Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-s2hrs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-09T07:23:11.338Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false
This chapter is part of a book that is no longer available to purchase from Cambridge Core

27 - Spiritual beings: a Darwinian, cognitive account

from Part V - DEALING WITH SPIRITS

Stewart Guthrie
Affiliation:
Fordham University
Graham Harvey
Affiliation:
Open University, UK
Get access

Summary

SOMETHING OLD AND SOMETHING NEW

Belief in spiritual beings, termed animism by E. B. Tylor, appears culturally universal. Nowadays, animism in the sense of “spirits everywhere” is often associated with people in small-scale societies, such as hunter-gatherers. Jean Piaget (1929, 1954) defined animism somewhat differently: as the attribution of agency to the biologically lifeless. Piaget associated this, as many still do, with children.

However, both associations are too narrow, since animism is common in industrial societies and adults. Moreover, according to Darwin, higher mammals may be animists as well. We all are fundamentally similar, he wrote, and all may see inanimate objects as inhabited by agents, as when his dog, seeing a parasol moved by wind, barked and growled fiercely.

Animism still puzzles us. Where does it come from? How does it relate to religion? Was Darwin's dog an animist? New work on cognition is relevant. A particular view of religion is buttressed by this work and, in turn, provides a context for applying it to animism.

A COGNITIVE THEORY

The underlying argument here first appeared as “A Cognitive Theory of Religion” (Guthrie 1980). Three of that paper's propositions – detecting intentional agents is of special concern, our sensitivities to them are correspondingly well developed, and we inevitably over-detect – have been adopted in varied cognitive approaches to religion. Still, the theory struck some as leaving an important question unanswered: if, as it holds, gods, ghosts and other humanlike agents, including their traces and messages, are anthropomorphisms, why are they frequently represented as invisible and/or immaterial, when actual humans are not? And if invisible, why are they plausible?

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Acumen Publishing
Print publication year: 2013

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×