Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-r5fsc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-26T01:07:28.241Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Bibliography

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 January 2024

K. Brad Wray
Affiliation:
Aarhus Universitet, Denmark
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2024

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Abbott, Andrew (2001). The Chaos of Disciplines. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Abbott, Andrew (2016). “Structure as Cited, Structure as Read.” In Richards, Robert J. and Daston, Lorraine (eds.), Kuhn’s Structure of Scientific Revolutions at Fifty: Reflections on a Science Classic, pp. 167181. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Abramo, G., D’Angelo, C. A., and Di Costa, F. (2012). “Identifying Interdisciplinarity through the Disciplinary Classification of Coauthors of Scientific Publications.” Journal of the American Society for Information Science and Technology 63, 11: 22062222.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Adler, K. (2013). “The History of Science as Oxymoron: From Scientific Exceptionalism to Episcience.” Isis 104, 1: 88101.Google Scholar
Andersen, Hanne (2000). “Learning by Ostension: Thomas Kuhn on Science Education.” Science and Education 9: 91106.Google Scholar
Andersen, Hanne (2001a). “Critical Notice: Kuhn, Conant and Everything – A Full or Fuller Account.” Philosophy of Science 68, 2: 258262.Google Scholar
Andersen, Hanne (2001b). On Kuhn. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth/Thomson.Google Scholar
Andersen, Hanne (2010). “Joint Acceptance and Scientific Change: A Case Study.” Episteme 7, 3: 248265.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Andersen, Hanne (2013). “The Second Essential Tension: On Tradition and Innovation in Interdisciplinary Research.” Topoi 32, 1: 38.Google Scholar
Andersen, Hanne (2014). “Co-Author Responsibility: Distinguishing between the Moral and Epistemic Aspects of Trust.” EMBO Reports 15: 915918.Google Scholar
Andersen, Hanne, Barker, Peter, and Chen, Xiang (2006). The Cognitive Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Andersen, Line E. (2017). “Outsiders Enabling Scientific Change: Learning from the Sociohistory of a Mathematical Proof.” Social Epistemology 31, 2: 184191.Google Scholar
Arabatzis, T. (2006). “On the Inextricability of the Context of Discovery and the Context of Justification.” In Schickore, J. and Steinle, F. (eds.), Revisiting Discovery and Justification, pp. 215230. Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
Barber, Bernard (1963). “Review of The Structure of Scientific Revolutions.” American Sociological Review 28, 2: 298299.Google Scholar
Barnes, S. Barry (1974). Scientific Knowledge and Sociological Theory. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Barnes, S. Barry (1977). Interests and the Growth of Knowledge. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Barnes, S. Barry (1982a). T. S. Kuhn and Social Science. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Barnes, S. Barry (1982b). “On the Implications of a Body of Knowledge.” Science Communication 4, 1: 95110.Google Scholar
Barnes, S. Barry (2011). “Relativism as a Completion of the Scientific Project.” In Schantz, R. and Seidel, M. (eds.), The Problem of Relativism in the Sociology of (Scientific) Knowledge, pp. 2339. Frankfurt: Ontos.Google Scholar
Barnes, S. Barry, and Bloor, David (1982). “Relativism, Rationalism and the Sociology of Knowledge.” In Hollis, M. and Lukes, S. (eds.), Rationality and Relativism, pp. 2147. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Barnes, S. Barry, Bloor, David, and Henry, J. (1996). Scientific Knowledge: A Sociological Analysis. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Barnes, S. Barry, and Dolby, R. G. A. (1970). “The Scientific Ethos: A Deviant Viewpoint.” European Journal of Sociology 11, 1: 325.Google Scholar
Bell, Randy, Abd-El-Khalick, Fouad, Lederman, Normal G., McComas, William F., and Matthews, Michael R. (2001). “The Nature of Science and Science Education: A Bibliography.” Science and Education 10: 187204.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bellos, David (2012). Is That a Fish in Your Ear? Translation and the Meaning of Everything. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux.Google Scholar
Ben-David, J. (1978). “Emergence of National Traditions in the Sociology of Science.” Sociological Inquiry 48, 3–4: 197218.Google Scholar
Bernal, John Desmond (1939). The Social Function of Science. London: George Routledge and Sons.Google Scholar
Bhopal, Raj. (1999). “Paradigms in Epidemiology Textbooks: In the Footsteps of Thomas Kuhn.” American Journal of Public Health 89, 8: 11621165.Google Scholar
Biagioli, Mario (1990). “Galileo’s System of Patronage.” History of Science 28, 1: 162.Google Scholar
Biagioli, Mario (1993). Galileo, Courtier: The Practice of Science in the Culture of Absolutism. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Biagioli, Mario (2012). “Productive Illusions: Kuhn’s Structure as a Recruitment Tool.” Historical Studies in the Natural Sciences 42, 5: 479484.Google Scholar
Bierman, Paul. (2006) “Reconsidering the Textbook.” Science Education Resource Center at Carleton College. Last revised 2006. Accessed November 1, 2022. http://serc.carleton.edu/files/textbook.Google Scholar
Binns, Ian C. (2013) “A Qualitative Method to Determine How Textbooks Portray Scientific Methodology.” In Khine, Myint Swe (ed.), Critical Analysis of Science Textbooks: Evaluating Instructional Effectiveness, pp. 239258. New York: Springer.Google Scholar
Bird, Alexander J. (2000a). Thomas Kuhn. Chesham: Acumen.Google Scholar
Bird, Alexander J. (2000b). Thomas Kuhn. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Bird, Alexander J. (2002). “Kuhn’s Wrong Turning.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 33, 3: 443463.Google Scholar
Bird, Alexander J. (2004). “Kuhn, Naturalism, and the Positivist Legacy.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 35, 2: 337356.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bird, Alexander J. (2010). “Social Knowing: The Social Sense of ‘Scientific Knowledge.’Philosophical Perspectives 24: 2356.Google Scholar
Bird, Alexander J. (2012a). “Kuhn, Naturalism, and the Social Study of Science.” In Kindi, V. and Arabatzis, T. (eds.), Kuhn’s The Structure of Scientific Revolutions Revisited, pp. 205230. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Bird, Alexander J. (2012b). “The Structure of Scientific Revolutions and Its Significance: An Essay Review of the Fiftieth Anniversary Edition.” British Journal of the Philosophy of Science 63: 859883.Google Scholar
Bird, Alexander J. (2014). “When Is There a Group That Knows? Distributed Cognition, Scientific Knowledge, and the Social Epistemic Subject.” In Lackey, Jennifer (ed.), Essays in Collective Epistemology, pp. 4263. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bird, Alexander J. (2015). “Kuhn and the Historiography of Science.” In Devlin, W. J. and Bokulich, A. (eds.), Kuhn’s Structure of Scientific Revolutions – 50 Years On, pp. 2328. Cham: Springer.Google Scholar
Birge, Raymond Thayer (1929). “Probable Values of the General Physical Constants.” Reviews of Modern Physics 1, 1: 173.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Birge, Raymond Thayer (1932). “The Calculation of Errors by the Method of Least SquaresPhysical Review 40: 207227.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Birge, Raymond Thayer (1941). “The General Physical Constants: As of August 1941 with Details on the Velocity of Light Only.” Reports on Progress in Physics 8, 1: 90134.Google Scholar
Birge, Raymond Thayer (1943). “Comments on ‘The Probable Accuracy of the General Physical Constants.’Physical Review 63, 5–6: 213.Google Scholar
Birge, Raymond Thayer (1957). “A Survey of the Systematic Evaluation of the Universal Physical Constants.” Il Nuovo Cimento 6, S1: 3967.Google Scholar
Bloom, Harold (1973). The Anxiety of Influence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bloor, David (1973). “Wittgenstein and Mannheim on the Sociology of Mathematics.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 4, 2: 173191.Google Scholar
Bloor, David (1976/1991). Knowledge and Social Imagery. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Bloor, David (1983a). “Relativism (methodological).” In Bynum, W. F. et al. (eds.), Macmillan Dictionary of the History of Science, p. 369. London: Macmillan Press.Google Scholar
Bloor, David (1983b). Wittgenstein: A Sociological Theory of Knowledge. London: Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bloor, David (1984). “The Sociology of Reasons: Or Why ‘Epistemic Factors’ Are Really ‘Social Factors.’” In Brown, J. R. (ed.), Scientific Rationality: The Sociological Turn, pp. 295324. Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar
Bloor, David (2004). “Sociology of Scientific Knowledge.” In Niiniluoto, I. et al. (eds.), Handbook of Epistemology, pp. 919962. Dordrecht: Kluwer.Google Scholar
Bloor, David (2007). “Epistemic Grace: Antirelativism as Theology in Disguise.” Common Knowledge 13, 2–3: 250280.Google Scholar
Bloor, David (2011). “Relativism and the Sociology of Scientific Knowledge.” In Hales, D. (ed.), A Companion to Relativism, pp. 433455. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Bloor, David (2017). Interview with David Bloor, by R. McKenna, A.-K. Koch, and N. Ashton. https://emergenceofrelativism.weebly.com/blog/interview-with-david-bloor.Google Scholar
Boas Hall, M. (1963). “Review of The Structure of Scientific Revolutions.” The American Historical Review 68, 3: 700701.Google Scholar
Bodenmann, S. (2010). “The 18th-Century Battle over Lunar Motion.” Physics Today 63, 1: 2732.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bohm, D. (1964). “Review of The Structure of Scientific Revolutions.” The Philosophical Review 14, 57: 377379.Google Scholar
Bokulich, Alisa (2020a). “Towards a Taxonomy of the Model-Ladenness of Data.” Philosophy of Science 87, 5: 793806.Google Scholar
Bokulich, Alisa (2020b). “Calibration, Coherence, and Consilience in Radiometric Measures of Geologic Time.” Philosophy of Science 87, 3: 425456.Google Scholar
Bokulich, Alisa, and Parker, William (2021). “Data Models, Representation and Adequacy-for-Purpose.” European Journal for Philosophy of Science 11, 1: 31.Google Scholar
Boyd, Richard (1979). “Metaphor and Theory Change: What Is ‘Metaphor’ a Metaphor For?” In Ortony, Andrew (ed.), Metaphor and Thought, pp. 481532. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Bratman, M. E. (1992). “Shared Cooperative Activity.” Philosophical Review 101, 2: 327341.Google Scholar
Briatte, F. (2007) “Entretien avec David Bloor.” Tracés: Revue de Sciences Humaine 12: 215228.Google Scholar
Brown, Matthew J., and Kidd, Ian James (2016). “Introduction: Reappraising Paul Feyerabend.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 57: 18.Google Scholar
Brush, Stephen G. (1974). “Should the History of Science Be Rated X?Science 183, 4230 (March 22): 11641172.Google Scholar
Brush, Stephen G. (2000). “Thomas Kuhn as a Historian of Science.” Science and Education 9: 3958.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buchwald, Jed Z., and Smith, George E. (1997). “Thomas S. Kuhn, 1922–1996.Philosophy of Science 64, 2: 361376.Google Scholar
Burian, Richard M. (2001). “The Dilemma of Case Studies Resolved: The Virtue of Using Case Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science.” Perspectives on Science 9, 4: 383404.Google Scholar
Bush, Vannevar (1945). Science: The Endless Frontier: A Report to the President. Washington, DC: US Government Printing Office.Google Scholar
Caneva, Kenneth L. (2000). “Possible Kuhns in the History of Science: Anomalies of Incommensurable Paradigms.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 31, 1: 87124.Google Scholar
Carnap, Rudolf (1932/1987). “On Protocol Sentences,” trans. Richard Creath and Richard Nollan. Nous 21: 457470.Google Scholar
Carnap, Rudolf (1934/1937). The Logical Syntax of Language, trans. Amethe Smeaton. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Carnap, Rudolf (1935). Philosophy and Logical Syntax. London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner.Google Scholar
Carnap, Rudolf (1936). “Testability and Meaning.” Philosophy of Science 3, 4: 419471.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carnap, Rudolf (1937). “Testability and Meaning – Continued.” Philosophy of Science 4, 1: 140.Google Scholar
Carnap, Rudolf (1956). “The Methodological Character of Theoretical Concepts.” In Feigl, Herbert and Scriven, Michael (eds.), The Foundations of Science and the Concepts of Psychology and Psychoanalysis, pp. 3878. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Carnap, Rudolf (1966). Philosophical Foundations of Physics: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Science, ed. Gardner, Martin. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Carrier, M. (2008). “The Aim and Structure of Methodological Theory.” In Soler, L. et al. (eds.), Rethinking Scientific Change and Theory Comparison: Stabilities, Ruptures, Incommensurabilities?, pp. 273290. Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
Cartwright, Nancy (1983). How the Laws of Physics Lie. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Cartwright, Nancy (1999). The Dappled World: A Study of the Boundaries of Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Cat, Jordi (2022). “The Unity of Science.” In Edward N. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2022 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2022/entries/scientific-unity.Google Scholar
Cavell, Stanley (2010). Little Did I Know: Excerpts from Memory. Palo Alto, CA: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Cedarbaum, D. G. (1983). “Paradigms.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 14, 3: 173213.Google Scholar
Chang, Hasok (2004). Inventing Temperature: Measurement and Scientific Progress. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Chang, Hasok (2012a). Is Water H2O? Evidence, Realism and Pluralism. Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
Chang, Hasok (2012b). “Incommensurability: Revisiting the Chemical Revolution.” In Kindi, Vasso and Arabatzis, Theodore (eds.), Kuhn’s Structure of Scientific Revolutions Revisited, pp. 153176. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Chu, J. S., and Evans, J. A. (2021). “Slowed Canonical Progress in Large Fields of Science.” PNAS 118, 41: e2021636118.Google Scholar
Cohen, E. Richard, Crowe, Kenneth M., and DuMond, Jesse W. (1957). The Fundamental Constants of Physics, vol. 1. New York: Interscience Publishers.Google Scholar
Cohen, E. Richard, and DuMond, Jesse W. (1957). “The Fundamental Constants of Atomic Physics.” In Richard Cohen, E., Crowe, Kenneth M., and DuMond, Jesse W. M. (eds.), Atoms I/Atome I, pp. 187. Berlin: Springer.Google Scholar
Cohen, E. Richard, and DuMond, Jesse W. (1965). “Our Knowledge of the Fundamental Constants of Physics and Chemistry in 1965.” Reviews of Modern Physics 37, 4: 537594.Google Scholar
Cohen, I. B. (1980). The Newtonian Revolution. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Collin, F. (2011). Science Studies as Naturalized Philosophy. Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
Collins, Harry (2011). “Language and Practice.” Social Studies of Science 41: 271300.Google Scholar
Collins, Harry (2012). “Comment on Kuhn.” Social Studies of Science 43, 3: 420423.Google Scholar
Collins, Harry (2018). “Studies of Expertise and Experience.” Topoi 37, 1: 6777.Google Scholar
Collins, Harry, and Evans, Robert (2017). Why Democracies Need Science. Cambridge: Polity Press.Google Scholar
Collins, Harry, Evans, Robert, Durant, Darrin, and Weinel, Martin (2020). “How Does Science Fit into Society? The Fractal Model.” In Experts and the Will of the People, pp. 6388. Cham: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Collins, Harry, Evans, Robert, and Gorman, Mike (2007). “Trading Zones and Interactional Expertise.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 38: 657666.Google Scholar
Comte, Auguste (1988). Introduction to Positive Philosophy. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett.Google Scholar
Conant, James B. (1947/1952). On Understanding Science. Mentor edition. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Conant, James B. (1947). On Understanding Science: An Historical Approach. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Conant, James B. (1950). “Science and Politics in the Twentieth Century.” Foreign Affairs 28, 2: 189202.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Conant, James B. (1951). “The Impact of Science on Industry and Medicine.” American Scientist 39, 1: 3349.Google Scholar
Conant, James B., and Nash, Leonard K. (eds.) (1948/1957). Harvard Case Histories in Experimental Science. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Cowan, Tyler (2013). “A Profession with an Egalitarian Core.” New York Times, Section BU (March 17): 4.Google Scholar
Creath, Richard (1990). “Introduction.” In W. V. Quine and Rudolf Carnap, Dear Carnap, Dear Van: The Quine-Carnap Correspondence and Related Work, ed. Creath, Richard, pp. 143. Los Angeles: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Creath, Richard (2004). “Quine on the Intelligibility and Relevance of Analyticity.” In Gibson, Roger (ed.), Cambridge Companion to Quine, pp. 4764. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Creath, Richard (2007). “Quine’s Challenge to Carnap.” In Friedman, Michael and Creath, Richard (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Carnap, pp. 316335. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Csiszar, A. (2018). The Scientific Journal: Authorship and the Politics of Knowledge in the Nineteenth Century. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Cushing, James T. (1994). Quantum Mechanics: Historical Contingency and the Copenhagen Hegemony. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
D’Agostino, F. (2010). Naturalizing Epistemology. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Daston, Lorraine (1994). “Historical Epistemology.” In Chandler, James, Davidson, Arnold I., and Harootunian, Harry (eds.), Questions of Evidence: Proof, Practice, and Persuasion across the Disciplines, pp. 282289. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Daston, Lorraine (2009). “Science Studies and the History of Science.” Critical Inquiry 35: 798813.Google Scholar
Daston, Lorraine (2016). “History of Science without Structure.” In Richards, R. J. and Daston, L. (eds.), Kuhn’s Structure of Scientific Revolutions at Fifty, pp. 115132. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Daston, Lorraine, and Galison, Peter (2007). Objectivity. New York: Zone Books.Google Scholar
Davidson, Arnold I. (2001). The Emergence of Sexuality: Historical Epistemology and the Formation of Concepts. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Davidson, Donald (1974/1984). “On the Very Idea of a Conceptual Science.” In Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation, pp. 183198. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Davidson, Donald (1997). “Gadamer and Plato’s Philebus.” In Hahn, L. E. (ed.), The Philosophy of Hans-Georg Gadamer. Chicago: Open Court.Google Scholar
Dear, Peter (ed.) (1991). The Literary Structure of Scientific Argument. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.Google Scholar
Dear, Peter (1995). “Cultural History of Science: An Overview with Reflections.” Science, Technology, and Human Values 20, 2: 150170.Google Scholar
Dear, Peter (2012). “Fifty Years of Structure.” Social Studies of Science 43, 3: 424428.Google Scholar
Del Vicario, M., Vivaldo, G., Bessi, A., Zollo, F., Scala, A., Caldarelli, G., and Quattrociocchi, W. (2016). “Echo Chambers: Emotional Contagion and Group Polarization on Facebook.” Scientific Reports 6, 1: 112.Google Scholar
Dewey, John (1916). Democracy and Education: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Education. New York: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Dimopoulos, Kostos, and Karamanidou, Christina (2013). “Towards a More Epistemologically Valid Image of School Science: Revealing the Textuality of School Science Textbooks.” In Khine, Myint Swe (ed.), Critical Analysis of Science Textbooks: Evaluating Instructional Effectiveness, pp. 6178. New York: Springer.Google Scholar
Donner, Wendy (1998). “Mill’s Utilitarianism.” In Skorupski, John (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Mill, pp. 255292. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Duhem, Pierre (1914/1954). The Aim and Structure of Physical Theory, 2nd ed., trans. Marcel Rivière. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Dupré, John (1993). The Disorder of Things: Metaphysical Foundations of the Disunity of Science. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Earman, John (1993). “Carnap, Kuhn, and the Philosophy of Scientific Methodology.” In Horwich, Paul (ed.), World Changes: Thomas Kuhn and the Nature of Science, pp. 936. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Edgerton, D. (2004). “The Linear Model Did Not Exist: Reflections on the History and Historiography of Science and Research in Industry in the Twentieth Century.” In Grandin, K., Wormbs, N., and Widmalm, S. (eds.), The Science-Industry Nexus. History, Policy, Implications. New York: Science History Publications, pp. 3157.Google Scholar
Fagan, Melinda Bonnie (2011). “Is There Collective Scientific Knowledge? Arguments from Explanation.” The Philosophical Quarterly 61, 243: 247269.Google Scholar
Fagan, Melinda Bonnie (2012a). “The Joint Account of Mechanistic Explanation.” Philosophy of Science 79, 4: 448472.Google Scholar
Fagan, Melinda Bonnie (2012b). “Collective Scientific Knowledge.” Philosophy Compass 7, 12: 821831.Google Scholar
Fan, F. (2012). “The Global Turn in the History of Science.” East Asian Science, Technology and Society: An International Journal 6: 249258.Google Scholar
Feest, Uljana, and Sturm, Thomas (2011). “What (Good) Is Historical Epistemology? Editors’ Introduction.” Erkenntnis 75, 3: 285302.Google Scholar
Feyerabend, Paul K. (1970). “Consolations for the Specialist.” In Lakatos, Imre and Musgrave, Alan (eds.), Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge, pp. 197230. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feyerabend, Paul K. (1975). Against Method: Outline of an Anarchistic Theory of Knowledge. London: New Left Books.Google Scholar
Feyerabend, Paul K. (1978a). Science in a Free Society. London: New-Left Books.Google Scholar
Feyerabend, Paul K. (1978b). Science in a Free Society. London: Verso Books.Google Scholar
Feyerabend, Paul K. (1987). Farewell to Reason. London: Verso.Google Scholar
Feyerabend, Paul K. (1989). “Realism and the Historicity of Knowledge.” Journal of Philosophy 86, 8: 393406.Google Scholar
Fiske, Edward B. (1987). “Colleges Prodded to Prove Worth.” New York Times, Section 1 (January 18): 1.Google Scholar
Fleck, Ludwik (1935/1979). Genesis and Development of a Scientific Fact, trans. Fred Bradley and Thaddeus J. Trenn. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Friedman, Michael (1987). “Carnap’s Aufbau Reconsidered.” Nous 21: 521545.Google Scholar
Friedman, Michael (2001). Dynamics of Reason: The 1999 Kant Lectures at Stanford University. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.Google Scholar
Fuller, Steve (2000a). “From Conant’s Education Strategy to Kuhn’s Research Strategy.” Science and Education 9: 2137.Google Scholar
Fuller, Steve (2000b). Thomas Kuhn: A Philosophical History for Our Times. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Fuller, Steve (2003). Kuhn vs. Popper: The Struggle for the Soul of Science. Duxford: Icon.Google Scholar
Fuller, Steve (2004). Kuhn vs. Popper: The Struggle for the Soul of Science. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Galison, Peter (1987). How Experiments End. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Galison, Peter (1988). “History, Philosophy, and the Central Metaphor.” Science in Context 2: 197212.Google Scholar
Galison, Peter (1997). Image and Logic. A Material Culture of Microphysics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Galison, Peter (1999). “Trading Zone: Coordinating Action and Belief.” In Biagioli, M. (ed.), The Science Studies Reader, pp. 137160. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Galison, Peter (2008). “Ten Problems for History and Philosophy of Science.” Isis 99, 1: 111114.Google Scholar
Galison, Peter (2011). “Scientific Cultures.” In Alexander, J. C., Smith, P., and Norton, M. (eds.), Interpreting Clifford Geertz: Cultural Investigation in the Social Sciences. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Galison, Peter (2016). “Practice All the Way Down.” In Richards, R. and Daston, L. (eds.), Kuhn’s “Structure of Scientific Revolutions” at Fifty: Reflections on a Science Classic, pp. 4269. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Galison, Peter, and Stump, David J. (eds.) (1996). The Disunity of Science: Boundaries, Contexts, and Power. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Garber, Daniel (2009). “Galileo, Newton and All That: If It Wasn’t a Revolution What Was It?Circumscribere 7: 918.Google Scholar
Geertz, C. (1997/2000). “The Legacy of Thomas Kuhn: The Right Text at the Right Time.” In Available Light, pp. 160166. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Giere, Ronald N. (1973). “History and Philosophy of Science: Intimate Relationship or Marriage of Convenience?British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 24, 3: 282297.Google Scholar
Giere, Ronald N. (1999). Science without Laws. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Gilbert, Margaret (1987). “Modelling Collective Belief.” Synthese 73, 1: 185204.Google Scholar
Gilbert, Margaret (1990). “Walking Together: A Paradigmatic Social Phenomenon.” Midwest Studies in Philosophy 15: 114.Google Scholar
Gilbert, Margaret (1992). On Social Facts. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Gilbert, Margaret (2000). “Collective Belief and Scientific Change.” In Sociality and Responsibility: New Essays in Plural Subject Theory, pp. 3749. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
Gillispie, C. C. (1962). “The Nature of Science.Science 138, 3546 (December 14): 12511253.Google Scholar
Giri, Leandro, and Melongo, Pablo (2023). “Towards a Genealogy of Thomas Kuhn’s Semantics.” Perspectives on Science 31: 385404.Google Scholar
Godfrey-Smith, P. (2003). Theory and Reality: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Golinski, J. (2012). “Thomas Kuhn and Interdisciplinary Conversation: Why Historians and Philosophers of Science Stopped Talking to One Another.” In Mauskopf, S. and Schmaltz, T. (eds.), Integrating History and Philosophy of Science, pp. 1328. Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
Goodwin, W. (2021). “Mop-Up Work.” In Brad Wray, K. (ed.), Interpreting Kuhn: Critical Essays, pp. 85104. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Gordin, M. D. (2020). “When National Styles Were Stylish.” Historical Studies in the Natural Sciences 50, 1–2: 1116.Google Scholar
Graham, G. (1997). The Shape of the Past: A Philosophical Approach to History. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Grégis, Fabien (2019a). “Assessing Accuracy in Measurement: The Dilemma of Safety versus Precision in the Adjustment of the Fundamental Physical Constants.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 74: 4255.Google Scholar
Grégis, Fabien (2019b). “On the Meaning of Measurement Uncertainty.” Measurement 133, 4146.Google Scholar
Grendler, P. F. (2002). The Universities of the Italian Renaissance. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
Guarnieri, M. (2010). “The Early History of Radar.” IEEE Industrial Electronics Magazine 4, 3: 3642.Google Scholar
Hacking, Ian (1975). The Emergence of Probability: A Philosophical Study of Early Ideas about Probability, Induction and Statistical Inference. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hacking, Ian (1982). “Experimentation and Scientific Realism.” Philosophical Topics 13, 1: 7187.Google Scholar
Hacking, Ian (1983). Representing and Intervening: Introductory Topics in the Philosophy of Natural Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hacking, Ian (1992). “‘Style’ for Historians and Philosophers.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 23, 1: 120.Google Scholar
Hacking, Ian (1999). The Social Construction of What? Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Hacking, Ian (2002). Historical Ontology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Hacking, Ian (2012). “Introductory Essay.” In Kuhn, T. S. (ed.), The Structure of Scientific Revolutions: 50th Anniversary Edition, pp. viixxxvii. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Hacking, Ian (2015). “Let’s Not Talk about Objectivity.” In Flavia, Padovani, Richardson, Alan, and Tsou, Jonathan Y. (eds.), Objectivity in Science: New Perspectives from Science and Technology Studies, pp. 1933. Cham: Springer.Google Scholar
Hacking, Ian (2016). “Paradigms.” In Richards, R. J. and Daston, L. (eds.), Kuhn’s Structure of Scientific Revolutions at Fifty: Reflections on a Science Classic, pp. 96112. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Hagstrom, W. O. (1974). “Competition in Science.” American Sociological Review 39, 1: 118.Google Scholar
Hakli, R. (2006). “Group Beliefs and the Distinction between Belief and Acceptance.” Cognitive Systems Research 7, 2–3: 286297.Google Scholar
Handelsman, Jo, Ebert-May, Diane, Beichner, Robert, Bruns, Peter, Chang, Amy, DeHaan, Robert, Gentile, Jim, et al. (2004). “Scientific Teaching.” Science 304, 5670: 521522. Accessed November 2, 2022. www.jstor.org/stable/3836701.Google Scholar
Hankins, T. L. (1985). Science and the Enlightenment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hannaway, O., Kargon, R., and Davis, A. B. (1983). “Annual Meeting of the History of Science Society, 28–31 October 1982.Isis 74, 2 (June): 243248.Google Scholar
Hanson, Norwood Russell (1958). Patterns of Discovery. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Haraway, D. (1988). “Situated Knowledges: The Science Question in Feminism and the Privilege of Partial Perspective.” Feminist Studies 14, 3: 575599.Google Scholar
Hardwig, John (1985). “Epistemic Dependence.” Journal of Philosophy 82, 7: 335349.Google Scholar
Hardwig, John (1991). “The Role of Trust in Knowledge.” Journal of Philosophy 88, 12: 693708.Google Scholar
Harman, G. (1986). Change in View: Principles of Reasoning. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Haufe, C. (2024). Fruitfulness. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Heesen, A. te (2020). “Thomas S. Kuhn, Earwitness: Interviewing and the Making of a New History of Science.Isis 111, 1: 8697.Google Scholar
Heilbron, John L. (1998). “Thomas Samuel Kuhn, 18 July 1922–17 June 1996.” Isis 1998, 89: 505515.Google Scholar
Helmholz, A. C. (1980). “Raymond Thayer Birge.” Physics Today 33, 8: 6870.Google Scholar
Hempel, Carl G. (1950). “Problems and Changes in the Empiricist Criterion of Meaning.Revue Internationale de Philosophie 41, 11: 4163.Google Scholar
Hempel, Carl G. (1966). Philosophy of Natural Science. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
Henrion, M., and Fischhoff, B. (1986). “Assessing Uncertainty in Physical Constants.” American Journal of Physics, 54, 9: 791798.Google Scholar
Hershberg, James (1993). James B. Conant: Harvard to Hiroshima and the Making of the Nuclear Age. New York: Alfred A. Knopf.Google Scholar
Hesse, Mary (1963). “Review of The Structure of Scientific Revolutions by Thomas S. Kuhn.” Isis 54, 2: 286287.Google Scholar
Hesse, Mary (1980). “The Hunt for Scientific Reason.” In Asquith, Peter D. and Giere, Ronald N. (eds.), PSA 1980: Proceedings of the 1980 Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, vol. 2, pp. 322. East Lansing, MI: Philosophy of Science Association.Google Scholar
Holbrook, J. B. (2005). “Assessing the Science–Society Relation: The Case of the US National Science Foundation’s Second Merit Review Criterion.” Technology in Society 27, 4: 437451.Google Scholar
Hollinger, A. D. (1973). “T. S. Kuhn’s Theory of Science and Its Implications for History.” The American Historical Review 78, 2: 370393.Google Scholar
Hooker, Brad (2015). “Rule Consequentialism,” bibliography. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Stanford University, accessed November 4, 2022. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/consequentialism-rule/.Google Scholar
Horwich, Paul (ed.) (1993). World Changes: Thomas Kuhn and the Nature of Science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Hoyningen-Huene, Paul (1987). “Context of Discovery and Context of Justification.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 18, 4: 501515.Google Scholar
Hoyningen-Huene, Paul (1989/1993). Reconstructing Scientific Revolutions: Thomas S. Kuhn’s Philosophy of Science, trans. Alex Levine. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Hoyningen-Huene, Paul (1992). “The Interrelations between the Philosophy, History and Sociology of Science in Thomas Kuhn’s Theory of Scientific Development.” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 43: 487501.Google Scholar
Hoyningen-Huene, Paul (1995). “Two Letters of Paul Feyerabend to Thomas S. Kuhn on a Draft of the Structure of Scientific Revolutions.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 26, 3: 353387.Google Scholar
Hoyningen-Huene, Paul (2006a). “Context of Discovery versus Context of Justification and Thomas Kuhn.” In Schickore, Jutta and Steinle, Friedrich (eds.), Revisiting Discovery and Justification: Historical and Philosophical Perspectives on the Context Distinction, pp. 119131. Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
Hoyningen-Huene, Paul (2006b). “More Letters by Paul Feyerabend to Thomas S. Kuhn on Proto-Structure.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 37, 4: 610632.Google Scholar
Hoyningen-Huene, Paul (2008). “Thomas Kuhn and the Chemical Revolution.” Foundations of Chemistry 10: 101115.Google Scholar
Hoyningen-Huene, Paul (2012). “Philosophical Elements in Thomas Kuhn’s Historiography of Science.” Theoria 75: 281292.Google Scholar
Hoyningen-Huene, Paul (2015a). “Kuhn’s Development before and after Structure.” In Devlin, W. J. and Bokulich, A. (eds.), Kuhn’s Structure of Scientific Revolutions – 50 Years On, pp. 185195. Cham: Springer.Google Scholar
Hoyningen-Huene, Paul (2015b). Systematicity: The Nature of Science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hufbauer, Karl (2012). “From Student of Physics to Historian of Science: T. S. Kuhn’s Education and Early Career, 1940–1958.” Physics in Perspective 14: 421470.Google Scholar
Hull, David L. (1989). Science as a Process. Chicago: Chicago University Press.Google Scholar
Hull, David L. (1996). “A Revolutionary Philosopher of Science.Nature 382 (July 18): 203204.Google Scholar
Hwang, R.-C., et al. (2010). “Dropping the Brand of Edinburgh School: An Interview with Barry Barnes.” East Asian Science, Technology and Society: An International Journal 4: 601617.Google Scholar
Irzik, Gürol, and Grünberg, Teo (1995). “Carnap and Kuhn: Arch Enemies or Close Allies?British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 46: 285307.Google Scholar
Isaac, J. (2012). “Kuhn’s Education: Wittgenstein, Pedagogy, and the Road to Structure.” Modern Intellectual History 9: 89107.Google Scholar
Isaac, J. (2013). “Review of Thomas S Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, Fiftieth Anniversary Edition.” Isis 104, 3: 658659.Google Scholar
James, R. J. (1989). “A History of Radar.” IEE Review 35, 9: 343349.Google Scholar
Jamieson, Annie, and Radick, Gregory (2017). “Genetic Determinism in the Genetics Curriculum: An Exploratory Study of the Effects of Mendelian and Weldonian Emphases.” Science and Education 26: 12611290.Google Scholar
Josephson, P. R. (1985). “Soviet Historians and The Structure of Scientific Revolutions.” Isis 76: 551559.Google Scholar
Kellert, Stephen H., Longino, Helen E., and Waters, C. Kenneth (2006). “Introduction: The Pluralist Stance.” In Kellert, Stephen H., Longino, Helen E., and Waters, C. Kenneth (eds.), Scientific Pluralism, pp. viixxix. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Kelves, D. (1977). “The National Science Foundation and the Debate over Postwar Research Policy, 1942–1945.” Isis 68: 526.Google Scholar
Khine, Myint Swe (ed.) (2013). Critical Analysis of Science Textbooks: Evaluating Instructional Effectiveness. New York: Springer.Google Scholar
Kindi, Vasso (2005a). “Should Science Teaching Involve the History of Science? An Assessment of Kuhn’s View.” Science and Education 14: 721731.Google Scholar
Kindi, Vasso (2005b). “The Relation of History of Science to Philosophy of Science in the Structure of Scientific Revolutions and Kuhn’s Later Philosophical Work.” Perspectives on Science 13, 4: 495530.Google Scholar
Kindi, Vasso (2012a). “Kuhn’s Paradigms.” In Kindi, V. and Arabatzis, T. (eds.), Kuhn’s The Structure of Scientific Revolutions Revisited, pp. 91111. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Kindi, Vasso (2012b). “The Structure’s Legacy: Not from Philosophy to Description.” Topoi 32, 1: 8189.Google Scholar
Kindi, Vasso (2015). “The Role of Evidence in Judging Kuhn’s Model: On the Mizrahi, Patton, Marcum Exchange.” Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective 4, 11: 2533. http://wp.me/p1Bfg0-2sQ.Google Scholar
Kindi, Vasso (2017). “The Kuhnian Straw Man.” In Mizrahi, M. (ed.), The Kuhnian Image of Science: Time for a Decisive Transformation?, pp. 95112. London: Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
Kindi, Vasso, and Arabatzis, Theodore (eds.) (2012). Kuhn’s The Structure of Scientific Revolutions Revisited. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Kitcher, P. (1990). “The Division of Cognitive Labor.” The Journal of Philosophy 87, 1: 522.Google Scholar
Klein, U. (2015). “The Revolution That Never Happened.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 49: 8090.Google Scholar
Klug, Anastasia, Müller, Olaf, Reinacher, Anna, Vine, Troy, and Yürüyen, Derya (eds.) (2021). Goethe, Ritter und die Polarität: Geschichte und Kontroversen. Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar
Kopec, M., and Miller, S. (2018). “Shared Intention Is Not Joint Commitment.” Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 13, 2: 179189.Google Scholar
Kourany, J. (1979). “The Nonhistorical Basis of Kuhn’s Theory of Science.” Nature and System 1: 4659.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (1952). “Robert Boyle and Structural Chemistry in the Seventeenth Century.” Isis 43, 1: 1236.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (1957). The Copernican Revolution: Planetary Astronomy in the Development of Western Thought. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (1959). Thomas S. Kuhn Papers, MC240, Box 3: Folder 12, Lectures, General, 1957–1959.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (1959/1977). “The Essential Tension: Tradition and Innovation in Scientific Research.” Reprinted in Kuhn, T. S. (ed.), The Essential Tension: Selected Studies in Scientific Tradition and Change, pp. 225239. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (1961/1977). “The Function of Measurement in Modern Physical Science.” In Kuhn’s, T. S. (ed.), Essential Tension: Selected Studies in Scientific Tradition and Change, pp. 178224. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Originally published in Isis 52, 2: 161–193.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (1961a). Letter from Thomas S. Kuhn to James B. Conant. Berkeley, CA, June 29, 1961. Harvard University Archives.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (1961b). Proto-Structure. Unpublished early manuscript of The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Thomas S. Kuhn Archives, MIT.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (1962). The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (1962/1970). The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2nd ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (1962/1996). The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. 3rd ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (1962/2012). The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 4th ed., 50th Anniversary Edition, with an Introductory Essay by Ian Hacking. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (1963). “The Function of Dogma in Scientific Research.” In Crombie, A. C. (ed.), Scientific Change: Historical Studies in the Intellectual, Social and Technical Conditions for Scientific Discovery and Technical Invention, from Antiquity to the Present, pp. 347369. London: Heinemann; New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (1964). Thomas S. Kuhn Papers, MC240, Box 3: Folder 13, Lectures, General, 1960–1964.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (1968/1977). “The History of Science.” In Kuhn, T. S. (ed.), The Essential Tension: Selected Studies in Scientific Tradition and Change, pp. 105126. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (1970/2012). “Postscript – 1969.” Kuhn, In T. S. (ed.), The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2nd–4th ed., pp. 173208. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (1970a). “Logic of Discovery or Psychology of Research?” In Lakatos, I. and Musgrave, A. (eds.), Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge, pp. 123. London: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (1970b). “Reflections on My Critics.” In Lakatos, Imre and Musgrave, Alan (eds.), Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge, pp. 231278. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (1971). “Notes on Lakatos.” In Buck, R. C. and Cohen, R. S. (eds.), PSA 1970: In Memory of Rudolf Carnap, pp. 137146. Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (1971/1977). “The Relations between History and History of Science.” In Kuhn, T. S. (ed.), The Essential Tension: Selected Studies in Scientific Tradition and Change, pp. 127161. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (1972). “Scientific Growth: Reflection on Ben-David’s Scientific Role.” Minerva 10: 166178.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (1973/1977). “Objectivity, Value Judgment, and Theory Choice.” In Kuhn, T. S. (ed.), The Essential Tension: Selected Studies in Scientific Tradition and Change, pp. 320339. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (1974). “Discussion.” In Suppe, F. (ed.), The Structure of Scientific Theories, pp. 500517. Urbana: University of Illinois Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (1974/1977). “Second Thoughts on Paradigms.” In Kuhn, T. S. (ed.), The Essential Tension: Selected Studies in Scientific Tradition and Change, pp. 293319. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (1976). “Mathematical versus Experimental Traditions in the Development of Physical Science.” Journal of Interdisciplinary History 7, 1: 131.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (1976/1977a). “Mathematical versus Experimental Traditions in the Development of Physical Science.” In Kuhn, T. S. (ed.), The Essential Tension: Selected Studies in Scientific Tradition and Change, pp. 3165. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (1976/1977b). “The Relations between the History and the Philosophy of Science.” In Kuhn, T. S. (ed.), The Essential Tension: Selected Studies in Scientific Tradition and Change, pp. 320. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (ed.) (1977). The Essential Tension: Selected Studies in Scientific Tradition and Change. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (1977a). “Preface.” In Kuhn, T. S. (ed.), The Essential Tension: Selected Studies in Scientific Tradition and Change, pp. ixxxiii. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (1978). Black-Body Theory and the Quantum Discontinuity, 1894–1912. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (1979). “Foreword.” In Ludwik Fleck, T. J. Trenn, and R. K. Merton, trans. F. Bradley and T. J. Trenn, Genesis and Development of a Scientific Fact, pp. vii–xi. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (1980). “The Halt and the Blind: Philosophy and History of Science.” British Journal for Philosophy of Science 31: 181192.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (1983). “Reflections on Receiving the John Desmond Bernal Award.4S Review 1, 4 (Winter): 2630.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (1984). “Professionalization Recollected in Tranquility.” Isis 75, 1: 2932.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (1986). “The Histories of Science: Diverse Worlds for Diverse Audiences.” Academe 72, 4: 2933.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (1989/1993). “Foreword.” In Hoyningen-Huene, Paul (ed.), Reconstructing Scientific Revolutions: Thomas S. Kuhn’s Philosophy of Science, pp. xixiii. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (1991/2000). “The Road since Structure.” In J. Conant and J. Haugeland (eds.), The Road since Structure: Philosophical Essays, 1970–1993, with an Autobiographical Interview, pp. 90104. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (1992/2000). “The Trouble with the Historical Philosophy of Science.” In J. Conant and J. Haugeland (eds.), The Road since Structure: Philosophical Essays, 1970–1993, with an Autobiographical Interview, pp. 105120. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (1993/2000). “Afterwords.” In J. Conant and J. Haugeland (eds.), The Road since Structure: Philosophical Essays, 1970–1993, with an Autobiographical Interview, pp. 224252. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (1997/2000). “A Discussion with Thomas S. Kuhn.” In The Road since Structure: Philosophical Essays, 1970–1993, with an Autobiographical Interview, ed. Conant, J. and Haugeland, J., pp. 253323. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (2000). The Road since Structure: Philosophical Essays, 1970–1993, with an Autobiographical Interview, ed. Conant, J. and Haugeland, J.. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (2016). “The Nature of Scientific Knowledge: An Interview with Thomas Kuhn (conducted by Skúli Sigurdsson).” In Blum, A. et al. (eds.), Shifting Paradigms. Thomas S. Kuhn and the History of Science, pp. 1730. Berlin: Max-Planck-Institute for the History of Science.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (2021). The Quest for Physical Theory. Problems in the Methodology of Scientific Research, ed. Reisch, George A.. Boston: MIT Libraries.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (2022). The Last Writings of Thomas S. Kuhn: Incommensurability in Science, edited by Mladenovic, Bojana. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Kusch, Martin (2010). “Hacking’s Historical Epistemology: A Critique of Styles of Reasoning.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 41, 2: 158173.Google Scholar
Kusch, Martin (2016). “Relativism in Feyerabend’s Later Writings.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 57: 106113.Google Scholar
Kusch, Martin (2021). Relativism in the Philosophy of Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kuukkanen, Jouni-Matti (2013). “Kuhn’s Legacy: Theoretical and Philosophical Study of History.” Topoi 32: 9199.Google Scholar
Kuusela, O. (2008). The Struggle against Dogmatism. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Kuusela, O. (2019). Wittgenstein on Logic as the Method of Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lakatos, Imre (1970). “Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes.” In Lakatos, Imre and Musgrave, Alan (eds.), Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge: Proceedings of the International Colloquium in the Philosophy of Science, London, 1965, vol. 4, pp. 91196. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Lakatos, Imre (1971). “History of Science and Its Rational Reconstructions.” In Buck, R. C. and Cohen, R. S. (eds.), PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1970, pp. 91136. Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar
Lakatos, Imre, and Musgrave, Alan (eds.) (1970). Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Latour, B. (1987). Science in Action: How to Follow Scientists and Engineers through Society. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Latour, Bruno, and Woolgar, Steve (1979). Laboratory Life: The Social Construction of Scientific Facts. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Laudan, Larry (1984). Science and Values: The Aims of Science and Their Role in Scientific Debate. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Levine, Alex (1999). “Scientific Progress and the Fregean Legacy.” Mind and Language 14, 3: 263290.Google Scholar
Levine, Alex (2000). “Which Way Is Up? Thomas S. Kuhn’s Analogy to Conceptual Development in Childhood.” Science and Education 9: 107122.Google Scholar
Levine, Alex, and Novoa, Adriana (2012). ¡Darwinistas! The Construction of Evolutionary Thought in Nineteenth Century Argentina, ed. Feingold, Mordechai. Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar
List, C., and Pettit, P. (2011). Group Agency: The Possibility, Design, and Status of Corporate Agents. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lloyd, Elisabeth A. (1996). “The Anachronistic Anarchist.” Philosophical Studies 81, 2–3: 247261.Google Scholar
Longino, Helen E. (1990). Science as Social Knowledge: Values and Objectivity in Scientific Inquiry. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Loving, Cathleen C., and Cobern, William W. (2000). “Invoking Thomas Kuhn: What Citation Analysis Reveals about Science Education.” Science and Education 9: 187206.Google Scholar
Luchetti, Michele (2021). “Coordination in Theory Extension: How Reichenbach Can Help Us Understand Endogenization in Evolutionary Biology.” Synthese 1999, 3–4: 98559880.Google Scholar
Ludwig, David, and Ruphy, Stéphanie (2021). “Scientific Pluralism.” In Edward N. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2021 edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2021/entries/scientific-pluralism.Google Scholar
Lynch, M. (2012). “Self-Exemplifying Revolutions? Notes on Kuhn and Latour.” Social Studies of Science 42, 3: 449455.Google Scholar
Maasen, S., and Weingart, P. (2000). Metaphors and the Dynamics of Knowledge. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Mach, Ernst (1911). History and Root of the Principle of the Conservation of Energy, trans. P. E. B. Jourdain. Chicago: Open Court.Google Scholar
Magnus, P. D. (2013). “Philosophy of Science in the 21st Century.” Metaphilosophy 44, 1–2: 4852.Google Scholar
Malpas, Jeff (2021). “Donald Davidson.” In Edward N. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2021 Edition).Google Scholar
Mandelbaum, Maurice (1969). “Two Moot Issues in Mill’s Utilitarianism.” In Schneewind, J. B. (ed.), Mill: A Collection of Critical Essays, pp. 206233. Notre Dame, IN: Notre Dame University Press.Google Scholar
Marcum, James A. (2015). Thomas Kuhn’s Revolutions: A Historical and an Evolutionary Philosophy of Science? London: Bloomsbury.Google Scholar
Masterman, Margaret (1970). “The Nature of Paradigms.” In Lakatos, I. and Musgrave, A. (eds.), Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge: Proceedings of the International Colloquium in the Philosophy of Science, London, 1965, vol. 4, pp. 5989. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Mathiesen, K. (2006). “The Epistemic Features of Group Belief.” Episteme 2, 3: 161175.Google Scholar
Matthews, Michael R. (2000). “Editorial.” Science and Education 9: 110.Google Scholar
Matthews, Michael R. (2003). “Thomas Kuhn’s Impact on Science Education: What Lessons Can Be Learned?Science Education 88, 1: 90118.Google Scholar
Matthews, Michael R. (2022). “Thomas Kuhn and Science Education: A Troubled Connection.” HP&ST Newsletter, April: 6–24.Google Scholar
Mayoral, Juan Vicente (2009). “Intensions, Belief and Science: Kuhn’s Early Philosophical Outlook (1940–1945).” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 40, 2: 175184.Google Scholar
Mayoral, Juan Vicente (2011). “Hacia una reinterpretación de la ciencia normal: Kuhn y la física de su tiempo (1940–1951).” Asclepio 63, 1: 221248.Google Scholar
Mayoral, Juan Vicente (2017). Thomas S. Kuhn: La búsqueda de La Estructura. Zaragoza: Prensas de la Universidad de Zaragoza.Google Scholar
Mayr, E. (1972). “The Nature of the Darwinian Revolution.” Science 176: 981989.Google Scholar
McMullin, Ernan (1984). “A Case for Scientific Realism.” In Leplin, J. (ed.), Scientific Realism, pp. 840. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
McMullin, Ernan (1993). “Rationality and Paradigm Change in Science.” In Horwich, Paul (ed.), World Changes: Thomas Kuhn and the Nature of Science, pp. 5578. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Melogno, Pablo (2022). “From Externalism to Internalism: The Historiographical Development of Thomas Kuhn.” Foundations of Science 27, 2: 371385.Google Scholar
Mercier, J. (1924). “De la synchronisation harmonique et multiple.” Journal de Physique et le Radium 5: 168179.Google Scholar
Michelson, A. A. (1927). “Measurement of the Velocity of Light between Mount Wilson and Mount San Antonio.” The Astrophysical Journal 65, 1: 114.Google Scholar
Mizrahi, M. (ed.) (2018). The Kuhnian Image of Science: Time for a Decisive Transformation? London: Rowman and Littlefield International.Google Scholar
Mladenović, B. (2007). “‘Muckracking in History’: The Role of the History of Science in Kuhn’s Philosophy.” Perspectives on Science 15, 3: 261294.Google Scholar
Morris, E. (2018). The Ashtray; or, The Man Who Denied Reality. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Moss, J. D. (1993). Novelties in the Heavens: Rhetoric and Science in the Copernican Controversy. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Nash, L. K. (1956). “The Origin of Dalton’s Chemical Atomic Theory.” Isis 47, 2: 101116.Google Scholar
National Science Board (2007). Enhancing Support of Transformative Research at the National Science Foundation. Arlington, VA: National Science Foundation.Google Scholar
NGSS Lead States (2013). “Appendix H, Understanding the Scientific Enterprise: The Nature of Science in the Next Generation Science Standards.” In Next Generation Science Standards for States by States, pp. 110. Washington, DC: National Academies Press.Google Scholar
Niaz, Mansoor (2001). “A Rational Reconstruction of the Origin of the Covalent Bond and Its Implications for General Chemistry Textbooks.” International Journal of Science Education 23, 6: 623645.Google Scholar
Niaz, Mansoor (2016). Chemistry Education and Contributions from History and Philosophy of Science. Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
Niaz, Mansoor, and Coştu, Bayram (2013). “Analysis of Turkish General Chemistry Textbooks Based on a History and Philosophy of Science Perspective.” In Khine, Myint Swe (ed.), Critical Analysis of Science Textbooks: Evaluating Instructional Effectiveness, pp. 199218. New York: Springer.Google Scholar
Niaz, Mansoor, and Maza, Arelys (2011). Nature of Science in General Chemistry Textbooks. Springer Briefs in Education. Accessed November 6, 2022. DOI: 10.1007/978-94-007-1920-0_1.Google Scholar
Nickles, Thomas (ed.) (2003a). Thomas Kuhn. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Nickles, Thomas (2003b). “Normal Science: From Logic to Case-Based and Model-Based Reasoning.” In Nickles, Thomas (ed.), Thomas Kuhn, pp. 142177. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Nickles, Thomas (2012). “Some Puzzles about Kuhn’s Exemplars.” In Kindi, V. and Arabatzis, T. (eds.), Kuhn’s The Structure of Scientific Revolutions Revisited, pp. 112133. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Nickles, Thomas (2017). “Historicist Theories of Scientific Rationality.” In Edward N. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2021 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/rationality-historicist/.Google Scholar
Nickles, Thomas (2021). “Kuhn on Scientific Discovery as Endogenous.” In Wray, K. Brad (ed.), Interpreting Kuhn: Critical Essays, pp. 185201. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Nola, Robert (2000). “Saving Kuhn from the Sociologists of Science.” Science and Education 9, 1: 7790.Google Scholar
Nola, Robert (2003). Rescuing Reason: A Critique of Anti-Rationalist Views of Science and Knowledge. Dordrecht: Kluwer.Google Scholar
North, J. (1992). “The Quadrivium.” In H. de Ridder-Symoens (ed.), A History of the University in Europe, vol. 1: Universities in the Middle Ages, pp. 337359. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Novoa, Adriana, and Levine, Alex (2010). From Man to Ape: Darwinism in Argentina, 1870–1920. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Nye, Mary Jo (2014). “Science and Politics in the Philosophy of Science: Popper, Kuhn, and Polanyi.” In Epple, M. and Zittel, C. (eds.), Science as Cultural Practice, pp. 201216. Berlin: De Gruyter.Google Scholar
Nye, Mary Jo (2019). “Shifting Trends in Modern Physics, Nobel Recognition, and the Histories That We Write.” Physics in Perspective 21: 322.Google Scholar
O’Donohue, William, and Willis, Brendan (2018). “Problematic Images of Science in Undergraduate Psychology Textbooks: How Well Is Science Understood and Depicted?Archives of Scientific Psychology 6, 1: 5162. Accessed October 10, 2022. doi:10.1037/arc0000040.Google Scholar
Olby, Robert C. (1966/1985). Origins of Mendelism, 2nd ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Olesko, Kathryn M. (2006). “Science Pedagogy as a Category of Historical Analysis: Past, Present, and Future.” Science and Education 15: 863880.Google Scholar
Oliveira, J.C. de Pinto (2021). “Kuhn and Logical Positivism: On the Image of Science and the Image of Philosophy.” In Wray, K. Brad (ed.), Interpreting Kuhn: Critical Essays, pp. 6582. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Oreskes, N., and Conway, E. M. (2010). Merchants of Doubt: How a Handful of Scientists Obscured the Truth on Issues from Tobacco Smoke to Climate Change. New York: Bloomsbury.Google Scholar
Pang, A. S. K. (1997). “Visual Representation and Post-Constructivist History of Science.” Historical Studies in the Physical and Biological Sciences 28, 1: 139171.Google Scholar
Papineau, D. (2021). “Naturalism.” In E. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2021/entries/naturalism/.Google Scholar
Patton, Lydia (2018). “Kuhn, Pedagogy, and Practice: A Local Reading of Structure.” In Mizrahi, M. (ed.), The Kuhnian Image of Science: Time for a Decisive Transformation?, pp. 113130. London: Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
Patton, Lydia (2021). “Kuhn’s Kantian Dimensions.” In Wray, K. Brad (ed.), Interpreting Kuhn: Critical Essays, pp. 2744. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Pettigrove, G. (2016). “Changing Our Mind.” In Brady, M. and Fricker, M. (eds.), The Epistemic Life of Groups, pp. 111130. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pickering, Andrew (2001). “Reading the Structure.” Perspectives on Science 9, 4: 499510.Google Scholar
Pickering, Andrew (2012). “The World since Kuhn,” Social Studies of Science 42, 3: 467473.Google Scholar
Pigliucci, Massimo, and Boudry, Maarten (eds.) (2013). Philosophy of Pseudoscience: Reconsidering the Demarcation Problem. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Pinch, Trevor (2017). “All Pumped Up about the Sociology of Scientific Knowledge.” Isis 108, 1: 127129.Google Scholar
Pirozelli, P. (2021). “The Structure of Scientific Controversies: Thomas Kuhn’s Social Epistemology.” Filosofia Unisinos: Unisinos Journal of Philosophy 22, 3: 117.Google Scholar
Pitt, Joseph C. (2001). “The Dilemma of Case Studies: Toward a Heraclitian Philosophy of Science.” Perspectives on Science 9, 4: 372383.Google Scholar
Popper, Karl R. (1935/1959). The Logic of Scientific Discovery. London: Hutchinson.Google Scholar
Popper, Karl R. (1963). Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth of Scientific Knowledge. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Popper, Karl R. (1970). “Normal Science and Its Dangers.” In Lakatos, Imre and Musgrave, Alan (eds.), Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge: Proceedings of the International Colloquium in the Philosophy of Science, London, 1965, vol. 4, pp. 5158. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Porter, A., Cohen, A., David Roessner, J., and Perreault, M. J. S. (2007). “Measuring Researcher Interdisciplinarity.” Scientometrics 72, 1: 117147.Google Scholar
Porter, A., and Rafols, I. (2009). “Is Science Becoming More Interdisciplinary? Measuring and Mapping Six Research Fields over Time.” Scientometrics 81, 3: 719745.Google Scholar
Porter, A., and Rossini, F. (1985). “Peer Review of Interdisciplinary Research Proposals.” Science, Technology, and Human Values 10, 3: 3338.Google Scholar
Poulsen, M.-B. J. (2001). “Competition and Cooperation: What Roles in Science Dynamics?International Journal of Technology, Policy and Management 22, 7–8: 782793.Google Scholar
Preston, John (1997a). Feyerabend: Philosophy, Science and Society. Cambridge: Polity Press.Google Scholar
Preston, John (1997b). “Feyerabend’s Retreat from Realism.Philosophy of Science 64 (Proceedings): S421S431.Google Scholar
Preston, John, Munévar, Gonzalo, and Lamb, David (eds.) (2000). The Worst Enemy of Science? Essays in Memory of Paul Feyerabend. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Price, Derek de Solla (1963). Little Science, Big Science. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Putnam, Hilary (1975). “The Meaning of ‘Meaning.’” Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science 7: 131193.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. O. (1951). “Two Dogmas of Empiricism.” Philosophical Review 60: 2043.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. O. (1960). Word and Object. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. O. (1969). “Epistemology Naturalized.” In Ontological Relativity and Other Essays, pp. 6990. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. O. (1971). “Epistemology Naturalized.” In Gabriel, L. (ed.), Akten des XIV. Internationalen Kongresses für Philosophie Wien, 2.–9. September 1968, vol. 6, pp. 87103. Vienna: Herder.Google Scholar
Quinn, T. (2011). “Time, the SI and the Metre Convention.” Metrologia 48, 4: S121.Google Scholar
Radick, Gregory (2016). “Teach Students the Biology of Their Time.Nature 533 (May 19): 293.Google Scholar
Rasmussen, S. B. (2014). Potentialeledelse: Om strategisk ledelse i fagprofessionelle organisationer. Copenhagen: Barlebo Forlag.Google Scholar
Reingold, Nathan (1980). “Through Paradigm-Land to a Normal History of Science.” Social Studies of Science 10, 4: 475496.Google Scholar
Reingold, Nathan (1987). “Vannevar Bush’s New Deal for Research: Or the Triumph of the Old Order.” Historical Studies in the Physical and Biological Sciences 17, 2: 299344.Google Scholar
Reisch, George A. (1991). “Did Kuhn Kill Logical Positivism?Philosophy of Science 58: 264277.Google Scholar
Reisch, George A. (1998). “Pluralism, Logical Empiricism, and the Problem of Pseudoscience.” Philosophy of Science 65, 2: 333348.Google Scholar
Reisch, George A. (2016). “Aristotle in the Cold War: On the Origins of Thomas Kuhn’s Structure of Scientific Revolutions.” In Richards, R. J. and Daston, L. (eds.), Kuhn’s Structure of Scientific Revolutions at Fifty: Reflections on a Science Classic, pp. 1229. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Reisch, George A. (2019). The Politics of Paradigms: Thomas S. Kuhn, James B. Conant, and the Cold War “Struggle for Men’s Minds.” Albany: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
Reisch, George A. (2021a). “A Public Intellectual and a Private Scholar: On Thomas Kuhn, James B. Conant, and the Place of History and Philosophy of Science in Postwar America.” In Wray, K. Brad (ed.), Interpreting Kuhn: Critical Essays, pp. 4564. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Reisch, George A. (2021b). “Thomas Kuhn’s Quest for Physical Theory: Editor’s Introduction.” In Reisch, George (ed.), The Quest for Physical Theory: Problems in the Methodology of Scientific Research. Cambridge, MA: MIT Libraries Digital Collections.Google Scholar
Renn, J. (2015). “The History of Science and the Globalization of Knowledge.” In Arabatzis, T., Renn, J., and Simões, A. (eds.), Relocating the History of Science, pp. 241252. Cham: Springer.Google Scholar
Renzi, B. G. (2009). “Kuhn’s Evolutionary Epistemology and Its Being Undermined by Inadequate Biological Concepts.” Philosophy of Science 76: 143159.Google Scholar
Reydon, T. A. C., and Hoyningen-Huene, P. (2010). “Discussion: Kuhn’s Evolutionary Analogy in The Structure of Scientific Revolutions and ‘The Road since Structure.’” Philosophy of Science 77: 468476.Google Scholar
Richards, Robert J., and Daston, Lorraine (2016). Kuhn’s Structure of Scientific Revolutions at Fifty: Reflections on a Science Classic. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Richardson, Alan W. (1998). Carnap’s Construction of the World: The Aufbau and the Emergence of Logical Empiricism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Richardson, Alan W. (2002). “Narrating the History of Reason Itself: Friedman, Kuhn, and a Constitutive A Priori for the Twenty-First Century.” Perspectives on Science 10, 3: 253274.Google Scholar
Richardson, Alan W. (2006). “The Many Unities of Science: Politics, Semantics, and Ontology.” In Keller, Stephen H., Longino, Helen E., and Waters, C. Kenneth (eds.), Scientific Pluralism, pp. 125. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Rolin, K. (2008). “Science as Collective Knowledge.” Cognitive Systems Research 9, 1–2: 115124.Google Scholar
Rorty, R. (1997/1999). “Thomas Kuhn, Rocks and the Laws of Physics.” In Philosophy and Social Hope, pp. 175189. London: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
Rosa, E. B., and Dorsey, N. E. (1907). “A New Determination of the Ratio of the Electromagnetic to the Electrostatic Unit of Electricity.Bulletin of the Bureau of Standards 3, 3: 433540.Google Scholar
Roth, Paul A. (2013). “The Silence of the Norms: The Missing Historiography of The Structure of Scientific Revolutions.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 44, 4: 545552.Google Scholar
Rothleitner, C., and Schlamminger, S. (2017). “Invited Review Article: Measurements of the Newtonian Constant of Gravitation, G.” Review of Scientific Instruments 88, 11: 111101.Google Scholar
Rowley, W. R. C. (1984). “The Definition of the Metre: From Polar Quadrant to the Speed of Light.” Physics Bulletin 35, 7: 282.Google Scholar
Sahlins, M. D. (1964). “Review of The Structure of Scientific Revolutions.” Scientific American, 210, 5 (May): 142144.Google Scholar
Sankey, Howard (2011). “Epistemic Relativism and the Problem of the Criterion.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science A 42, 4: 562570.Google Scholar
Sankey, Howard (2012). “Scepticism, Relativism and the Argument from the Criterion.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science A 43, 1: 182190.Google Scholar
Sankey, Howard (2020). “The Relativistic Legacy of Kuhn and Feyerabend.” In Kusch, Martin (ed.), The Routledge Handbook of the Philosophy of Relativism, pp. 379387. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Saul, Stephanie (2022). “N.Y.U. Students Were Failing Class. The Professor Lost His Job.” New York Times, Section A (October 3): 1.Google Scholar
Scheffler, Israel (1967). Science and Subjectivity. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill.Google Scholar
Schickore, Jutta (2011). “More Thoughts on HPS: Another 20 Years Later.” Perspectives on Science 19, 3: 453481.Google Scholar
Schickore, Jutta, and Steinle, Friedrich (2006). “Introduction: Revisiting the Context Distinction.” In Schickore, J. and Steinle, F. (eds.), Revisiting Discovery and Justification, pp. 719. Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
Schindler, Samuel (2013). “The Kuhnian Mode of HPS.” Synthese 190, 18: 41374154.Google Scholar
Schwab, Joseph J. (1962). The Teaching of Science as Enquiry. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Searle, John R. (1993). “Rationality and Realism, What Is at Stake?Daedalus 122, 4: 5583.Google Scholar
Secord, James A. (2004). “Knowledge in Transit.” Isis 95, 4: 654672.Google Scholar
Seidel, Markus (2013). “Between Relativism and Absolutism? – The Failure of Kuhn’s Moderate Relativism.” In M. Hoeltje, T. Spitzley, and W. Spohn (eds.), Was dürfen wir glauben? Was sollen wir tun? Sektionsbeiträge des achten internationalen Kongresses der Gesellschaft für Analytische Philosophie e.V., pp. 172–185. Online Publication of the University of Duisburg–Essen (DuEPublico), https://duepublico2.uni-due.de/servlets/MCRFileNodeServlet/duepublico_derivate_00033085/GAP8_Proceedings.pdf.Google Scholar
Seidel, Markus (2014). Epistemic Relativism: A Constructive Critique. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Seidel, Markus (2021a). “Portraying the Relativist Spectrum.” Metascience 30: 357360.Google Scholar
Seidel, Markus (2021b). “Kuhn’s Two Accounts of Scientific Disagreement in Science: An Interpretation and Critique.” Synthese 198: 60236051.Google Scholar
Šešelja, D., and Straßer, C. (2013). “Kuhn and the Question of Pursuit Worthiness.” Topoi 32, 1: 919.Google Scholar
Sewell, W. H., Jr. (2005). Logics of History: Social Theory and Social Transformation. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Shan, Yafeng (2020). “Kuhn’s ‘Wrong Turning’ and Legacy Today.” Synthese 197, 1: 381406.Google Scholar
Shapere, Dudley (1964). “Review of The Structure of Scientific Revolutions.” The Philosophical Review 73, 3: 383394.Google Scholar
Shapin, Steven (1980). “Social Uses of Science.” In Rousseau, G. S. and Porter, R. (eds.), The Ferment of Knowledge: Studies in the Historiography of Eighteenth-Century Science, pp. 93139. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Shapin, Steven (1992). “Discipline and Bounding: The History and Sociology of Science as Seen through the Externalism-Internalism Debate.” History of Science 30: 333369.Google Scholar
Shapin, Steven (2008). The Scientific Life: A Moral History of a Late Modern Vocation. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Shapin, Steven (2015). “Kuhn’s Structure: A Moment in Modern Naturalism.” In Devlin, W. J. and Bokulich, A. (eds.), Kuhn’s Structure of Scientific Revolutions – 50 Years On, pp. 1121. Cham: Springer.Google Scholar
Shapin, Steven, and Schaffer, Simon (1985). Leviathan and the Air Pump. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Shapiro, S. J. (2002). “Law, Plans, and Practical Reason.” Legal Theory 8, 4: 387441.Google Scholar
Sharrock, W., and Read, R. (2002). Kuhn: Philosopher of Scientific Revolutions. Cambridge: Polity Press.Google Scholar
Shaw, Jamie, and Bschir, Karim (2021). “Introduction: Paul Feyerabend’s Philosophy in the Twenty-First Century.” In Bschir, Karim and Shaw, Jamie (eds.), Interpreting Feyerabend: Critical Essays, pp. 110. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Shipman, Harry L. (2000). “Thomas Kuhn’s Influence on Astronomers.” Science and Education 9: 161171.Google Scholar
Siegel, Harvey (1990). Educating Reason: Rationality, Critical Thinking and Education. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Siegel, Harvey (2011). “Relativism, Incoherence, and the Strong Programme.” In Schantz, R. and Seidel, M. (eds.), The Problem of Relativism in the Sociology of (Scientific) Knowledge, pp. 4164. Frankfurt: Ontos.Google Scholar
Sigurdsson, S. (2016). “The Nature of Scientific Knowledge: An Interview with Thomas S. Kuhn.” In Blum, A., Gavroglu, K., Joas, C., and Renn, J. (eds.), Shifting Paradigms: Thomas S. Kuhn and the History of Science, pp. 1730. Berlin: Edition Open Access.Google Scholar
Smart, J. J. C. (1956). “Extreme and Restricted Utilitarianism.” Philosophical Quarterly 6: 344354.Google Scholar
Smith, George E. (2010). “Revisiting Accepted Science: The Indispensability of the History of Science,” ed. Sugden, Sherwood J. B.. Monist 93, 4: 545579.Google Scholar
Smith, George E. (2014). “Closing the Loop: Testing Newtonian Gravity, Then and Now.” In Biener, Z. and Schliesser, E. (eds.), Newton and Empiricism, pp. 262351. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sober, Elliott (2009). Core Questions in Philosophy: A Text with Readings, 5th ed. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.Google Scholar
Soler, Léna (2022). “Incompatible Judgments about the Operational Coherence and Success of Competing Epistemic Systems of Practice.” Presentation at the conference “Can Realism Allow Pluralism and Contingency,” Université de Lorraine, October 19.Google Scholar
Solomon, Miriam (2001). Social Empiricism. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Solomon, Miriam, and Richardson, Alan (2005). “A Critical Context for Longino’s Critical Contextual Empiricism.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 36, 1: 211222.Google Scholar
“Stem Futures: The Future Substance of STEM Education Project.” STEM Futures. Science Education Resource Center at Carleton College. Last revised October 7, 2022. Accessed October 31, 2022. https://serc.carleton.edu/stemfutures/index.html.Google Scholar
Stewart, David, Blocker, H. Gene, and Petrik, James (2013). Fundamentals of Philosophy, 8th ed. Boston: Pearson.Google Scholar
Stopes-Roe, H. V. (1964). “Review of The Structure of Scientific Revolutions.” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 15, 58: 158161.Google Scholar
Struik, D. (1967). A Concise History of Mathematics. London: Bell and Sons.Google Scholar
Sunstein, C. R. (2002). “The Law of Group Polarization.” Journal of Political Philosophy 10, 2: 175195.Google Scholar
Suppe, F. (ed.) (1974). The Structure of Scientific Theories, pp. 459482. Urbana: University of Illinois Press.Google Scholar
Suppes, Patrick (1978). “The Plurality of Science.” In Asquith, Peter and Hacking, Ian (eds.), PSA 1978: Proceedings of the 1978 Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, vol. 2, pp. 316. East Lansing, MI: Philosophy of Science Association.Google Scholar
Tal, E. (2011). “How Accurate Is the Standard Second?Philosophy of Science 78, 5: 10821096.Google Scholar
Tanghe, K. B., Pauwels, L., De Tiège, A., and Braeckman, J. (2021). “Interpreting the History of Evolutionary Biology through a Kuhnian Prism: Sense or Nonsense?Perspectives on Science 29, 1: 135.Google Scholar
Tarski, Alfred (1956). “The Concept of Truth in Formalized Languages.” In Corcoran, John (ed.) and Translated by Woodger, J. W., Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics: Papers from 1923 to 1938. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Taylor, B. N., Parker, W. H. and Langenberg, D. N. (1969). “Determination of e/h, Using Macroscopic Quantum Phase Coherence in Superconductors: Implications for Quantum Electrodynamics and the Fundamental Physical Constants.Reviews of Modern Physics 41, 3: 375496.Google Scholar
Taylor, Barry N. (1971). “Comments on Least-Squares Adjustments of the Constants.” In Langenberg, D. N. and Taylor, B. N. (eds.), Precision Measurement and Fundamental Constants, pp. 495498. Washington, DC: National Bureau of Standards.Google Scholar
Thackray, A. (1984). “Sarton, Science, and History.” Isis 75, 1: 79.Google Scholar
Tiesinga, E., Mohr, P. J., Newell, D. B., and Taylor, B. (2021). “CODATA Recommended Values of the Fundamental Physical Constants: 2018.” Reviews of Modern Physics 93, 2: 025010.Google Scholar
Toon, Ernest R., and George L., Ellis (1978). Foundations of Chemistry. New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston.Google Scholar
Toulmin, Stephen (1970). “Does the Distinction between Normal and Revolutionary Science Hold Water?” In Lakatos, I. and Musgrave, A. (eds.), Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge, pp. 2948. London: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Tsou, Jonathan Y. (2003a). “A Role for Reason in Science.Dialogue: Canadian Philosophical Review 42, 3: 573598.Google Scholar
Tsou, Jonathan Y. (2003b). “Reconsidering Feyerabend’s ‘Anarchism.’” Perspectives on Science 11, 2: 208235.Google Scholar
Tsou, Jonathan Y. (2010). “Putnam’s Account of Apriority and Scientific Change: Its Historical and Contemporary Interest.” Synthese 176, 3: 429445.Google Scholar
Tsou, Jonathan Y. (2015). “Reconsidering the Carnap-Kuhn Connection.” In Devlin, W. J. and Bokulich, A. (eds.), Kuhn’s Structure of Scientific Revolutions – 50 Years On, pp. 5169. Cham: Springer.Google Scholar
Tsou, Jonathan Y. (forthcoming). “Philosophical Naturalism and Empirical Approaches to Philosophy.” In Rossberg, Marcus (ed.), The Cambridge Handbook of Analytic Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Tuomela, Raimo (1992). “Group Beliefs.” Synthese 91, 3: 285318.Google Scholar
Urmson, J. O. (1953). “The Interpretation of the Moral Philosophy of J. S. Mill.” Philosophical Quarterly 3: 3339.Google Scholar
van Berkel, Berry, de Vos, Wobbe, Verdonk, Adri H., and Pilot, Albert (2000). “Normal Science Education and Its Dangers: The Case of School Chemistry.” Science and Education 9: 123159.Google Scholar
Wagenknecht, Susann (2016). A Social Epistemology of Research Groups: Collaboration in Scientific Practice. London: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Walker, T. C. (2010). “The Perils of Paradigm Mentalities: Revisiting Kuhn, Lakatos, and Popper.” Perspectives on Politics 8, 2: 433451.Google Scholar
Warwick, Andrew (2003). Masters of Theory: Cambridge and the Rise of Mathematical Physics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Watkins, John (1970). “Against ‘Normal Science.’” In Lakatos, Imre and Musgrave, Alan (eds.), Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge, pp. 2537. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weatherall, James O., and Gilbert, Margaret (2016). “Collective Belief, Kuhn, and the String Theory Community.” In Brady, M. and Fricker, M. (eds.), The Epistemic Life of Groups, pp. 191218. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Weinberg, S. (1998). “The Revolution That Didn’t Happen.” New York Review of Books (October 8): 48–52.Google Scholar
Williams, David Lay (2020). “Was Slavery a ‘Necessary Evil’? Here’s What John Stuart Mill Would Say.” Washington Post (July 30). Accessed November 4, 2022. www.washingtonpost.com/politics/2020/07/30/was-slavery-necessary-evil-heres-what-john-stuart-mill-would-say/.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, Ludwig (1953/2009). Philosophical Investigations, 4th ed., ed. Anscombe, E.. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, Ludwig (1977/1994). Culture and Value, ed. von Wright, G. H., Nyman, H., and Pichler, A.. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Woolgar, Steve (1981). “Discovery: Logic and Sequence in a Scientific Text.” In Knorr, Karin D., Krohn, Roger, and Whitley, Richard (eds.), The Social Process of Scientific Investigation, pp. 239268. Boston: D. Reidel.Google Scholar
Worrall, John (1989). “Structural Realism: The Best of Both Worlds?Dialectica 43, 1–2: 99124.Google Scholar
Worrall, John (2003). “Normal Science and Dogmatism, Paradigms and Progress: Kuhn ‘versus’ Popper and Lakatos.” In Nickles, Thomas (ed.), Thomas Kuhn, pp. 65100. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Wray, K. Brad (2001). “Collective Belief and Acceptance.” Synthese 129: 319333.Google Scholar
Wray, K. Brad (2003). “Is Science Really a Young Man’s Game?Social Studies of Science 33, 1: 137149.Google Scholar
Wray, K. Brad (2004). “An Examination of the Contributions of Young Scientists in New Fields.” Scientometrics 61, 1: 117128.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wray, K. Brad (2007). Who Has Scientific Knowledge?” Social Epistemology 21, 3: 337347.Google Scholar
Wray, K. Brad (2010a). “Kuhn’s Constructionism.” Perspectives on Science 18, 3: 311327.Google Scholar
Wray, K. Brad (2010b). “Rethinking the Size of Scientific Specialties: Correcting Price’s Estimate.” Scientometrics 83, 2: 471476.Google Scholar
Wray, K. Brad (2011a). “Kuhn and the Discovery of Paradigms.” Philosophy of the Social Sciences 41, 3: 380397.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wray, K. Brad (2011b). Kuhn’s Evolutionary Social Epistemology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wray, K. Brad (2015). “Kuhn’s Social Epistemology and the Sociology of Science.” In Devlin, W. J. and Bokulich, A. (eds.), Kuhn’s Structure of Scientific Revolutions – 50 Years On, pp. 167183. Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
Wray, K. Brad (2016a). “Kuhn’s Influence on the Social Sciences.” In McIntyre, L. and Rosenberg, A. (eds.), The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Social Science, pp. 6575. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Wray, K. Brad (2016b). “The Influence of James B. Conant on Kuhn’s Structure of Scientific Revolutions.” HOPOS: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 6, 1: 123.Google Scholar
Wray, K. Brad (2018). “Thomas Kuhn and the T. S. Kuhn Archives at MIT.” OUPBlog, May 27. Accessed September 10, 2021. https://blog.oup.com/2018/05/thomas-kuhn-archives-mit/.Google Scholar
Wray, K. Brad (2021a). Kuhn’s Intellectual Path: Charting The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Wray, K. Brad (ed.) (2021b). Interpreting Kuhn: Critical Essays. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Wray, K. Brad (2021c). “Reassessing Kuhn’s Theoretical Monism: Addressing the Pluralists’ Challenge.” In Wray, K. Brad (ed.), Interpreting Kuhn: Critical Essays, pp. 222237. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wray, K. Brad, and Andersen, Line E. (2020). “Reporting the Discovery of New Chemical Elements: Working in Different Worlds, Only 25 Years Apart.” Foundations of Chemistry 22, 2: 137146.Google Scholar
Wright, G., van der Heijden, K., Bradfield, R., Burt, G., and Cairns, G. (2004). “Why Organizations Are Slow to Adapt and Change – And What Can Be Done about It.” Journal of General Management 29, 4: 2035.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wu, L., Wang, D., and Evans, J. A. (2019). “Large Teams Develop and Small Teams Disrupt Science and Technology.” Nature 566, 7744: 378382.Google Scholar
Wuchty, S., Jones, B. F., and Uzzi, B. (2007). “The Increasing Dominance of Teams in Production of Knowledge.” Science 316: 10361039.Google Scholar
Wylie, Alison (1999). “Rethinking Unity as a ‘Working Hypothesis’ for Philosophy of Science: How Archaeologists Exploit the Disunities of Science.” Perspectives on Science 7, 3: 293317.Google Scholar
Xu, F., Wu, L., and Evans, J. (2022). “Flat Teams Drive Scientific Innovation.” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 119, 23: e2200927119.Google Scholar
Zachary, G. (1997). Endless Frontier: Vannevar Bush, Engineer of the American Century. New York: Simon and Schuster.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Bibliography
  • Edited by K. Brad Wray, Aarhus Universitet, Denmark
  • Book: Kuhn's <i>The Structure of Scientific Revolutions</i> at 60
  • Online publication: 05 January 2024
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009122696.021
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Bibliography
  • Edited by K. Brad Wray, Aarhus Universitet, Denmark
  • Book: Kuhn's <i>The Structure of Scientific Revolutions</i> at 60
  • Online publication: 05 January 2024
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009122696.021
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Bibliography
  • Edited by K. Brad Wray, Aarhus Universitet, Denmark
  • Book: Kuhn's <i>The Structure of Scientific Revolutions</i> at 60
  • Online publication: 05 January 2024
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009122696.021
Available formats
×