Book contents
- Frontmatter
- Contents
- Acknowledgements
- Miscellaneous Frontmatter
- Abbreviations
- Table of cases
- Table of statutes and other public documents
- Part I General introduction
- Part II Regulatory prudence and precaution
- 5 Regulatory prudence I: health, safety and environment: GM crops, nanoparticles and sound science
- 6 Regulatory prudence II: precaution
- Part III Regulatory legitimacy
- 8 Key boundary-marking concepts
- 9 Human rights as boundary markers
- 10 A look at procedural legitimacy: the role of public participation in technology regulation
- Part IV Regulatory effectiveness
- Part V Regulatory connection
- Concluding overview
- Index
- References
6 - Regulatory prudence II: precaution
from Part II - Regulatory prudence and precaution
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 05 August 2012
- Frontmatter
- Contents
- Acknowledgements
- Miscellaneous Frontmatter
- Abbreviations
- Table of cases
- Table of statutes and other public documents
- Part I General introduction
- Part II Regulatory prudence and precaution
- 5 Regulatory prudence I: health, safety and environment: GM crops, nanoparticles and sound science
- 6 Regulatory prudence II: precaution
- Part III Regulatory legitimacy
- 8 Key boundary-marking concepts
- 9 Human rights as boundary markers
- 10 A look at procedural legitimacy: the role of public participation in technology regulation
- Part IV Regulatory effectiveness
- Part V Regulatory connection
- Concluding overview
- Index
- References
Summary
Introduction
According to Elizabeth Fisher, Judith Jones and René von Schomberg:
At its most basic, the precautionary principle is a principle of public decision making that requires decision makers in cases where there are ‘threats’ of environmental or health harm not to use ‘lack of full scientific certainty’ as a reason for not taking measures to prevent such harm.
Significantly, the principle can be viewed as representing ‘a departure from the previous state of affairs where political actors could use or abuse a persistent dissent among scientists as a reason (or excuse) for not taking action at all’.
In line with this principle, and possibly as its most celebrated articulation, Principle 15 of the Rio Declaration in 1992 enjoins states to take measures to prevent serious and irreversible damage to the environment even if there is a ‘lack of full scientific certainty’. In other words, even if there is some doubt about whether, say, carbon emissions cause serious and irreversible climate change, at the very least, lack of clinching evidence should not stand in the way of preventive measures and, at strongest, preventive measures should be taken. Similarly, in a health care context, it might be urged that, even if there is some doubt about whether smoking tobacco causes lung cancer and heart disease, this should not bar the taking of preventive measures. As the Appellate Body at the WTO remarked in the Hormones dispute, ‘responsible, representative governments commonly act from perspectives of prudence and precaution where risks of irreversible, e.g., life-terminating, damage to human health are concerned’. Although the Rio Declaration qualifies the protective obligation by limiting it to the capabilities of particular states, and even though the nature of the measures to be taken is unspecified, the precautionary principle has attracted a huge amount of criticism.
- Type
- Chapter
- Information
- Law and the Technologies of the Twenty-First CenturyText and Materials, pp. 137 - 166Publisher: Cambridge University PressPrint publication year: 2012