Hostname: page-component-599cfd5f84-8nxqw Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-01-07T07:52:35.272Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Vickrey auction vs BDM: difference in bidding behaviour and the impact of other-regarding motives

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2025

Niall Flynn
Affiliation:
Department of Economics, Innsbruck University, Innsbruck, Austria
Christopher Kah*
Affiliation:
Department of Economics, Innsbruck University, Innsbruck, Austria
Rudolf Kerschbamer
Affiliation:
Department of Economics, Innsbruck University, Innsbruck, Austria
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

In an experiment, we first elicit the distributional preferences of subjects and then let them bid for a lottery, either in a Becker–DeGroot–Marschak (BDM) mechanism or a Vickrey auction (VA). The standard theory predicts that altruistic subjects underbid in the VA—compared to the BDM—while spiteful subjects overbid in the VA. The data do not confirm those predictions. While we observe aggregate underbidding in the VA, the result is not driven by the choices of altruistic subjects.

Type
Original Paper
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This article is distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons license, and indicate if changes were made.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s) 2016

1 Motivation and related literature

Deviations of bids from true valuations in second-price private-value or ‘Vickrey’ auctions (VA; Vickrey Reference Vickrey1961) have been a recurrent theme, see Kagel et al. (Reference Kagel, Harstad and Levin1987) or Kagel and Levin (Reference Kagel and Levin1993). The more recent literature has attributed this finding, at least partially, to spite. Andreoni et al. (Reference Andreoni, Che and Kim2007) find that bids increase in rivals’ (known) valuations, which is consistent with the spite explanation. With unknown valuations but costly signals about the latter, Cooper and Fang (Reference Cooper and Fang2008) also report evidence consistent with the spite hypothesis. If spite, or any form of distributional preferences, is causal for non-sincere bidding in the VA, then deviations of bids from true valuations per construction should be absent in the Becker–DeGroot–Marschak mechanism (BDM; Becker et al. Reference Becker, DeGroot and Marschak1964)—which, under the standard assumptions, is strategically equivalent to the VA. Intuitively, in the BDM, the decision is made in isolation and the outcome has only consequences for the decision maker, whereas in the VA, the outcome is also affected by the behaviour of a rivalling bidder, and by changing the own bid, a subject influences the monetary outcome for both parties involved. To test the impact of distributional preferences on bidding behaviour in the lab, we first elicit the distributional preferences of subjects and then let them bid for lottery tickets either in a BDM or in a VA. We then compare the bids across the two mechanisms. We observe underbidding in the aggregate in the VA, but the experimental data do not confirm our predictions at the individual level.

Our contribution to the existing literature is twofold. First, by keeping all details except for the treatment variation constant across treatments, our experimental design allows for a neat comparison of BDM and VA bids at the aggregate level; and second, by classifying subjects into distributional preference types and comparing their bidding behaviour across mechanisms, our design allows for a clean test of the hypotheses that distributional preferences are causal for a potential treatment difference.Footnote 1 Keeping the number of bidders constant across the two mechanisms seems indispensable, as the probability that a bidder becomes pivotal decreases in the number of rivals and because with a higher probability of pivotality, we expect bidders to perform higher cognitive effort, as their actions are more likely to influence the final monetary payoff distribution.Footnote 2 Keeping instructions comparable across treatments also seems important, because framing effects are known to potentially influence the behaviour in the lab (see Levin et al. Reference Levin, Schneider and Gaeth1998).

2 Experimental setup and theoretical predictions

The experiment consists of two treatments—the BDM treatment and the VA treatment—implemented in a between-subject design and paid under random lottery incentives. Each treatment consists of two parts, and subjects know that only one part is payoff-relevant:Footnote 3

  1. 1. In part 1, we elicit the distributional preferences of subjects with the Equality Equivalence Test (EET) by Kerschbamer (Reference Kerschbamer2015), and then, we expose them to an incentivised survey.

  2. 2. In part 2, a lottery ticket (giving either w = 12 EUR or 0 EUR with equal probabilities) is auctioned off under either the BDM or the VA. Subjects’ initial endowment in part 2 is e = 10 EUR.Footnote 4

EET: This procedure exposes each subject to a number (in our case 10) choices between two allocations, each specifying a payoff for the subject and a payoff for a randomly assigned anonymous second subject. In half of the choices, there is advantageous inequality (the deciding subject is ahead in monetary terms), in the other half, there is disadvantageous inequality (the deciding subject is behind in monetary terms). From the choices of the subject, x- and y-scores measuring the benevolence in the two domains of inequality are calculated. A higher x-score (y-score) means more benevolence in the domain of disadvantageous (advantageous) inequality. These scores jointly determine the distributional type of the subject.

BDM: In the BDM, each subject i is asked to submit a bid b i , then a random price p i is drawn. The allocation rule is:

  1. (i) if b i > p i : subject i buys the lottery ticket at price p i ;

  2. (ii) if b i < p i : subject i keeps the endowment; and

  3. (iii) if b i = p i : either (i) or (ii) is implemented with equal probability.

VA: In the VA, subjects are randomly assigned to pairs. In each pair, the subjects—denoted i and j with i j —are asked to submit bids b i and b j . The allocation rule is:

  1. (i) if b i > b j : subject i buys the lottery ticket at price b j , while subject j keeps the endowment;

  2. (ii) if b i < b j : subject j buys the lottery ticket at price b i , while subject i keeps the endowment; and

  3. (iii) if b i = b j : either (i) or (ii) is implemented with equal probability.

Consider a subject i of distributional type d self , alt , spite , where self stands for selfish, alt for altruistic, and spite for spiteful. Let f i d · be strictly increasing and normalise f i d 0 0 . In the BDM, the unique admissible bid for subject i of type d, b i d , is implicitly defined by

(2.1) 1 2 f i d e + w - b i d + 1 2 f i d e - b i d = f i d ( e ) .

Let ( x i , x j ) denote the final monetary allocation and u i d x i , x j the associated utility of subject i of distributional type d. In the VA, the utility for a selfish subject is—as in the BDM—of the form u i self x i , x j = f i self x i . Thus, b i = b i self is a weakly dominant strategy for selfish in the VA. Sincere bidding is not necessarily a weakly dominant strategy for non-selfish subjects in the VA. An altruist i’s utility increases in the monetary payoff of j, i.e., u i alt x i , x j = f i alt ( x i ) + g i alt ( x j ) , where g i alt ( · ) is strictly increasing. Conversely, under spite, we have u i spite x i , x j = f i spite ( x i ) - g i spite ( x j ) , where g i spite ( · ) is again strictly increasing. Note that our formulation allows for a possible dependence of a subject’s risk preferences on her distributional type. That is, we explicitly allow the f i d · function to depend on the distributional archetype of the subject. We assume that if x j is good (bad), i.e., altruism (spite), i is more (less) risk-averse in j’s monetary gains than in her own. Empirical evidence includes, e.g., Chakravarty et al. (Reference Chakravarty, Harrison, Haruvy and Rutstrom2011) or Mengarelli et al. (Reference Mengarelli, Moretti, Faralla, Vindras and Sirigu2014). In extending the distributional preferences (as defined here for certain outcomes) to a lottery framework, we follow the expected utility approach. As pointed out, among others, by Fudenberg and Levine (Reference Fudenberg and Levine2012) and Saito (Reference Saito2013), an alternative procedure for extending distributional preferences to lotteries is to replace the certain income in the utility function with its expected value. This would allow for ex-ante fairness, while the expected utility extension does not. While the distinction between ex-ante and ex-post fairness is interesting and important, in general, it seems less relevant in our context. The reason is that our focus is on the change in the behaviour of distributional archetypes who have preferences that are monotonic in the material payoff of the other subject (i.e., selfish, altruists, and spiteful), while the ex-ante vs ex-post fairness discussion is most relevant for distributional archetypes who have preferences that are non-monotonic in the material payoff of the other subject (i.e., fairness-minded or inequality averse subjects).Footnote 5 See Fudenberg and Levine (Reference Fudenberg and Levine2012) and Saito (Reference Saito2013) for a discussion.

Restricting ourselves to admissible bids, we can prove (see Appendix A for details):

Proposition 1.

In the VA,

  1. (i) a selfish subject never has an incentive to deviate from b i self ;

  2. (ii) an altruistic subject never has an incentive to overbid relative to b i alt , and might have an incentive to underbid;

  3. (iii) a spiteful subject never has an incentive to underbid relative to b i spite , and might have an incentive to overbid.

From Proposition Footnote 1 and the fact that selfish and altruistic subjects combined comprise the majority in experimental data (see Kerschbamer Reference Kerschbamer2015), we derive:

Theoretical prediction 1. Comparing bids across treatments,

  1. (i) selfish subjects will not change their bids, while altruistic (spiteful) types will underbid (overbid) in VA relative to the BDM;

  2. (ii) in the aggregate, we expect underbidding in the VA relative to the BDM.

3 Results

We conducted all sessions in paper-and-pen at the University of Innsbruck in October and November 2013 and collected n = 320 observations—146 in the BDM and 174 in the VA. We classify subjects as:

  1. (i) selfish, if - 0.5 x score 0.5 and - 0.5 y score 0.5 ;

  2. (ii) altruistic, if x score 0 and y score 0 ;

  3. (iii) spiteful, if x score 0 and y score 0 .Footnote 6

Table 1 reports the mean bid by type and treatment, and the p values for t tests comparing mean bids.Footnote 7 Figure 1 shows the distribution of bids by type and treatment.

Fig. 1 Bids by types across treatments BDM (left) and VA (right)

Table 1 Comparison of mean bid by type and treatment (standard error in parentheses; number of observations in brackets)

n

Mean bid

Mean bid

BDM - VA

p-value

BDM

VA

(t-test)

All

320

4.77

4.18

(0.24)

(0.22)

0.59

0.070

[146]

[174]

(0.32)

Selfish

118

5.12

4.11

(0.35)

(0.38)

1.01

0.054

[65]

[53]

(0.52)

Altruist

231

4.50

4.24

(0.28)

(0.25)

0.26

0.485

[105]

[126]

(0.38)

Spiteful

30

6.43

4.59

(0.68)

(0.81)

1.83

0.100

[14]

[16]

(1.07)

Absolute treatment effect sizes that could have been detected with 80 % power at a 5 % level of significance given our sample sizes and data (values for one-sided tests in parantheses): 0.91 (0.79) for the sample All, 1.5 (1.33) for the subsample Selfish, 1.06 (0.94) for the subsample Altruist, and 2.94 (2.64) for the subsample Spiteful

We observe a difference in aggregate bidding behaviour, which is significant at the 10 % level. Given the relatively large share of altruists in the population, one might be tempted to see the predictions of Proposition Footnote 1 confirmed. However, we cannot reconcile the treatment difference measured at the aggregate level with the data at the individual level. For both selfish and spiteful types, we observe a significant (at the 10 % level) change in bids, while for altruists, there is no significant difference. This contradicts our theoretical predictions.

4 Conclusion

Our experimental design allows for a genuine comparison of BDM and VA, both at the aggregate level and at the level of the distributional type. While we observe a behavioural difference between the two mechanisms at the aggregate level, the difference cannot be explained by a purely consequentialist utility function of the form u i d ( x i , x j ) = f i d ( x i ) ± g i d ( x j ) . Such functions seem to be well suited to explain behaviour in simple decision problems, such as dictator games, but less suited to explain behaviour in market environments, such as the VA.

Acknowledgements

Open access funding provided by University of Innsbruck and Medical University of Innsbruck.

Footnotes

Electronic supplementary material The online version of this article (doi:10.1007/s40881-016-0027-5) contains supplementary material, which is available to authorized users.

We thank Martin Halla, Michael Pfaffermayer, Herbert Stocker, Martin Strobel, Markus Walzl, and two anonymous referees for helpful discussions and suggestions. Financial support from the Austrian Science Fund (FWF) through grant no. P-22669 is gratefully acknowledged.

1 For a comprehensive survey of distributional preferences, see Fehr and Schmidt (Reference Fehr, Schmidt, Kolm and Ythier2006) and the references mentioned therein.

2 Rutstrom (Reference Rutstrom1998) reports that BDM bids being significantly below VA bids. However, the recruiting procedure is not constant across mechanisms and the number of bidders in the VA is not constant across sessions. See Kagel and Levin (Reference Kagel and Levin1993) for a significant effect of increasing the number of bidders in the VA.

3 See Supplementary material Appendix B for the experimental instructions. If part 1 was payoff-relevant, one of the ten choices was paid.

4 We include control questions to overcome possible obstacles caused by these mechanisms.

5 We do not derive a prediction for inequality averse subjects. An inequality averse subject [the most prominent models of inequality aversion are those of Fehr and Schmidt (Reference Fehr and Schmidt1999) and Bolton and Ockenfels (Reference Bolton and Ockenfels2000)] might either underbid or overbid in the VA relative to the BDM depending on whether it expects to be in the domain of advantageous or disadvantageous inequality. Thus, the direction of the deviation of the bid of an inequality averse subject from the BDM benchmark depends on the subject’s expectation which precludes a testable hypothesis.

6 Scores between −0.5 and +0.5 are compatible with selfishness and other types. We classify subjects as selfish whenever they are potentially selfish resulting in "double-counting" several observations.

7 We only include those types for which a prediction as embodied in Proposition Footnote 1 exists. Non-parametric Mann–Whitney tests (not reported here) confirm our results.

References

Andreoni, J., Che, Y. K., Kim, J. (2007). Asymmetric information about rivals types in standard auctions: an experiment. Games and Economic Behavior, 59(2), 240259. 10.1016/j.geb.2006.09.003CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Becker, G. M., DeGroot, M. H., Marschak, J. (1964). Measuring utility by a single-response sequential method. Behavioral Science, 9(3), 226232. 10.1002/bs.3830090304CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bolton, G. E., Ockenfels, A. (2000). ERC: a theory of equity, reciprocity, and competition. American Economic Review, 90(1), 166193. 10.1257/aer.90.1.166CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chakravarty, S., Harrison, G. W., Haruvy, E. E., Rutstrom, E. E. (2011). Are you risk averse over other peoples money? Southern Economic Journal, 77(4), 901913. 10.4284/0038-4038-77.4.901CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cooper, D. J., Fang, H. (2008). Understanding overbidding in second price auctions: An experimental study. The Economic Journal, 118(532), 15721595. 10.1111/j.1468-0297.2008.02181.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fehr, E., Schmidt, K. M. (1999). A theory of fairness, competition, and cooperation. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 114(3), 817868. 10.1162/003355399556151CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fehr, E., & Schmidt, K. M. (2006). The economics of fairness, reciprocity and altruism–experimental evidence and new theories. In Kolm, S. C. & Ythier, J. M. (Eds.), Handbook of the economics of giving, altruism and reciprocity (pp. 615691). Amsterdam: John Benjamins Publishing Company.Google Scholar
Fudenberg, D., Levine, D. K. (2012). Fairness, risk preferences and independence: impossibility theorems. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 81(2), 606612. 10.1016/j.jebo.2011.09.004CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kagel, J. H., Levin, D. (1993). Independent private value auctions: bidder behaviour in first-, second- and third-price auctions with varying numbers of bidders. The Economic Journal, 103(419), 868879. 10.2307/2234706CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kagel, J. H., Harstad, R. M., Levin, D. (1987). Information impact and allocation rules in auctions with affiliated private values: a laboratory study. Econometrica, 55(6), 12751304. 10.2307/1913557CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kerschbamer, R. (2015). The geometry of distributional preferences and a non-parametric identification approach: the equality equivalence test. European Economic Review, 76, 85103. 10.1016/j.euroecorev.2015.01.008CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levin, I. P., Schneider, S. L., Gaeth, G. J. (1998). All frames are not created equal: a typology and critical analysis of framing effects. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 76(2), 149188. 10.1006/obhd.1998.2804CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mengarelli, F., Moretti, L., Faralla, V., Vindras, P., Sirigu, A. (2004). Economic decisions for others: an exception to loss aversion law. PLOS One, 9(1),e85042. 10.1371/journal.pone.0085042CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rutstrom, E. E. (1998). Home-grown values and incentive compatible auction design. International Journal of Game Theory, 27(3), 427441. 10.1007/s001820050082Google Scholar
Saito, K. (2013). Social preferences under risk: equality of opportunity versus equality of outcome. The American Economic Review, 103(7), 30843101. 10.1257/aer.103.7.3084CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vickrey, W. (1961). Counterspeculation, auctions, and competitive sealed tenders. The Journal of Finance, 16(1), 837. 10.1111/j.1540-6261.1961.tb02789.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Figure 0

Fig. 1 Bids by types across treatments BDM (left) and VA (right)

Figure 1

Table 1 Comparison of mean bid by type and treatment (standard error in parentheses; number of observations in brackets)

Supplementary material: File

Flynn et. al. supplementary material

Appendix A and B
Download Flynn et. al. supplementary material(File)
File 194.3 KB
Supplementary material: File

Flynn et. al. supplementary material 1

Flynn et. al. supplementary material 1
Download Flynn et. al. supplementary material 1(File)
File 230.5 KB