general a theorem of this fragment.

Finally, the translation $(-)^\#: {\sf MS4} \to {\sf MS4.t}$ suggests a translation of ${\sf QS4}$ into ${\sf Q^\circ S4.t}$ which replaces each occurrence of $\Box $ with $\Box _F$ . It is easy to see that for sentences this translation is full and faithful. Composing it with the standard Gödel translation of ${\sf IQC}$ into ${\sf QS4}$ yields a translation ${\sf IQC} \to {\sf Q^\circ S4.t}$ which is different from the translation of [Reference Bezhanishvili, Carai, Olivetti, Verbrugge, Negri and Sandu4]. This translation restricts to the translation $(-)^{t \#}: {\sf MIPC} \to {\sf MS4.t}$ for bounded formulas. Thus, the upper part of the diagram of Section 4 extends to the predicate case.

On the other hand, we do not see a natural way to interpret the tense modalities of ${\sf TS4}$ as monadic quantifiers, and hence we cannot think of a natural predicate logic which could take the role of ${\sf TS4}$ in the diagram of Section 4. Thus, the lower part of the diagram does not seem to have a natural extension to the predicate case. Nevertheless, we can consider the predicate analogue of the translation $(-)^{\natural \dagger }:{\sf MIPC} \to {\sf MS4.t}$ . Arguing as in Theorems 5.2 and 5.4 yields a translation of ${\sf IQC}$ into ${\sf Q^\circ S4.t}$ that is full and faithful on sentences and coincides, up to logical equivalence in ${\sf Q^\circ S4.t}$ , with the other two predicate translations described in this section.

We thus obtain the following diagram in the predicate case which is commutative up to logical equivalence in ${\sf Q^\circ S4.t}$ .

Acknowledgments

We would like to thank Ilya Shapirovsky for simplifying the proofs in Section 3 and for pointing out some references. We would also like to thank the referee for the comments that have improved the presentation of the paper.

Footnotes

1 While [Reference Bezhanishvili, Carai, Olivetti, Verbrugge, Negri and Sandu4] is a sequel to this paper, as it often happens, it appeared in print before this paper.

2 By the monadic fragment of $\mathsf{IQC}$ we mean all the theorems of $\mathsf{IQC}$ containing one fixed variable.

References

BIBLIOGRAPHY

Bass, H. (1958). Finite monadic algebras. Proceedings of the American Mathematical Society, 9, 258268.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bezhanishvili, G. (1998). Varieties of monadic Heyting algebras. I. Studia Logica, 61(3), 367402.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bezhanishvili, G. (1999). Varieties of monadic Heyting algebras. II. Duality theory. Studia Logica, 62(1), 2148.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bezhanishvili, G., & Carai, L. (2020). Temporal interpretation of intuitionistic quantifiers . In Olivetti, N., Verbrugge, R., Negri, S., and Sandu, S., editors. Advances in Modal Logic, Vol. 13. London: College Publications, pp. 95114.Google Scholar
Blackburn, P., de Rijke, M., & Venema, Y. (2001). Modal Logic. Cambridge Tracts in Theoretical Computer Science, Vol. 53. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blok, W. J. (1976). Varieties of Interior Algebras. Ph.D. Thesis, University of Amsterdam.Google Scholar
Bull, R. A. (1965). A modal extension of intuitionist logic. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 6(2), 142146.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bull, R. A. (1966). MIPC as the formalisation of an intuitionist concept of modality. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 31(4), 609616.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chagrov, A., & Zakharyaschev, M. (1997). Modal Logic. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Esakia, L. (1975). The problem of dualism in the intuitionistic logic and Browerian lattices. V Inter. Congress of Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science, pp. 78.Google Scholar
Esakia, L. (1978). Semantical analysis of bimodal (tense) systems. Logic, Semantics and Methodology . Tbilisi: Metsniereba Press, pp. 8799 (in Russian).Google Scholar
Esakia, L. (1988). Provability logic with quantifier modalities. Intensional Logics and Logical Structure of Theories. Tbilisi: Metsniereba Press, pp. 49 (in Russian).Google Scholar
Esakia, L. (2019). Heyting Algebras: Duality Theory . Trends in Logic—Studia Logica Library, Vol. 50. Cham: Springer. Edited by Guram Bezhanishvili and Wesley H. Holliday, Translated from the Russian edition by Anton Evseev.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fischer-Servi, G. (1977). On modal logic with an intuitionistic base. Studia Logica, 36(3), 141149.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fischer-Servi, G. (1978). The finite model property for MIPQ and some consequences. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 19(4), 687692.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gabbay, D. M., Kurucz, A., Wolter, F., & Zakharyaschev, M. (2003). Many-Dimensional Modal Logics: Theory and Applications . Amsterdam: North-Holland.Google Scholar
Gabbay, D. M., & Shehtman, V. B. (1998). Products of modal logics. I. Logic Journal of IGPL, 6(1), 73146.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldblatt, R. (1992). Logics of Time and Computation (second edition). CSLI Lecture Notes, Vol. 7. Stanford: Center for the Study of Language and Information, Stanford University.Google Scholar
Grefe, C. (1998). Fischer Servi’s intuitionistic modal logic has the finite model property. In Kracht, M., de Rijke, M., Wansing, H., and Zakharyaschev, M., editors. Advances in Modal Logic (Berlin, 1996), Vol. 1. CSLI Lecture Notes, 87. Stanford: CSLI Publications, pp. 8598.Google Scholar
Halmos, P. R. (1956). Algebraic logic. I. Monadic Boolean algebras. Compositio Mathematica, 12, 217249.Google Scholar
Jónsson, B., & Tarski, A. (1951). Boolean algebras with operators. I. American Journal of Mathematics, 73, 891939.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McKinsey, J. C. C., & Tarski, A. (1944). The algebra of topology. Annals of Mathematics. Second Series, 45, 141191.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ono, H. (1977). On some intuitionistic modal logics. Publications of the Research Institute for Mathematical Sciences, 13(3), 687722.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ono, H. (1987). Some problems in intermediate predicate logics. Reports on Mathematical Logic, 21, 5567.Google Scholar
Ono, H., & Suzuki, N.-Y. (1988). Relations between intuitionistic modal logics and intermediate predicate logics. Reports on Mathematical Logic, 22, 6587 (1989).Google Scholar
Prior, A. N. (1957). Time and Modality. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Rasiowa, H., & Sikorski, R. (1963). The Mathematics of Metamathematics. Warsaw: Państwowe Wydawnictwo Naukowe.Google Scholar
Rauszer, C. (1973/74). Semi-Boolean algebras and their applications to intuitionistic logic with dual operations. Fundamenta Mathematicae, 83(3), 219249.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Segerberg, K. (1970). Modal logics with linear alternative relations. Theoria, 36, 301322.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thomason, S. K. (1972). Semantic analysis of tense logics. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 37, 150158.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wolter, F. (1998). On logics with coimplication. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 27(4), 353387.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Figure 0

Fig. 1 Diagram of translations.

Figure 1

Fig. 2 Condition (O2).

Figure 2

Fig. 3 Condition (E).