Hostname: page-component-7bb8b95d7b-fmk2r Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-10-04T22:32:26.300Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

(P.) DESTRÉE Aristote. Poétique (GF n°1637 - Philosophie). Paris: Flammarion, 2021. Pp. 272. €20.43. 9782080712295.

Review products

(P.) DESTRÉE Aristote. Poétique (GF n°1637 - Philosophie). Paris: Flammarion, 2021. Pp. 272. €20.43. 9782080712295.

Part of: Philosophy

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  11 April 2023

Frédérique Woerther*
Affiliation:
CNRS (UMR 8230, Centre Jean Pépin/ENS Ulm)
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Type
Reviews of Books: Philosophy
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of the Society for the Promotion of Hellenic Studies

As a specialist in Aristotle’s Poetics, Pierre Destrée provides an annotated French translation of the text. The translation is accompanied by an introduction; a bibliography that gathers the most useful editions, translations, commentaries and studies, as well as articles that deal with specific issues listed by topic (253–64); and an index of authors and titles (265–70). The translation is a revised version of the annotated translation published in P. Pellegrin (ed.), Œuvres Complètes d’Aristote (Paris 2014), and is based on the OCT edition by Kassel (Oxford 1966). Alist of the lectiones borrowed from other editions is provided (249–51).

The book opens with a long and illuminating introduction (5–83), in which the author gives an overview of the issues raised by the Poetics from antiquity up to the present, and pertinently questions the targeted readership of the treatise. Does Aristotle address future poets? Does he, as a philosopher, set rules to learn how to develop critical thinking skills?

By embedding the text in its historical, cultural and philosophical contexts, Destrée sheds light on several controversial issues. For instance, he raises the question of the value of poetry and its relationship to ethics; he defends the idea that, in spite of what is usually said, Aristotle does not rule out or underestimate the role of staging among the parts of tragedy (18–22); he explains the famous idea according to which poetry is more philosophical than historical by offering a convincing interpretation of the adverb katholou (‘selon une structure générale’, according to a general structure) in Poet. 9 (44–48). Finally, he offers a global explanation of katharsis (67–75). If in the wake of Bernays’ Zwei Abhandlungen über die aristotelische Theorie des Drama (Berlin 1857), ‘medical’ exegetes stated that spectators sought to purge their emotions, ‘ethical’ exegetes read the Poetics as a counterpart of the Ethics and interpreted katharsis in regard to the idea of ‘right measure’ (‘katharsis would be the “purgation” of an emotional overflow, which would allow for the “purification” of piety, or its just measure, which transforms it into a virtue’, my translation from the French, 71). The interpretation of Martha Nussbaum (‘Tragedy and Self-Sufficiency: Plato and Aristotle on Fear and Pity’, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 10 (1992), 107–52) relies on a different translation of katharsis (‘clarification’), which has no relation to the musical katharsis of the Politics. Destrée suggests a more ‘minimalistic’ and ‘global’ interpretation of katharsis (as it also applies to comedy, according to Iamblichus and Proclus) that takes into account Politics VIII and Aristotle’s biological corpus. By inducing fear and pity through the plot (which culminates in recognition), the katharsis of these emotions would be nothing more than their expression, which happens concretely through the tears and shouts of fear and lamentation. Like comedy and music (in the Politics), tragedy would therefore bring a kind of emotional relief which, in addition, does not contradict the goal of these activities, which is leisure.

The French translation is never pedantic and always tends towards transparency. In this respect, the book does not address specialists but targets a broader readership without, however, giving up on precision and scholarship. Destrée avoids literal translations that might be misleading or obscure; for example, according to the context, λέξις is translated as langage (‘language’), mot (‘word’), expression or figure de style (‘figure of speech’). Inote some wonderful solutions: for example, translating Δειλιάς as Poltroniade (‘Cowardiad’, 1448a13), where Destrée maintains the play on the word in French; grave et sérieuse (‘grave and serious’) to translate (or gloss) the adjective σπουδαίος (1449a24), qualifying the kind of action represented by tragedy; intègre (‘upright’) to render χρηστός, defining the first virtue of the characters in tragedy (1454a17); revirement de situation (‘sudden turn’) for περιπέτεια (which indeed does not correspond to the French péripétie, ‘incident’); translating τῇ λέξει συναπεργάζεσθαι (1455a22–23) with ‘when he builds his plots, the poet must help himself by reciting them’ (my translation), where συναπεργάζεσθαι (usually understood as ‘completing the effect [of the emotions]’) and λέξις (usually understood as ‘expression’) are translated according to the explanation in footnote 203: for Destrée refers here to the passage in 1455a30, where lexis designates the attitude of the poet reading his own plot out loud. As a result, Aristotle’s advice is the following: while reciting the text he is composing, the poet must visualize its action.

Reading this beautiful translation is even more pleasant because Destrée adds titles and subtitles to Aristotle’s text, making clear a structure that can be hard to grasp at first sight. The footnotes (171–248) provide historical, cultural and Aristotelian context; they explain and justify, in a more technical but always clear manner, the choices made in the translation