Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-nmvwc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-04T22:42:20.550Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Bibliography

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  29 April 2023

David Machek
Affiliation:
Universität Bern, Switzerland
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2023

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Ackrill, J. L. 1974. ‘Aristotle on Eudaimonia’. In Essays on Aristotle’s Ethics, ed. by Rorty, A. O.. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1534.Google Scholar
Ademollo, F. 2020. ‘Cosmic and Individual Soul in Early Stoicism’. In Body and Soul in Hellenistic Philosophy, ed. by Inwood, B. and Warren, J.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 113144.Google Scholar
Agar, N. 2001. Life’s Intrinsic Value: Science, Ethics, and Nature. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Altman, W. 2011. ‘Reading Order and Authenticity: The Place of Theages and Cleitophon in Platonic Pedagogy’. Plato Journal 11: 150.Google Scholar
Annas, J. 1981. An Introduction to Plato’s Republic. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Annas, J. 1985. ‘Self-Knowledge in Early Plato’. In Platonic Investigations, ed. by O’Meara, D. J.. Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 111137.Google Scholar
Annas, J. 1992. Hellenistic Philosophy of Mind. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Annas, J. 1993. The Morality of Happiness. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Annas, J. 1996. ‘Aristotle and Kant on Morality and Practical Reasoning’. In Aristotle, Kant and the Stoics, ed. by Engstrom, S. and Whiting, J.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 237258.Google Scholar
Annas, J. 1999. Platonic Ethics: Old and New. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Annas, J. and Woolf, R. eds. 2001. Cicero: On Moral Ends. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Arenson, K. 2019. Health and Hedonism in Plato and Epicurus. London and New York: Bloomsbury Press.Google Scholar
Atkins, E. M. and Griffin, M. T. eds. 1991. Cicero: On Duties. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Aubenque, P. 1963. La prudence chez Aristote. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.Google Scholar
Aubry, G. 2014. ‘Metaphysics of Soul and Self in Plotinus’. In The Routledge Handbook of Neoplatonism, ed. by Remes, P. and Slaveva-Griffin, S.. London: Routledge, 310323.Google Scholar
Baier, K. 1988. ‘Threats of Futility: Is Life Worth Living?’ Free Inquiry 8: 4752.Google Scholar
Baier, K. 1997. Problems of life and death. Amherst: Prometheus Books.Google Scholar
Baranzke, H. 2012. ‘“Sanctity-of-Life” – A Bioethical Principle for a Right to Life?’ Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 15: 295308.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barney, R. 2003. ‘A Puzzle in Stoic Ethics’. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 24: 303340.Google Scholar
Barney, R. 2008. ‘Aristotle’s Argument for Human Function’. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 34: 293322.Google Scholar
Barney, R. 2020. ‘Becoming Bad: Aristotle on Vice and Moral Habituation’. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 57: 273308.Google Scholar
Barney, R., Brennan, T. and Brittain, C. eds. 2012. Plato and the Divided Self. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Barry, R. L. 2002. The Sanctity of Human Life and Its Protection. Lanham, MD: University Press of America.Google Scholar
Bayertz, K. ed. 1996. Sanctity of Life and Human Dignity. Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
Benatar, D. 2006. Better Never to Have Been: The Harm of Coming into Existence. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Bénatouil, T. 2013. ‘The Stoic System: Ethics and Nature’. In The Routledge Companion to Ancient Philosophy, ed. by Sheffield, F. and Warren, J.. London: Routledge, 424437.Google Scholar
Betegh, G. 2020. ‘Plato on Illness in the Phaedo, the Republic, and the Timaeus’. In Plato’s Timaeus. Proceedings of the Tenth Symposium Platonicum Pragense, ed. by Jorgenson, C., Karfík, F. and Špinka, Š.. Leiden: Brill, 228258.Google Scholar
Bett, R. 2010. ‘Socratic Ignorance’. In The Cambridge Companion to Socrates, ed. by Morrison, D.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 215236.Google Scholar
Bobonich, C. 2002. Plato’s Utopia Recast: His Later Ethics and Politics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Bonhöffer, A. F. 1996. The Ethics of the Stoic Epictetus, transl. by W. Stephens. New York: Peter Lang.Google Scholar
Bowe, G. S. 2007. ‘In Defense of Clitophon’. Classical Philology 102.3: 245264.Google Scholar
Boys Stones, G. R. 2001. Post-Hellenistic Philosophy: A Study of Its Development from the Stoics to Origen. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bradford, G. 2016. ‘Perfectionism’. In Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Well-Being, ed. by Fletcher, Guy. London and New York: Routledge, 124134.Google Scholar
Bradley, B. 1998. ‘Extrinsic Value’. Philosophical Studies 91: 109126.Google Scholar
Bradley, B. 2002. ‘Is Intrinsic Value Conditional?’ Philosophical Studies 107: 2344.Google Scholar
Bradley, B. 2013. ‘Intrinsic Value’. In International Encyclopedia of Ethics, ed. by Lafollette, H.. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Brennan, T. 2000. ‘Reservation in Stoic Ethics’. Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 82.2: 149177.Google Scholar
Brennan, T. 2005. The Stoic Life: Emotions, Duties, and Fate. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Brisson, L. 2006. ‘The Doctrine of Degrees of Virtue in the Neoplatonists: An Analysis of Porphyry’s Sentence 32, Its Antecedents, and Its Heritage’. In Reading Plato in Antiquity, ed. by Tarrant, H. and Baltzly, D.. London: Duckworth, 89106.Google Scholar
Brisson, L. and Pradeau, J.-F. eds. 2002. Plotin: Traités 1–6. Paris: Flammarion.Google Scholar
Brittain, C. 2003. ‘Attention Deficit in Plotinus and Augustine: Psychological Problems in Christian and Platonist Theories of the Grades of Virtue’. Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 18.1: 223275.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brouwer, R. 2014. The Stoic Sage: The Early Stoics on Wisdom, Sagehood and Socrates. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Brickhouse, T. C. and Smith, N. D. 1989. ‘A Matter of Life and Death in Socratic Philosophy’. Ancient Philosophy 9: 155165.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Broadie, S. 1991. Ethics with Aristotle. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Broadie, S. and Rowe, C. eds. 2002. Aristotle: Nicomachean Ethics: Translation, Introduction and Commentary. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Broome, J. 1985. ‘The Economic Value of Life’. Economica 52: 281294.Google Scholar
Broome, J. 2008. ‘What Is Your Life Worth?’ Daedalus 137: 4956.Google Scholar
Brunschwig, J. 1986. ‘The Cradle Argument in Epicureanism and Stoicism’. In The Norms of Nature: Studies in Hellenistic Ethics, ed. by Schofield, M. and Striker, G.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 113144.Google Scholar
Burnet, J. 1916. ‘The Socratic Doctrine of the Soul’. Proceedings of the British Academy 7: 235259.Google Scholar
Cagnoli Fiecconi, E. 2019. ‘Aristotle’s Peculiarly Human Psychology’. In Aristotle’s Anthropology, ed. by Geert, K. and Kreft, N.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 6076.Google Scholar
Camus, A. 1951. L’Homme révolté. Paris: Gallimard.Google Scholar
Christensen, A. 2017. ‘Better Off Dead: Suicide in Plato’s Philosophy’. PhD dissertation, Washington University in St. Louis.Google Scholar
Christensen, A. 2020. ‘As the God Leads’. Ancient Philosophy 40.2: 267284.Google Scholar
Chroust, A. H. 1966. ‘Eudemus or on the Soul: A Lost Dialogue of Aristotle on the Immortality of the Soul’. Mnemosyne 19: 1730.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ciapalo, R. T. 1987. ‘Life (Zōē´) in Plotinus’ Explanation of Reality’. PhD dissertation, Loyola University Chicago.Google Scholar
Claus, D. 1981. Toward the Soul: An Inquiry into the Meaning of ψυχή before Plato. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Connell, S. 2015. Aristotle on Female Animals. A Study of the Generation of Animals. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Cooper, J. 1989. ‘Greek Philosophers on Euthanasia and Suicide’. In Suicide and Euthanasia: Philosophy and Medicine, ed. by Brody, B. A.. Dordrecht: Springer, 938.Google Scholar
Cooper, J. ed. 1997. Plato: Complete Works. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
Cooper, J. 1999. ‘Pleasure and Desire in Epicurus’. In Reason and Emotion: Essays on Ancient Moral Psychology and Ethical Theory, ed. by Cooper, J.. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 485514.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cooper, J. M. 2012. Pursuits of Wisdom: Six Ways of Life in Ancient Philosophy from Socrates to Plotinus. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Corrigan, K. 2014. ‘Humans, Other Animals, Plants and the Question of the Good: The Platonic and Neoplatonic Traditions’. In The Routledge Handbook of Neoplatonism, ed. by Remes, P. and Slaveva-Griffin, S.. London: Routledge, 372392.Google Scholar
Crisp, R. 2006. Reasons and the Good. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Crisp, R. 2018. ‘Prudential and Moral Reasons’. In The Oxford Handbook of Reasons and Normativity, ed. by Star, D.. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 800820.Google Scholar
Csikszentmihalyi, M. and Csikszentmihalyi, I. S. eds. 2006. A Life Worth Living: Contributions to Positive Psychology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Devereux, D. 2017. ‘Virtue and Happiness in Plato’. In The Cambridge Companion to Ancient Ethics, ed. by Bobonich, C.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 5371.Google Scholar
Dillon, J. 1996. ‘An Ethic for the Late Antique Sage’. In The Cambridge Companion to Plotinus, ed. by Gerson, L.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 315335.Google Scholar
Dimas, P. 2015. ‘Epicurus on Pleasure, Desire, and Friendship’. In The Quest for the Good Life: Ancient Philosophers on Happiness, ed. by Rabbås, Ø., Emilsson, E. K., Fossheim, H. and Tuominen, M.. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 164182.Google Scholar
Echeñique, J. 2021. ‘A Peripatetic Argument for the Intrinsic Goodness of Human Life: Alexander of Aphrodisias’ Ethical Problems I’. Apeiron 54.3: 367384.Google Scholar
Emilsson, K. E. 2017. Plotinus. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Engelhardt, H. T. 1996. ‘Sanctity of Life and Menschenwürde: Can these Concepts Help Direct the Use of Resources in Critical Care?’ In Sanctity of Life and Human Dignity, ed. by Bayertz, K.. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 201219.Google Scholar
Englert, W. 1994. ‘Stoics and Epicureans on the Nature of Suicide’. Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 10.1: 6798.Google Scholar
Fagles, R. transl. 1996. Homer: The Odyssey. London: Penguin.Google Scholar
Fainlight, R. and Littman, R. transl. 2009. Sophocles: The Theban Plays: Oedipus the King, Oedipus at Colonus, Antigone. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
Feldman, F. 1994. Confrontations with the Reaper: A Philosophical Study of the Nature and Value of Death. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Feldman, F. 2006. Pleasure and the Good Life: Concerning the Nature, Varieties and Plausibility of Hedonism. First paperback ed. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Fleet, B. 2012. Plotinus Ennead IV.8: Translation, with an Introduction, and Commentary. Las Vegas: Parmenides Publishing.Google Scholar
Fletcher, G. 2016. The Philosophy of Well-Being: An Introduction. London; New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Foot, P. 1977. ‘Euthanasia’. Philosophy and Public Affairs 6.2: 85112.Google Scholar
Fortenbaugh, W. ed. 2018a. Arius Didymus on Peripatetic Ethics, Household Management, and Politics: Text, Translation, and Discussion. London; New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Fortenbaugh, W. 2018b. ‘Didymus on Types of Life’. In Arius Didymus on Peripatetic Ethics, Household Management, and Politics: Text, Translation, and Discussion, ed. by Fortenbaugh, W.. London; New York: Routledge, 227254.Google Scholar
Frede, M. 1999. ‘On the Stoic Conception of the Good’. In Topics in Stoic Philosophy, ed. by Ierodiakonou, K.. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 7194.Google Scholar
Fumagalli, R. 2018. ‘Eliminating “Life Worth Living”’. Philosophical Studies 175.3: 769792.Google Scholar
Gauthier, R. A. and Jolif, J. Y. 1958–1959. L’Éthique à Nicomaque. Introduction, traduction et commentaire. Louvain: Nauwelaerts.Google Scholar
Gerson, L. 1994. Plotinus. London; New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Gerson, L. ed. 1996. The Cambridge Companion to Plotinus. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Gerson, L. 1997. ‘Socrates’ Absolutist Prohibition of Wrongdoing’. Apeiron 30.4: 111.Google Scholar
Gerson, L. 2013. ‘Platonic Ethics’. In The Oxford Handbook of the History of Ethics, ed. by Crisp, R.. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 129146.Google Scholar
Gerson, L. et al. transl. 2019. Plotinus: The Enneads. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Graeser, A. 1972. Plotinus and the Stoics: A Preliminary Study. Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar
Gill, C. 2006. The Structured Self in Hellenistic and Roman Thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Gill, C. 2013. ‘Cynicism and Stoicism’. In The Oxford Handbook of the History of Ethics, ed. by Crisp, R.. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 93111.Google Scholar
Gill, C. forthcoming. Learning to Live Naturally. Stoic Ethics and Its Modern Significance. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Gomez-Lobo, A. 1989. ‘The Ergon Inference’. Phronesis 34.2: 170184.Google Scholar
Gosling, J. C. B. and Taylor, C. C. W. 1982. The Greeks on Pleasure. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Graver, M. 2015. ‘Honor and the Honorable: Cato’s Discourse in De Finibus 3’. In Cicero’s De Finibus: Philosophical Approaches, ed. by Annas, J. and Betegh, G.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 118146.Google Scholar
Graver, M. and Long, A. A. transl. 2015. Letters on Ethics: To Lucilius. Chicago: Chicago University Press.Google Scholar
Griffin, M. 1986. ‘Philosophy, Cato, and Roman Suicide: I’. Greece & Rome 33.1: 6477.Google Scholar
Grube, G. M. A. 1931. ‘The Cleitophon of Plato’. Classical Philology 26.3: 302308.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hahm, D. 2007. ‘Critolaus and Late Hellenistic Peripatetic Philosophy’. In Pyrrhonists, Patricians, Platonizers: Tenth Symposium Hellenisticum, ed. by Ioppolo, A. M. and Sedley, D.. Naples, 49101.Google Scholar
Harris, J. 1985. The Value of Life. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Hatzimichali, M. 2018. ‘Bodily and External Goods in Relation to Happiness’. In Arius Didymus on Peripatetic Ethics, Household Management, and Politics: Text, Translation, and Discussion, ed. by Fortenbaugh, W.. London; New York: Routledge, 205226.Google Scholar
Haybron, D. M. 2010. The Pursuit of Unhappiness: The Elusive Psychology of Well-Being. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Henry, W. B. ed. 2009. Philodemus: On Death. Atlanta: Society of Biblical Literature.Google Scholar
Holmes, B. 2010. The Symptom and the Subject: The Emergence of the Physical Body in Ancient Greece. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Hurka, T. 2009. Perfectionism. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hursthouse, R. 1999. On Virtue Ethics. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hutchinson, D. S. and Johnson, M. R. 2017. Aristotle: Protrepticus, or Exhortation to Philosophy. Citations, Fragments, Paraphrases, and Other Evidence. Online version at protrepticus.info.Google Scholar
Indelli, G. and Tsouna-McKirahan, V. eds. 1995. Philodemus: On Choices and Avoidances. Naples: Bibliopolis.Google Scholar
Inwood, B. 1985. Ethics and Human Action in Early Stoicism. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Inwood, B. 2005. Reading Seneca: Stoic Philosophy at Rome. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Inwood, B. 2014a. Ethics After Aristotle. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Inwood, B. 2014b. ‘Ancient Goods: The Tria Genera Bonorum in Ethical Theory’. In Strategies of Argument: Essays in Ancient Ethics, Epistemology and Logic, ed. by Lee, M.-K.. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 255280.Google Scholar
Inwood, B. 2017. Stoicism: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Inwood, B. and Gerson, L. 1994. The Epicurus Reader: Selected Writings and Testimonia. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
Inwood, B. and Gerson, L. 2008. The Stoics Reader. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
Ionescu, C. 2019. On the Good Life: Thinking through the Intermediaries in Plato’s Philebus. Albany: SUNY Press.Google Scholar
Irwin, T. 1977. Plato’s Moral Theory: The Early and Middle Dialogues. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Irwin, T. 1991. ‘Aristippus against Happiness’. The Monist 74: 5582.Google Scholar
Irwin, T. 1995. Plato’s Ethics. New York; Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Irwin, T. 1999. Aristotle: Nicomachean Ethics. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
Irwin, T. 2012. ‘Antiochus, Aristotle and the Stoics on Degrees of Happiness’. In The Philosophy of Antiochus, ed. by Sedley, D.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 151172.Google Scholar
James, W. 1895. ‘Is Life Worth Living?’ International Journal of Ethics 6: 124.Google Scholar
Joachim, H. 1951. Aristotle: Nicomachean Ethics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Johansen, T. 2004. Plato’s Natural Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Johnson, M. 2005. Aristotle on Teleology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kagan, S. 1998. ‘Rethinking Intrinsic Value’. The Journal of Ethics 2: 277297.Google Scholar
Kalogiratou, A. 2009. ‘Plotinus’ View on Soul, Suicide and Reincarnation’. ΣΧΟΛΗ 3: 387400.Google Scholar
Kamm, F. M. 2003. ‘Rescuing Ivan Ilych: How We Live and How We Die’. Ethics 113: 202233.Google Scholar
Kamtekar, R. 1998. ‘Imperfect Virtue’. Ancient Philosophy 18: 315339.Google Scholar
Kamtekar, R. 2001. ‘Social Justice and Happiness in the Republic: Plato’s Two Principles’. History of Political Thought 22: 189220.Google Scholar
Kass, L. 2008. ‘Defending Human Dignity’. In Human Dignity and Bioethics, ed. by Pellegrino, E., Schulman, A. and Merrill, T.. Washington, DC: President’s Council on Bioethics, 297332.Google Scholar
Keil, G. and Kreft, N. eds. 2019. Aristotle’s Anthropology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Keown, J. 2002. Euthanasia, Ethics, and Public Policy: An Argument against Legalisation. Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Keyt, D. 2006. ‘Plato on Justice’. In A Companion to Plato, ed. by Benson, H.. Malden: Blackwell, 341355.Google Scholar
Kietzmann, C. 2019. ‘Aristotle on the Definition of What It Is to Be Human’. In Aristotle’s Anthropology, ed. by Keil, G. and Kreft, N.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2543.Google Scholar
Klein, J. 2015. ‘Making Sense of the Stoic Indifferents’. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 49: 227281.Google Scholar
Konstan, D. 2009. ‘Epicurus’. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.Google Scholar
Korsgaard, C. 1983. ‘Two Distinctions in Goodness’. The Philosophical Review 92.2: 169195.Google Scholar
Korsgaard, C. 2008. The Constitution of Agency: Essays on Practical Reason and Moral Psychology. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kraut, R. 1973. ‘Reason and Justice in the Republic’. In Exegesis and Argument: Studies in Greek Philosophy. Presented to Gregory Vlastos, ed. by Lee, E., Mourelatos, A. and Rorty, R.. Phronesis Supplementary Volume, 207224.Google Scholar
Kraut, R. 1984. Socrates and the State. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Kraut, R. 1989. Aristotle on the Human Good. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Kraut, R. 2007. ‘The Examined Life’. In A Companion to Socrates, ed. by Ahbel-Rappe, S. and Kamtekar, R.. Malden: Blackwell, 228242.Google Scholar
Kraut, R. 2009. What Is Good and Why: The Ethics of Well-Being. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Kraut, R. 2010a. ‘What Is Intrinsic Goodness?’ Classical Philology 105.4: 450462.Google Scholar
Kraut, R. 2010b. ‘Ordinary Virtue from the Phaedo to the Laws’. In Plato’s Laws: A Critical Guide, ed. by Bobonich, C.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 5170.Google Scholar
Kremer, M. ed. 2004. Plato’s Cleitophon: On Socrates and the Modern Mind. Lanham: Lexington Books.Google Scholar
Kuhse, H. 1987. The Sanctity of Life Doctrine in Medicine: A Critique. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Kymlicka, W. 1990. Contemporary Political Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lampe, K. 2015. The Birth of Hedonism: The Cyrenaic Philosophers and Pleasure as a Way of Life. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Landau, I. 2017. Finding Meaning in an Imperfect World. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Latham, R. E. and Godwin, J. eds. 1994. Lucretius: On the Nature of the Universe. Penguin Books.Google Scholar
Lear, Richardson G. 2004. Happy Lives and the Highest Good: An Essay on Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Lear, Richardson G. 2006. ‘Aristotle on Moral Virtue and the Fine’. In The Blackwell Guide to Nicomachean Ethics, ed. by Kraut, R.. Blackwell, 116136.Google Scholar
Lear, Richardson G. 2015. ‘Aristotle on Happiness and Long Life’. In The Quest for the Good Life: Ancient Philosophers on Happiness, ed. by Rabbås, Ø., Emilsson, E. K., Fossheim, H. and Tuominen, M.. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 127145.Google Scholar
LeBar, M. 2013. The Value of Living Well. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lee, A. 2022. ‘The Neutrality of Life’. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, on-line first version. https://doi.org/10.1080/00048402.2022.2033284Google Scholar
Lennox, J. 1999. ‘Aristotle on the Biological Roots of Human Virtue’. In Biology and the Foundations of Ethics, ed. by Maienschein, J. and Ruse, M.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1031.Google Scholar
Lennox, J. 2001. Aristotle: On the Parts of Animals I–IV. Translation with an Introduction and Commentary. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Lennox, J. 2010. ‘Bios and Explanatory Unity in Aristotle’s Biology’. In Definition in Greek Philosophy, ed. by Charles, D.. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 329–55.Google Scholar
Lesses, G. 1989. ‘Virtue and the Goods of Fortune in Stoic Moral Theory’. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 7: 95127.Google Scholar
Leunissen, M. 2010. Explanation and Teleology in Aristotle’s Science of Nature. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Leunissen, M. 2017. From Natural Character to Moral Virtue in Aristotle. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Levin, S. 2014. Plato’s Rivalry with Medicine: A Struggle and Its Dissolution. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lewis, C. I. 1955. The Ground and Nature of the Right. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Long, A. A. and Sedley, D. N. 1987. The Hellenistic Philosophers. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Long, A. A. 2015. Greek Models of Mind and Self. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Long, A. G. 2019. Death and Immortality in Ancient Philosophy: Key Themes in Ancient Philosophy. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Lorenz, H. 2003. ‘Ancient Theories of the Soul’. Entry in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/ancient-soul/Google Scholar
Machek, D. 2021. ‘Is the Life of a Mediocre Philosopher Better Than the Life of an Excellent Cobbler? Aristotle on the Value of Activity in Nicomachean Ethics x. 4-8’. The Journal of Value Inquiry. Online-first version. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10790-021-09805-1Google Scholar
Machek, D. 2022. ‘Aristotle on the Goodness of Unhappy Lives’. Journal of the History of Philosophy 60.3: 359383.Google Scholar
Matheson, D. 2020. ‘The Worthwhileness of Meaningful Lives’. Philosophia 48.1: 313324.Google Scholar
McMahan, J. 2002. The Ethics of Killing: Problems at the Margins of Life. Oxford Ethics Series. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Matson, W. 1998. ‘Hegesias the Death-Persuader; or, the Gloominess of Hedonism’. Philosophy 73: 553558.Google Scholar
McCabe, M. M. 2015. Platonic Conversations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
McGroarty, K. 2006. Plotinus on Eudaimonia: A Commentary on Ennead I 4. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mensch, P. and Miller, J. eds. 2018. Diogenes Laertius. Lives of the Eminent Philosophers. Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Metz, T. 2012. ‘The Meaningful and the Worthwhile: Clarifying the Relationships’. The Philosophical Forum 43: 435448.Google Scholar
Metz, T. 2014. ‘Life Worth Living’. In Encyclopedia of Quality of Life and Well-Being Research, ed. by Michalos, A. C.. Dordrecht: Springer, 36023605.Google Scholar
Meyer, S. S. 2008. Ancient Ethics: A Critical Introduction. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Michael of Ephesus. 2001. On Aristotle Nicomachean Ethics 9. In Aspasius, Michael of Ephesus, Anonymous: On Aristotle Nicomachean Ethics 8–9, transl. D. Konstan. London, New York: Bloomsbury, 131232.Google Scholar
Mitsis, P. 1988. Epicurus’ Ethical Theory: The Pleasures of Invulnerability. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Moraux, P. 1973. Der Aristotelismus bei den Griechen. Von Andronikos bis Alexander von Aphrodisias. Berlin: De Gruyter.Google Scholar
Morrison, D. 1987. ‘The Evidence for Degrees of Being in Aristotle’. The Classical Quarterly 37: 382401.Google Scholar
Nagel, T. 1970. ‘Death’. Noûs 4.1: 7380.Google Scholar
Nagel, T. 1971. ‘The Absurd’. The Journal of Philosophy 68.20: 716727.Google Scholar
Narbonne, J.-M. 2014. ‘Matter and Evil in the Neoplatonic Tradition’. In The Routledge Handbook of Neoplatonism, ed. by Remes, P. and Slaveva-Griffin, S.. London: Routledge, 231244.Google Scholar
Natali, C. 2009. ‘Nicomachean Ethics VII, 1148b15–1150a8: Beastliness, Irascibility, Akrasia’. In Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. Book VII, ed. by Natali, C.. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 103129.Google Scholar
Nehamas, A. and Woodruff, P. 1989. Symposium: Translated with Introduction & Notes. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
Nikolsky, B. 2001. ‘Epicurus on Pleasure’. Phronesis 46.4: 440465.Google Scholar
Nozick, R. 1974. Anarchy, State, and Utopia. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Nozick, R. 1989. The Examined Life: Philosophical Meditations. New York: Simon & Schuster.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, M. 1972. ‘ΨΥΧΗ in Heraclitus I’. Phronesis 17.1: 116.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, M. 1986. The Fragility of Goodness. Chicago: Chicago University Press.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, M. 1995. ‘Aristotle on Human Nature and the Foundations of Ethics’. In World, Mind and Ethics: Essays on the Ethical Philosophy of Bernard Williams, ed. by Altham, J. and Harrison, R.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 86131.Google Scholar
O’Keefe, T. 2001. ‘Is Epicurean Friendship Altruistic?’ Apeiron 34: 269305.Google Scholar
O’Meara, D. 1993. Plotinus: An Introduction to the Enneads. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
O’Meara, D. 2003. Platonopolis: Platonic Political Philosophy in Late Antiquity. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
O’Meara, D. 2005. ‘The Metaphysics of Evil in Plotinus: Problems and Solutions’. In Essays in Honour of D. O’Brien, ed. by Dillon, J. M. and Dixsaut, M.. Aldershot: Ashgate, 179185.Google Scholar
O’Reilly, K. 2019. ‘The Jellyfish’s Pleasures in Philebus 20b-21d’. Phronesis 64.3: 277291.Google Scholar
Orwin, C. 2004. ‘On the Cleitophon’. In Plato’s Cleitophon: On Socrates and the Modern Mind, ed. by Kremer, M.. Lanham: Lexington Books, 5970.Google Scholar
Osborne, C. 2007. Dumb Beasts and Dead Philosophers: Humanity and the Humane in Ancient Philosophy and Literature. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Owen, G. E. L. 1960. ‘Logic and metaphysics in some earlier works of Aristotle’. In Aristotle and Plato in the mid-fourth century, ed. by Düring, I. and Owen, G. E. L.. Göteborg: Almquist & Wiksell, 163–90.Google Scholar
Pakaluk, M. 2008. Aristotle: Nicomachean Ethics: Books VIII and XI. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Papadimitriou, J. D. et al. 2007. ‘Euthanasia and Suicide in Antiquity: Viewpoint of the Dramatists and Philosophers’. Journal of the Royal Society of Medicine 100.1: 2528.Google Scholar
Parfit, D. 1984. Reasons and Persons. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Purinton, J. 1993. ‘Epicurus on the Telos’. Phronesis 38.3: 281320.Google Scholar
Rabbås, Ø. 2015. ‘Eudaimonia, Human Nature, and Normativity. Reflections on Aristotle’s Project in Nicomachean Ethics Book I’. In The Quest for the Good Life: Ancient Philosophers on Happiness, ed. by Rabbås, Ø., Emilsson, E. K., Fossheim, H. and Tuominen, M.. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 88112.Google Scholar
Rabbås, Ø., Emilsson, E. K., Fossheim, H. and Tuominen, M. eds. 2015. The Quest for the Good Life: Ancient Philosophers on Happiness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Rachels, J. 1986. The End of Life. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Rackham, H. transl. 1932. Aristotle: Politics. Loeb Classical Library 264. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. 1999. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Raz, J. 2001. Value, Respect, and Attachment: John Robert Seeley Lectures. Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Remes, P. 2008. Neoplatonism. Stocksfield: Acumen.Google Scholar
Remes, P. and Slaveva-Griffin, S. eds. 2014. The Routledge Handbook of Neoplatonism. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Remes, P. and Sihvola, J. eds. 2008. Ancient Philosophy of the Self. Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
Reeve, C. 1998. Aristotle: Politics. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
Reydams-Schils, G. 2005. The Roman Stoics. Chicago: Chicago University Press.Google Scholar
Rider, B. 2020. ‘Epicureans on Pleasure, Desire and Happiness’. In The Routledge Handbook of Hellenistic Philosophy, ed. by Arenson, K.. London: Routledge, 295306.Google Scholar
Rist, J. 1967. Plotinus: The Road to Reality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Rist, J. 1969. Stoic Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Rist, J. 1983. Human Value: A Study in Ancient Philosophical Ethics. Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar
Roochnik, D. 2004. ‘The Riddle of the Cleitophon’. In Plato’ Cleitophon: On Socrates and the Modern Mind, ed. by Kremer, M.. Lanham: Lexington Books, 4358.Google Scholar
Rosenbaum, S. 1990. ‘Epicurus on Pleasure and the Complete Life’. The Monist 73: 2141.Google Scholar
Russell, D. 2012. Happiness for Humans. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Santas, G. 2010. Understanding Plato’s Republic. Malden: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Schniewind, A. 2003. L’éthique du sage chez Plotin. Le paradigm du spoudaios. Paris: Vrin.Google Scholar
Schniewind, A. 2015. ‘Plotinus’ Way of Defining “Eudaimonia” in Ennead I 4 [46] 1–3’. In The Quest for the Good Life: Ancient Philosophers on Happiness, ed. by Rabbås, Ø., Emilsson, E. K., Fossheim, H. and Tuominen, M.. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 212221.Google Scholar
Schofield, M. 1991. The Stoic Idea of the City. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Sedley, D. 1991. ‘Is Aristotle’s Teleology Anthropocentric?’ Phronesis 36.2: 179196.Google Scholar
Sedley, D. 2017. ‘Epicurean versus Cyrenaic Happiness’. In Selfhood and the Soul: Essays on Ancient Thought and Literature in Honour of Christopher Gill, ed. by Seaford, R., Wilkins, J. and Wright, M.. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 89106.Google Scholar
Segev, M. 2022. ‘Death, Immortality, and the Value of Human Existence in Aristotle’s Eudemus Fragment 6 Ross.’ Classical Philology 117.3: 438461.Google Scholar
Seidler, M. J. 1983. ‘Kant and the Stoics on Suicide’. Journal of the History of Ideas 44.3: 429453.Google Scholar
Sellars, J. 2006. Stoicism. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Sharples, R. 2007. ‘Peripatetics on Happiness’. In Greek and Roman Philosophy 100BC–200AD, Volume 2, ed. by Sharples, R. and Sorabji, R.. London: Institute of Classical Studies, University of London, 627637.Google Scholar
Sharples, R. 2010. Peripatetic Philosophy 200 BC to AD 200: An Introduction and Collection of Sources in Translation. Cambridge Source Books in Post-Hellenistic Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Sheffield, F. 2018. ‘Plato on Virtue and the Good Life’. In The Routledge Companion to Ancient Philosophy, ed. by Warren, J. and Sheffield, F.. London: Routledge, 471501.Google Scholar
Simpson, P. 2017. transl. The Great Ethics of Aristotle. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Singer, P. 1995. Rethinking Life and Death: The Collapse of Our Traditional Ethics. New York: St. Martin’s Press.Google Scholar
Singer, P. 1993. Practical Ethics (2nd ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Slings, S. 1999. Plato: Clitophon. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Smith, N.Return to the Cave’. In Plato’s Republic. A Critical Guide, ed. by McPherran, M.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 83102.Google Scholar
Smuts, A. 2014. ‘To Be or Never to Have Been: Anti-Natalism and a Life Worth Living’. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 17.4: 711729.Google Scholar
Snell, B. 1946. Die Entdeckung des Geistes. Studien zur Entstehung des europäischen Denkens bei den Griechen. Hamburg: Claassen & Goverts.Google Scholar
Song, E. 2013. ‘Ashamed of Being in the Body? Plotinus versus Porphyry’. In Plato Revived: Essays on Ancient Platonism in Honour of Dominic J. O’Meara, ed. by Karfík, F. and Song, E.. Berlin; Boston: De Gruyter, 96116.Google Scholar
Sorabji, R. 1993. Animal Minds and Human Morals: The Origins of the Western Debate. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Sorabji, R. 2006. Self: Ancient and Modern Insights about Individuality, Life and Death. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Stern-Gillet, S. 2013. ‘When Virtue Bids Us Abandon Life. (Ennead VI 8 [39] 6, 14–26).’ In Plato Revived: Essays on Ancient Platonism in Honour of Dominic J. O’Meara, ed. by Karfík, F. and Song, E.. Berlin; Boston: De Gruyter, 182198.Google Scholar
Stern-Gillet, S. 2014. ‘Plotinus on Metaphysics and Morality’. In The Routledge Handbook of Neoplatonism, ed. by Remes, P. and Slaveva-Griffin, S.. London: Routledge, 396420.Google Scholar
Striker, G. 1996. ‘Antipater, or the Art of Living’. In Essays on Hellenistic Epistemology and Ethics ed. by Striker, G.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 185204.Google Scholar
Strycker, E. de. 1968. ‘Prédicats univoques et prédicats analogiques dans le Protreptique d’Aristote’. Revue Philosophique de Louvain 66: 597618.Google Scholar
Sumner, L. W. 1996. Welfare, Happiness, and Ethics. Oxford and New York: Clarendon Press and Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Szaif, J. 2012. Gut des Menschen. Untersuchungen zur Problematik und Entwicklung der Glücksethik bei Aristoteles und in der Tradition des Peripatos. Berlin; Boston: De Gruyter.Google Scholar
Szaif, J. 2018. ‘Two Conceptions of “Primary Acts of Virtue” in Doxography C’. In Arius Didymus on Peripatetic Ethics, Household Management, and Politics: Text, Translation, and Discussion, ed. by Fortenbaugh, W.. London; New York: Routledge, 161203.Google Scholar
Taylor, C. 1989. Sources of the Self: The Making of the Modern Identity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Taylor, P. 1986. Respect for Nature: A Theory of Environmental Ethics. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Tiberius, V. 2014. ‘Well-Being, Philosophical Theories Of’. In Encyclopedia of Quality of Life and Well-Being Research, ed. by Michalos, A.. Dordrecht: Springer, 71107113.Google Scholar
Torres, J. 2020. ‘Plato’s Medicalisation of Ethics’. Apeiron: A Journal for Ancient Philosophy and Science 54.3: 287316.Google Scholar
Torres, J. 2021. ‘Plato’s Anthropocentrism Reconsidered’. Environmental Ethics 43.2: 119141.Google Scholar
Trisel, B. 2007. ‘Judging Life and Its Value’. Sorites 18: 6075.Google Scholar
Tsouna, V. 2002. ‘Is There an Exception to Greek Eudaimonism?’ In Le style de la pensée. Mélanges J. Brunschwig, ed. by Canto, M. and Pellegrin, P.. Paris: Les Belles Lettres, 464489.Google Scholar
Tsouna, V. 2007. The Ethics of Philodemus. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Tsouna, V. 2020. ‘Hedonism’. In Oxford Handbook of Epicurus and Epicureanism, ed. by Mitsis, P.. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 141188.Google Scholar
Tsouni, G. 2017. ‘Didymus’ Outline of Peripatetic Ethics, Household Management and Politics: An Edition with Translation’. In Arius Didymus on Peripatetic Ethics, Household Management, and Politics: Text, Translation, and Discussion, ed. by Fortenbaugh, W.. London; New York: Routledge, 167.Google Scholar
Tsouni, G. 2019. Antiochus and Peripatetic Ethics. Cambridge Classical Studies. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Velleman, D. 1991. ‘Well-being and time’. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 72: 4877.Google Scholar
Visnjic, J. 2021. The Invention of Duty: Stoicism as Deontology. Philosophia Antiqua 157. Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar
Vlastos, G. 1978. ‘Justice and Happiness in the Republic’. In Plato: A Collection of Critical Essays vol. 2, ed. by Vlastos, G., Notre Dame: Notre Dame University Press, 6695.Google Scholar
Vlastos, G. 1985. ‘Happiness and Virtue in Socrates’ Moral Theory’. Topoi 4: 322.Google Scholar
Vlastos, G. 1991. Socrates: Ironist and Moral Philosopher. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Vogt, K. 2014Taking the Same Things Seriously and Not Seriously: A Stoic Proposal on Value and the Good’. In Epictetus: His Continuing Influence and Contemporary Relevance, ed. by Gordon, D. R. and Suits, D. B.. RIT Press, 5576.Google Scholar
Wallis, R. T. 1972. Neoplatonism. London: Duckworth.Google Scholar
Warren, J. 2001. ‘Socratic Suicide’. The Journal of Hellenic Studies 121: 91106.Google Scholar
Warren, J. 2002. Epicurus and Democritean Ethics: An Archaeology of Ataraxia. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Warren, J. 2004. Facing Death: Epicurus and His Critics. Oxford and New York: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Warren, J. 2014. The Pleasures of Reason in Plato, Aristotle, and the Hellenistic Hedonists. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Warren, J. 2018. ‘The Cyrenaics’. In The Routledge Companion to Ancient Philosophy, ed. by Warren, J. and Sheffield, F.. London: Routledge, 9741006.Google Scholar
Werner, D. 2018. ‘Suicide in the Phaedo’. Rhizomata 6.2: 157188.Google Scholar
White, S. 2002. ‘Happiness in the Hellenistic Lyceum’. Apeiron, suppl. 35: 6993.Google Scholar
Wilkinson, D. 2011. ‘A Life Worth Giving? The Threshold for Permissible Withdrawal of Life Support from Disabled Newborn Infants’. The American Journal of Bioethics 11.2: 2032.Google Scholar
Williams, B. 1973. ‘The Makropulos Case: Reflections on the Tedium of Immortality’. In Problems of the Self, ed. by Williams, B.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 82100.Google Scholar
Williams, B. 1985. Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Williams, B. 1993. Shame and Necessity. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Wolf, S. 2015. The Variety of Values: Essays on Morality, Meaning, and Love. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Wolfsdorf, D. 2013. Pleasure in Ancient Greek Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Woods, M. 1982. Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics: Books I, II and VIII. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Woolf, R. 2009. ‘Pleasure and Desire’. In The Cambridge Companion to Epicureanism, ed. by Warren, J.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 158178.Google Scholar
Zavaliy, A. 2019. ‘Cowardice and Injustice. The Problem of Suicide in Aristotle’s Ethics’. History of Philosophy Quarterly 36.4: 319336.Google Scholar
Zillioli, U. 2012. The Cyrenaics. London: Routledge.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Bibliography
  • David Machek, Universität Bern, Switzerland
  • Book: The Life Worth Living in Ancient Greek and Roman Philosophy
  • Online publication: 29 April 2023
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009257916.009
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Bibliography
  • David Machek, Universität Bern, Switzerland
  • Book: The Life Worth Living in Ancient Greek and Roman Philosophy
  • Online publication: 29 April 2023
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009257916.009
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Bibliography
  • David Machek, Universität Bern, Switzerland
  • Book: The Life Worth Living in Ancient Greek and Roman Philosophy
  • Online publication: 29 April 2023
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009257916.009
Available formats
×