Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-gvvz8 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-22T22:47:33.860Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

5 - Kant, Fichte, and Apperception

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 June 2012

Karl Ameriks
Affiliation:
University of Notre Dame, Indiana
Get access

Summary

FICHTE S LEGACY AND CONTEMPORARY THEORIES OF APPERCEPTION

The Fichtean strand in the development of post-Kantian philosophy is rooted from the very start in a fundamental duality in Fichte's creative use of the basic Kantian notion of the “I think.” On the one hand, when Fichte reinterpreted this “fact of consciousness” as an original “act” (Tathandlung rather than Tatsache), he eventually incorporated it into a popular – but, as I have argued, questionable – radicalization of the doctrine of the “primacy of practical reason,” a radicalization that put pure practical philosophy at the base of all philosophy. On the other hand, Fichte also used his “active” understanding of the “I think” as part of a reconceptualization (especially in his earliest works) of the nature of pure theoretical reason. It is this second side of Fichte's influence, which is independent of action in an ordinary practical or moral sense, that I will be focusing on here.

Although Kant is also well known for having discussed thinking, even in its purest theoretical sense, as an “activity” rooted in the unique spontaneity of subjectivity, he did not directly develop a complete account of subjectivity as such. Following immediately upon Reinhold's focus on a general faculty of representation (Vorstellungsvermogen), Fichte insisted on such an account, and from the beginning he put a special stress on the bare notion of self-consciousness as a synthetic activity of apperception that is indispensable to “scientific philosophy” as such, that is, to anything like a Wissenschaftslehre or systematic theory of subjectivity.

Type
Chapter
Information
Kant and the Fate of Autonomy
Problems in the Appropriation of the Critical Philosophy
, pp. 234 - 264
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2000

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×