Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-dlnhk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-22T17:52:20.680Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Unitary representations of type B rational Cherednik algebras and crystal combinatorics

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  29 September 2021

Emily Norton*
Affiliation:
School of Mathematics, Statistics and Actuarial Science, Sibson Building, Parkwood Road, University of Kent, Canterbury, Kent CT2 7FS
*
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

We compare crystal combinatorics of the level $2$ Fock space with the classification of unitary irreducible representations of type B rational Cherednik algebras to study how unitarity behaves under parabolic restriction. We show that the crystal operators that remove boxes preserve the combinatorial conditions for unitarity, and that the parabolic restriction functors categorifying the crystals send irreducible unitary representations to unitary representations. Furthermore, we find the supports of the unitary representations.

Type
Article
Copyright
© Canadian Mathematical Society 2021

1 Motivation and summary of results

1.1 Motivation

The unitary representations in the category $\mathcal {O}_c(W)$ of a rational Cherednik algebra associated to a complex reflection group W were first introduced and studied by Etingof and Stoica, who classified the unitary irreducible representations for rational Cherednik algebras of symmetric groups $S_n$ [Reference Fishel, Griffeth and Manosalva11]. This classification was extended by Griffeth to the wreath product groups $W=G(\ell ,1,n)$ , which include $S_n$ as $G(1,1,n)$ and the Weyl group $B_n$ as $G(2,1,n)$ [Reference Jacon and Lecouvey19]. The classification for $G(\ell ,1,n)$ is inductive and complicated, but for $B_n$ , there exist closed conditions for unitarity in terms of contents of certain boxes in bipartitions [Reference Jacon and Lecouvey19, Corollaries 8.4 and 8.5]. The goal of this paper is to study how these conditions interact with the crystal combinatorics of level $2$ Fock spaces, which controls the cuspidal data of the irreducible representations in $\mathcal {O}_c(B_n)$ for appropriate parameters c.

Unitary representations stand out from the rest of the representations in $\mathcal {O}_c(W)$ by their relative tractability. In many cases, they are known to possess closed-form, multiplicity-free character formulas in terms of a saturated subset of the poset of lowest weights [Reference Bowman, Norton and Simental7, Reference Gerber12, Reference Shelley-Abrahamson27], which may often be elegantly expressed using affine type A alcove geometry [Reference Berest, Etingof and Ginzburg4, Reference Bowman, Norton and Simental7]. It is possible to write explicit bases for the unitary representations or for the corresponding representations of closely related algebras such as the Morita equivalent diagrammatic Cherednik algebra or the Hecke algebra. This has been done in type $G(\ell ,1,n)$ using a variety of methods and perspectives. Griffeth constructed a basis of any unitary irreducible Cherednik algebra representation using nonsymmetric Jack polynomials [Reference Jacon and Lecouvey19, Theorem 1.1]. Using the methods of Griffeth [Reference Griffeth, Gusenbauer, Juteau and Lanini18] in type A, Gorsky, Simental, and Vazirani recently showed how such a basis for $L(\mathsf {triv})$ provides a basis for the $\mathbb {C}^\times $ -equivariant cohomology of a parabolic Hilbert scheme [Reference Griffeth17]. On the finite-dimensional algebra side, Bowman, the author, and Simental constructed bases valid over a ground field of any characteristic for the unitary modules of Hecke and diagrammatic Cherednik algebras of type A and, for certain parameters, type $G(\ell ,1,n)$ [Reference Bowman, Norton and Simental7].

At the categorical level, the unitary irreducible representations in type A, and for certain parameters, type $G(\ell ,1,n)$ , have been proved to possess resolutions by complexes of direct sums of standard modules [Reference Bezrukavnikov and Etingof1, Reference Bowman, Hazi and Norton6, Reference Bowman, Norton and Simental7]. Such resolutions, known in the literature as Bernstein-Gelfand-Gelfand (BGG) resolutions, categorify character formulas via the Euler characteristic of the complex. Let us briefly discuss the history of this problem. Berest, Etingof, and Ginzburg constructed the BGG resolution of $L(\mathsf {triv})\in \mathcal {O}_{\frac {1}{h}}(W)$ when W is a real reflection group, $\mathsf {triv} $ is the trivial representation of W, and h is the Coxeter number of W [Reference Bezrukavnikov and Etingof1]. Based on Ruff’s character formula for the unitary representations of the Hecke algebra of the symmetric group [Reference Shelley-Abrahamson27], Berkesch-Zamaere, Griffeth, and Sam conjectured the existence of BGG resolutions of all unitary irreducible representations in type $A_{n-1}$ for parameter $c=\frac {1}{e}$ , $2\leq e\leq n$ [Reference Bowman and Cox2]. Bowman, the author, and Simental proved this conjecture in [Reference Bowman, Norton and Simental7], additionally constructing the resolutions of unitary irreducible representations in type $G(\ell ,1,n)$ for specific types of parameters and thus providing the first known closed character formulas of these representations. Moreover, one might consider not just a unitary representation by itself, but the whole Serre subcategory or subquotient category determined by the saturated subset of the poset of lowest weights appearing in its character. In type A, Bowman, Cox, and Hazi have recently shown that this subcategory of $\mathcal {O}_{\frac {1}{e}}(S_n)$ is equivalent to a truncation of an Elias–Williamson category of parabolic Soergel bimodules of type $A_{e'}\subset \widetilde {A}_{e'}$ for some $e'\leq e$ [Reference Berkesch Zamaere, Griffeth and Sam5].

In type A, the BGG resolutions of unitary modules are invariant under Chuang and Miyachi’s “runner removal Morita equivalences” [Reference Chuang and Rouquier8], equivalently, under dilation of e-alcoves in the affine type A alcove geometry determining the maps in the complex by the results of Bowman and Cox [Reference Berest, Etingof and Ginzburg4]. Consequently, the BGG resolutions and hence the character formulas of all unitary irreducible modules for type A Cherednik algebras at all parameters are actually classified by a subset of them, the unitary modules $L_{\frac {1}{e}}(e^m)$ labeled by rectangles with e columns, where $c=\frac {1}{e}$ is the parameter for the Cherednik algebra $H_c(S_n)$ and $n=em$ for some $m\geq 1$ [Reference Bowman, Norton and Simental7]. All other characters and resolutions of unitary irreducible representations in type A are simply obtained by relabeling partitions via an easy combinatorial procedure. The rectangles $(e^m)$ have an interesting interpretation in terms of the combinatorics of certain simply directed graphs called crystals whose vertices are partitions.

This hints that it may be interesting to study the interaction of the combinatorial conditions for unitarity with crystal combinatorics on higher-level Fock spaces. In this paper, we carry out this comparison for the rational Cherednik algebra of $B_n$ and the level $2$ Fock space. Perhaps the patterns revealed in this study may lead to a more conceptual description of the unitary irreducible representations in $\mathcal {O}_c(G(\ell ,1,n))$ at parameters c such that $\bigoplus _n\mathcal {O}_c(G(\ell ,1,n)$ categorifies a level $\ell $ Fock space. We also hope that it will help to suggest the different types of alcove geometries we need to consider to give an attractive solution to the problem of constructing BGG resolutions of unitary representations in $\mathcal {O}_c(B_n)$ , and ultimately in $\mathcal {O}_c(G(\ell ,1,n))$ .

1.2 The finite-dimensional unitary representations

Finite-dimensional representations play the role of cuspidals in the representation theory of rational Cherednik algebras. A natural first question, and the starting point of this paper, is which unitary representations of these algebras are also finite-dimensional? The answer can be deduced from a result of Montarani on wreath product algebras [Reference Ruff25] together with the a criterion of Etingof–Stoica [Reference Fishel, Griffeth and Manosalva11]. Montarani studied symplectic reflection algebras associated to wreath products $G(\ell ,1,n)$ , which includes the rational Cherednik algebra of $B_n=G(2,1,n)$ . Montarani proved that if an irreducible $G(\ell ,1,n)$ -representation $\underline {\lambda }$ extends to a representation of a rational Cherednik algebra at some parameters, then $\underline {\lambda }$ is a rectangle concentrated in a single component, and she gave the formula for the parameters for which it extends depending on the height and width of the rectangle [Reference Ruff25]. Etingof and Stoica proved that for the rational Cherednik algebra of a real reflection group W, if $L(\underline {\lambda })$ is unitary, then $L(\underline {\lambda })$ is in addition finite-dimensional if and only if $L(\underline {\lambda })$ is equal to the irreducible W-representation $\underline {\lambda }$ [Reference Fishel, Griffeth and Manosalva11, Proposition 4.1].

Let $(e,\underline {s})$ be a parameter for a level $2$ Fock space, so $e\in \mathbb {Z}_{\geq 2}$ , and $\underline {s}=(s_1,s_2)\in \mathbb {Z}^2$ . To the parameter $(e,\underline {s})$ , we can associate a rational Cherednik algebra $H_{e,\underline {s}}(B_n)$ and its category $\mathcal {O}$ of representations, denoted $\mathcal {O}_{e,\underline {s}}(n)$ . This is the case we will be concerned with throughout this paper, and the representation theory of rational Cherednik algebras in type B can, to a great extent, be reduced to this case (or to the even simpler case of a product of type A rational Cherednik algebras). It is important to note that the property of unitarity does not behave well under functors which change parameters in a way inducing Morita equivalences on the categories of representations. However, the character-theoretical and homological properties, which one usually wants to deduce from unitarity, are preserved. Under our choice of parameters, the criterion for finite-dimensional representations to be unitary is given as follows.

Theorem 1.1 [Reference Ruff25]

Let $\underline {\lambda }$ be a bipartition, and let $(e,\underline {s})\in \mathbb {Z}_{\geq 2}\times \mathbb {Z}^2$ be a parameter for the Fock space. The irreducible representation $L(\underline {\lambda })\in \mathcal {O}_{e,\underline {s}}(n)$ is both unitary and finite-dimensional if and only if (i) $\underline {\lambda }=(\lambda ,\emptyset )$ or $\underline {\lambda }=(\emptyset ,\lambda )$ for some rectangle $\lambda $ , and (ii) the parameter $(e,\underline {s})$ satisfies the following conditions depending on $\underline {\lambda }$ , where r is the number of rows and q the number of columns of $\lambda $ , and $s=s_2-s_1$ :

  1. (1) if $\underline {\lambda }=(\lambda ,\emptyset )$ , then $r-q=s-e$ ;

  2. (2) if $\underline {\lambda }=(\emptyset ,\lambda )$ , then $r-q=-s$ .

1.3 Parabolic restriction and supports of unitary representations in type B

The main results of this paper concern the behavior of the unitary representations in $\mathcal {O}_c(W)$ under the parabolic restriction functor ${{}^{\mathcal {O}}\operatorname {Res}}^W_{W'}:\mathcal {O}_c(W)\rightarrow \mathcal {O}_c(W')$ defined in [Reference Bowman, Cox and Hazi3], where $W'\subset W$ is a parabolic subgroup. We are interested in the following conjecture of Etingof.

Conjecture 1.2 (Etingof’s conjecture on restriction of unitary representations)

If L is a unitary irreducible representation in $\mathcal {O}_c(W)$ , and $W'\subset W$ is a parabolic subgroup of W, then ${{}^{\mathcal {O}}\operatorname {Res}}^W_{W'} L$ is unitary.

Recently, Shelley-Abrahamson extended Etingof’s conjecture to consider arbitrary signatures [Reference Shelley-Abrahamson30, Section 6.3].

The main theorem of this paper is a proof using the combinatorics of the $\widehat {\mathfrak {sl}}_e$ -crystal that the parabolic restriction functor ${{}^{\mathcal {O}}\operatorname {Res}}^n_{n-1}:={{}^{\mathcal {O}}\operatorname {Res}}^{B_n}_{B_{n-1}}:\mathcal {O}_{e,\underline {s}}(n)\rightarrow \mathcal {O}_{e,\underline {s}}(n-1)$ takes unitary irreducible representations to unitary representations or to $0$ , as well as the analogous statement for the functors corresponding to the operators in the $\mathfrak {sl}_{\infty }$ -crystal that remove e-strips.

Remark 1.3 Let p and q be the depths of $\underline {\lambda }^t$ in the $\widehat {\mathfrak {sl}}_e$ -crystal and the $\mathfrak {sl}_{\infty }$ -crystal on $\mathcal {F}_{e,\underline {s}}^2$ , respectively. Then, $p+q$ is the dimension of support of $L(\underline {\lambda })$ [Reference Bowman, Cox and Hazi3, Reference Montarani23, Reference Wilcox28, Reference Shan and Vasserot29]. We note that in the case that $L(\underline {\lambda })$ has full support, i.e., $\underline {\lambda }^t$ has depth $n=|\underline {\lambda }|$ in the $\widehat {\mathfrak {sl}}_e$ -crystal on $\mathcal {F}_{e,\underline {s}}^2$ , then the first statement of Theorem 1.4 should follow from the results of [Reference Shelley-Abrahamson30]. We thank Griffeth for pointing this out. However, there are other unitary representations floating around that are not sent to $0$ by ${{}^{\mathcal {O}}\operatorname {Res}}^n_{n-1}$ but that do not have full support either. In advance of doing the work, we cannot say too much about this, so we do not try to take any shortcuts.

Theorem 1.4 Let $L(\underline {\lambda })\in \mathcal {O}_{e,\underline {s}}(n)$ be a unitary irreducible representation. Then, ${{}^{\mathcal {O}}\operatorname {Res}}^n_{n-1}L(\underline {\lambda })$ is unitary or $0$ . Moreover, if $\underline {\lambda }^t$ has nonzero depth in the $\mathfrak {sl}_{\infty }$ -crystal, then ${{}^{\mathcal {O}}\operatorname {Res}}^{B_n}_{B_{n-e}\times S_e}L(\underline {\lambda })$ is a unitary irreducible representation, and ${{}^{\mathcal {O}}\operatorname {Res}}^n_{n-1}L(\underline {\lambda })=0$ .

By standard properties of unitary modules, ${{}^{\mathcal {O}}\operatorname {Res}}^n_{n-1}L(\underline {\lambda })$ is then semisimple, but our argument goes the other way around: semisimplicity is part and parcel of the proof. We show that each direct summand $\mathrm {E}_i$ of the functor ${{}^{\mathcal {O}}\operatorname {Res}}^{n}_{n-1}$ sends a unitary $L(\underline {\lambda })$ to an irreducible representation or to $0$ , and we show that $\tilde {e}_i$ , the $\widehat {\mathfrak {sl}}_e$ -crystal operator sending $\underline {\lambda }^t$ to $\underline {\mu }^t$ if $L(\underline {\mu })$ is in the head of $\mathrm {E}_i L(\underline {\lambda })$ , sends bipartitions labeling unitary irreducible representations to bipartitions labeling unitary irreducible representations. These two steps combined imply that ${{}^{\mathcal {O}}\operatorname {Res}}^n_{n-1}$ preserves unitarity. Along with the corresponding statements for the $\mathfrak {sl}_{\infty }$ -crystal and the functor associated to it, these steps are carried out in Propositions 3.1, 3.3, and 3.8.

Our methods are combinatorial. We never interact with the definition of unitary representation; we only use the combinatorial classification of bipartitions labeling irreducible representations that are unitary, the combinatorial rules governing the two crystals, and some very easy representation-theoretic consequences of the categorical actions on $\bigoplus \limits _n\mathcal {O}_{e,\underline {s}}(n)$ connecting the two crystals to parabolic restriction functors [Reference Chuang, Miyachi, Gyoja, Nakajima, Shinoda, Shoji and Tanisaki9, Reference Wilcox28, Reference Shan and Vasserot29]. As [Reference Jacon and Lecouvey19, Corollaries 8.4 and 8.5] give a case-by-case classification of bipartitions labeling unitary representations, our proofs are an exhausting case-by-case analysis as well. We have tried to include some pictures and examples along the way to improve the readability. The story we are trying to tell is one in which unitary modules may be studied in terms of certain paths in crystal graphs originating from special multipartitions, a story in which functional analysis plays no role. We expect this line of inquiry to lead to sharp character formulas similar to the e-abacus formula in type A discovered by Ruff [Reference Shelley-Abrahamson27] which will be valid for the diagrammatic Cherednik algebra and the Hecke algebra over fields of arbitrary characteristic.

As a corollary of the work done in the proof of Proposition 3.1 together with Theorem 1.1, we can classify the supports of all unitary irreducible representations in $\mathcal {O}_{e,\underline {s}}(n)$ . The module $L(\underline {\lambda })$ is a module over the subalgebra $\mathbb {C}[x_1,\ldots , x_n]$ of the rational Cherednik algebra of $B_n$ . The support of $L(\underline {\lambda })$ is defined to be its support as a $\mathbb {C}[x_1,\ldots , x_n]$ -module. As explained in [Reference Montarani23], the support of $L(\underline {\lambda })$ is of the form $B_n\mathfrak {h}^{W'}$ where $\mathfrak {h}\cong \mathbb {C}^n$ is the reflection representation of $B_n$ and $W'\subseteq B_n$ is a subgroup of the form $W'=B_{n'}\times S_{e}^{ m}\times S_1^{ p}\cong B_{n'}\times S_e^{m}$ such that $n=n'+em+p$ . The parabolic subgroup $W'$ is then minimal with respect to the property that ${{}^{\mathcal {O}}\operatorname {Res}}^{B_n}_{W'}L(\underline {\lambda })\neq 0$ , and ${{}^{\mathcal {O}}\operatorname {Res}}^{B_n}_{W'}L(\underline {\lambda })$ is a finite-dimensional representation in $\mathcal {O}_c(W')$ [Reference Bowman, Cox and Hazi3]. The additional data of the isotypy class $L(\underline {\mu })$ of ${{}^{\mathcal {O}}\operatorname {Res}}^{B_n}_{W'}L(\underline {\lambda })$ together with $W'$ give the cuspidal support of $L(\underline {\lambda })$ as the pair $(L(\underline {\mu }),W')$ . Losev showed that the number m of copies of $S_e$ in $W'$ is equal to the depth of $\underline {\lambda }^t$ in the $\mathfrak {sl}_{\infty }$ -crystal on $\mathcal {F}_{e,\underline {s}}^2$ , and the number p of copies of $S_1\cong \{1\}$ in $W'$ is equal to the depth of $\underline {\lambda }^t$ in the $\widehat {\mathfrak {sl}}_e$ -crystal on $\mathcal {F}^2_{e,\underline {s}}$ [Reference Montarani23].

Corollary 1.5 The set of parabolic subgroups $W'\subseteq B_n$ such that $B_n\mathfrak {h}^{W'}$ is the support of some unitary representation $L(\underline {\lambda })\in \mathcal {O}_{e,\underline {s}}(n)$ is given by:

  • $W'=\{1\}$ ,

  • $W'=S_e^m$ if and only if $n=em$ for some $m\in \mathbb {N}$ ,

  • for every $q,r\in \mathbb {N}$ such that $rq\leq n$ and $r-q=s_2-s_1-e$ , $W'=B_{rq}$ ,

  • for every $q,r\in \mathbb {N}$ such that $rq+em=n$ for some $m\in \mathbb {N}$ and $r-q=s_2-s_1-e$ , $W'=B_{rq}\times S_e^m$ ,

  • for every $q,r\in \mathbb {N}$ such that $rq\leq n$ and $r-q=-(s_2-s_1)$ , $W'=B_{rq}$ ,

  • for every $q,r\in \mathbb {N}$ such that $rq+em=n$ for some $m\in \mathbb {N}$ and $r-q=-(s_2-s_1)$ , $W'=B_{rq}\times S_e^m$ .

2 Background and notation

2.1 Bipartitions, the level $2$ Fock space, and the category $\mathcal {O}_{e, \underline {s}}(n)$

A partition is a finite, nonincreasing sequence of positive integers: $\lambda =(\lambda _1,\lambda _2,\dots ,\lambda _r)$ such that $\lambda _1\geq \lambda _2\geq \dots \geq \lambda _r> 0$ . We use the notation $\emptyset $ for the empty sequence $()$ when $r=0$ . Let $\mathcal {P}=\{\lambda \mid \lambda \text { is a partition}\}$ be the set of all partitions. We use the notation $\emptyset $ for the empty sequence $()$ when $r=0$ . For a partition $\lambda $ , we write $|\lambda |=\sum _{i=1}^r\lambda _i$ , and we identify $\lambda $ with its Young diagram, the upper-left-justified array of $|\lambda |$ boxes in the plane with $\lambda _1$ boxes in the top row, $\lambda _2$ boxes in the second row from the top,…, $\lambda _r$ boxes in the rth row from the top. If a box of $\lambda $ is in row x and column y, then its content is defined to be $\mathrm {ct}(b):=y-x$ . A partition $\lambda $ is a rectangle if and only if $\lambda _1=\lambda _2=\dots =\lambda _r$ . The transpose of $\lambda $ , denoted $\lambda ^t$ , is defined to be the partition whose Young diagram has $\lambda _1$ boxes in the leftmost column, $\lambda _2$ boxes in the second column from the left, and so on.

Let $B_n$ be the type B Weyl group of rank n, also known as the hyperoctahedral group or the complex reflection group $G(2,1,n)$ . Then, $B_n\cong \left (\mathbb {Z}/2\mathbb {Z}\right )^n\rtimes S_n$ , and the irreducible representations of $B_n$ over $\mathbb {C}$ are labeled by bipartitions of n defined as

$$ \begin{align*} \mathcal{P}^2(n):= \{\underline{\lambda}=(\lambda^1,\lambda^2)\mid \;\lambda^1,\lambda^2\in\mathcal{P}\text{ and }|\lambda^1|+|\lambda^2|=n\}. \end{align*} $$

We call $\lambda ^1$ and $\lambda ^2$ the components of $\underline {\lambda }$ . Given $\underline {\lambda }=(\lambda ^1,\lambda ^2)$ , we define $\underline {\lambda }^t=((\lambda ^1)^t,(\lambda ^2)^t)$ . Set

$$ \begin{align*} \mathcal{P}^2=\bigcup_{n\geq 0}\mathcal{P}^2(n), \end{align*} $$

and fix $e\in \mathbb {N}_{\geq 2}$ and $\underline {s}=(s_1,s_2)\in \mathbb {Z}^2$ .

The level $2$ Fock space

$$ \begin{align*} \mathcal{F}^2_{e,\underline{s}}=\bigoplus_{\underline{\mu}\in\mathcal{P}^2}\mathbb{C}|\underline{\mu},\underline{s}\rangle \end{align*} $$

depending on the parameter $(e,\underline {s})$ has formal basis given by charged bipartitions $|\underline {\mu },\underline {s}\rangle $ , which are simply bipartitions $\underline {\mu }$ with the additional data of the charge $\underline {s}$ . A charged bipartition $|\underline {\mu },\underline {s}\rangle $ may be identified with the pair of Young diagrams for $\mu ^1$ and $\mu ^2$ with the additional data that each box $b\in \underline {\mu }$ is filled with its charged content, defined as $\widetilde {\mathrm {ct}}(b)=s_j+y-x$ , where b belongs to row x and column y of $\mu ^j$ for $j\in \{1,2\}$ . Let $s=s_2-s_1$ . The algebra we will associate to the level $2$ Fock space depends only on e and s, so unless otherwise noted we will always take $\underline {s}=(0,s)$ for some $s\in \mathbb {Z}$ .

Convention 2.1 To $\underline {\lambda }\in \mathcal {P}^2$ , we will associate the charged bipartition $|\underline {\lambda }^t,\underline {s}\rangle \in \mathcal {F}^2_{e,\underline {s}}$ .

The rational Cherednik algebra is a deformation of $\mathbb {C}[x_1,\dots ,x_n,y_1,\dots ,y_n]\rtimes \mathbb {C} B_n$ with multiplication depending on a pair of parameters $(c,d)\in \mathbb {C}^2$ [Reference Etingof and Ginzburg10, Reference Jacon and Lecouvey19]. We will be interested in unitary representations, and for these to make sense, c and d must be real numbers. So, from now on, we assume $(c,d)\in \mathbb {R}^2$ . We write $H_{e,\underline {s}}(B_n)$ for the rational Cherednik algebra depending on parameters $(c,d)$ as defined in [Reference Jacon and Lecouvey19, equation (2.12)], where c and d are determined from the Fock space parameter $(e,\underline {s})$ by the formulas [Reference Shan and Vasserot29]:

(2.2) $$ \begin{align} c=\frac{1}{e},\qquad d=-\frac{1}{2}+\frac{s}{e}, \end{align} $$

where, as above, $\underline {s}=(s_1,s_2)$ and $s=s_2-s_1$ . Thus, the rational Cherednik algebra determined from the Fock space parameter $(e,\underline {s})$ is the same as the rational Cherednik algebra determined from the Fock space parameter $(e,\underline {s}+(a,a))$ for any $a\in \mathbb {Z}$ . This justifies our fixing $\underline {s}=(0,s)$ once and for all.

The algebra $H_{e,\underline {s}}(B_n)$ has a category $\mathcal {O}_{e,\underline {s}}(n)$ of representations which in particular contains all finite-dimensional representations [Reference Griffeth16]. The irreducible representations in $\mathcal {O}_{e,\underline {s}}(n)$ are labeled by $\mathcal {P}^2(n)$ and denoted $L(\underline {\lambda })$ for $\underline {\lambda }\in \mathcal {P}^2(n)$ [Reference Griffeth16]. The irreducible representation $L(\underline {\lambda })$ comes with a nondegenerate contravariant Hermitian form, and $L(\underline {\lambda })$ is called unitary if this form is positive definite [Reference Fishel, Griffeth and Manosalva11]. The unitary $L(\underline {\lambda })$ were classified combinatorially by Griffeth [Reference Jacon and Lecouvey19, Corollary 8.4]. In fact, he considers arbitrary parameters $(c,d)\in \mathbb {R}^2$ without any reference to the Fock space. It is known that the resulting category $\mathcal {O}$ is equivalent to either the one arising from a level $2$ Fock space as above, or to a direct sum of tensor products of category $\mathcal {O}$ ’s for rational Cherednik algebras of symmetric groups [Reference Shan26, Theorem 6.3]. In this paper, we are focused on the more interesting case, when the Grothendieck group of $\mathcal {O}$ is a level $2$ Fock space. The other case leaves little room for finite-dimensional unitary modules due to the paucity of finite-dimensional modules in type A (only the row or column can ever be finite-dimensional, and this happens only when the parameter is rational with denominator equal to the number of boxes [Reference Bezrukavnikov and Etingof1]). Similarly, all the questions we are concerned with in this paper—restriction of the unitary representations, their positions in the crystals on the Fock space, and their supports—are known in type A, hence known in the case of a tensor product of type A categories.

The element $\sum _{i=1}^n x_iy_i+y_ix_i\in H_{e,\underline {s}}(B_n)$ acts on the irreducible $\mathbb {C} B_n$ -representation $\underline {\lambda }$ , the lowest weight space of $L(\underline {\lambda })$ , by a scalar $c_{\underline {\lambda }}$ . Using the formula given in [Reference Jimbo, Misra, Miwa and Okado20, Section 5.1] and then correcting for the renormalization introduced in that formula, we have the following formula for $c_{\underline {\lambda }}$ in terms of the parameter $(e,\underline {s})$ :

$$ \begin{align*} c_{\underline{\lambda}}=|\lambda^1|+\frac{s}{e}\left(|\lambda^2|-|\lambda^1|\right)-\frac{2}{e}\sum_{b\in\underline{\lambda}}\mathrm{ct}(b), \end{align*} $$

where the sum runs over all boxes b in $\underline {\lambda }$ . The category $\mathcal {O}_{e,\underline {s}}(n)$ is a lowest weight category (i.e., a “highest weight category” but with lowest instead of highest weights) with order given by $\underline {\lambda }\prec \underline {\mu }$ if and only if $c_{\underline {\lambda }}< c_{\underline {\mu }}$ . In particular, if $[\Delta (\underline {\lambda }):L(\underline {\mu })]>0$ , then $c_{\underline {\lambda }}<c_{\underline {\mu }}$ or $\underline {\lambda }=\underline {\mu }$ . The head of $\Delta (\underline {\lambda })$ is $L(\underline {\lambda })$ , and $[\Delta (\underline {\lambda }):L(\underline {\lambda })]=1$ .

By abuse of notation, write $\underline {\lambda }$ for the irreducible $B_n$ -representation labeled by the bipartition $\underline {\lambda }$ . Write $\mathfrak {h}^\ast $ for the reflection representation of $B_n$ .

Lemma 2.3 [Reference Fishel, Griffeth and Manosalva11]

A unitary representation $L(\underline {\lambda })$ is finite-dimensional if and only if $L(\underline {\lambda })=\underline {\lambda }$ . The statement $L(\underline {\lambda })=\underline {\lambda }$ holds if and only if $c_{\underline {\lambda }}=0$ , and for every irreducible constituent $\underline {\mu }$ of the $B_n$ -representation $\mathfrak {h}^\ast \otimes \underline {\lambda }$ , we have $c_{\underline {\mu }}=1$ .

The Fock space $\mathcal {F}^2_{e,\underline {s}}$ comes endowed with the structure of an $\widehat {\mathfrak {sl}}_e$ -crystal [Reference Losev22] as well as an exotic structure of an $\mathfrak {sl}_{\infty }$ -crystal [Reference Gerber and Norton13, Reference Ginzburg, Guay, Opdam and Rouquier14, Reference Montarani23, Reference Shan and Vasserot29], and the combinatorial formulas for both actions depend on $\underline {s}$ and e. A crystal is a certain directed graph with at most one arrow between any two vertices. The vertices of both the $\widehat {\mathfrak {sl}}_e$ - and the $\mathfrak {sl}_{\infty }$ -crystals are $\{|\underline {\lambda }^t,\underline {s}\rangle \mid \underline {\lambda }\in \mathcal {P}^2\}$ . We call $|\underline {\lambda }^t,\underline {s}\rangle $ a source vertex in a crystal if it has no incoming arrow. These crystals can be derived from a realization of $\mathcal {F}^2_{e,\underline {s}}$ as the Grothendieck group of

$$ \begin{align*} \mathcal{O}_{e,\underline{s}}:=\bigoplus_{n\geq 0}\mathcal{O}_{e,\underline{s}}(n), \end{align*} $$

where $\mathcal {O}_{e,\underline {s}}(n)$ is the category $\mathcal {O}$ of the rational Cherednik algebra of $B_n$ with parameters $(c,d)$ determined by the Fock space parameter $(e,\underline {s})$ as in equation (2.2). The $\widehat {\mathfrak {sl}}_e$ -crystal on the Fock space arises via a categorical action of $\widehat {\mathfrak {sl}}_e$ on $\mathcal {O}_{e,\underline {s}}$ ; the Chevalley generators $f_i$ and $e_i$ act by i-induction and i-restriction functors, direct summands of the parabolic induction and restriction functors between $\mathcal {O}_{e,\underline {s}}(n)$ and $\mathcal {O}_{e,\underline {s}}(n+1)$ [Reference Wilcox28]. Furthermore, there is a Heisenberg algebra action on $\mathcal {O}_{e,\underline {s}}$ relevant for describing branching of irreducible representations with respect to categories $\mathcal {O}$ attached to parabolic subgroups of the form $B_m\times S_e^{\times k}$ [Reference Shan and Vasserot29]. The categorical Heisenberg action gives rise to an $\mathfrak {sl}_{\infty }$ -crystal structure on $\mathcal {F}^2_{e,\underline {s}}$ whose arrows add a certain collection of e boxes at a time to a bipartition [Reference Montarani23]. The $\mathfrak {sl}_{\infty }$ -crystal operators commute with the $\widehat {\mathfrak {sl}}_e$ -crystal operators [Reference Gerber and Norton13].

Theorem 2.4 [Reference Shan and Vasserot29]

The irreducible representation $L(\underline {\lambda })\in \mathcal {O}_{e,\underline {s}}(n)$ is finite-dimensional if and only if $\underline {\lambda }^t$ is a source vertex for both the $\widehat {\mathfrak {sl}}_e$ -crystal and the $\mathfrak {sl}_{\infty }$ -crystal on $\mathcal {F}^2_{e,\underline {s}}$ .

In the next two sections, we recall the combinatorial rules for these crystals.

2.2 The $\widehat {\mathfrak {sl}}_e$ -crystal

Let $\mu \in \mathcal {P}^2$ be a bipartition. A box $b\in \underline {\mu }$ is said to be removable if $\underline {\mu }\setminus \{b\}\in \mathcal {P}^2$ . Similarly, an addable box of $\underline {\mu }$ is a box $a\notin \mu $ such that $\mu \cup \{a\}\in \mathcal {P}^2$ .

The generators $e_i$ and $f_i$ of $\widehat {\mathfrak {sl}}_e$ , $i\in \mathbb {Z}/e\mathbb {Z}$ , act on $\mathcal {O}_{e,\underline {s}}$ by biadjoint, exact functors $\mathsf {E}_i$ and $\mathsf {F}_i$ that are direct summands of parabolic induction and restriction functors [Reference Wilcox28]. We will only use the functors $\mathsf {E}_i$ , which satisfy:

$$ \begin{align*} {{}^{\mathcal{O}}\operatorname{Res}}^{B_n}_{B_{n-1}}\simeq \bigoplus_{i\in\mathbb{Z}/e\mathbb{Z}}\mathsf{E}_i. \end{align*} $$

Applying $\mathsf {E}_i$ to a standard module $\Delta (\underline {\lambda }):=H_{(e,\underline {s})}(n)\otimes _{\mathbb {C}[\mathfrak {h}]}\underline {\lambda }$ , where $\mathfrak {h}$ acts by $0$ on $\underline {\lambda }$ , we get a $\Delta $ -filtered module $\mathsf {E}_i\Delta (\underline {\lambda })$ whose standard subquotients are all those $\Delta (\underline {\mu })$ where $|\underline {\mu }^t,\underline {s}\rangle \in \mathcal {F}_{e,\underline {s}}^2$ is obtained from $|\underline {\lambda }^t,\underline {s}\rangle $ by removing a box of charged content $i\mod e$ (a “removable i-box”) [Reference Wilcox28]:

$$ \begin{align*} [\mathsf{E}_i\Delta(\underline{\lambda})]=\sum_{|\underline{\mu}^t,\underline{s}\rangle=|\underline{\lambda}^t\setminus \{i-\mathrm{box}\},\underline{s}\rangle}[\Delta(\underline{\mu})]. \end{align*} $$

If $|\underline {\lambda }^t,\underline {s}\rangle $ has no removable i-box, then $\mathsf {E}_i\Delta (\underline {\lambda })=0$ . On irreducible modules, $\mathsf {E}_i$ sends $L(\underline {\lambda })$ either to $0$ or to an indecomposable module $\mathsf {E}_iL(\underline {\lambda })$ whose head and socle are simple and equal to $L((\tilde {e}_i(\underline {\lambda }^t)^t)$ [Reference Wilcox28]. The charged bipartition $|\tilde {e}_i(\underline {\lambda }^t),\underline {s}\rangle $ is defined as $|\underline {\lambda }^t,\underline {s}\rangle $ minus a certain “good removable i-box” when $\mathsf {E}_iL(\underline {\lambda })$ is nonzero, and $0$ otherwise.

Let us recall the rule for finding the good removable i-box [Reference Losev22]. Order all of the removable and addable i-boxes in $|\underline {\lambda }^t,\underline {s}\rangle $ according to increasing order of charged content, with a box in Component $1$ being considered as bigger than a box of the same charged content in Component $2$ . This produces a totally ordered list. Then, recursively cancel all occurrences of a removable box immediately followed by an addable box in the list. The good removable i-box, if it exists, is then the smallest removable i-box remaining after no more cancellations are possible. Likewise, the good addable i-box is the largest addable i-box remaining. The $\widehat {\mathfrak {sl}}_e$ -crystal is then defined to be the simple directed $\mathbb {Z}/e\mathbb {Z}$ -colored graph with vertices given by the charged bipartitions $\{|\underline {\lambda }^t,\underline {s}\rangle \mid \underline {\lambda }\in \mathcal {P}^2\}$ and with an i-colored edge $|\underline {\mu }^t,\underline {s}\rangle \stackrel {i}{\rightarrow }|\underline {\lambda }^t,\underline {s}\rangle $ if and only if $\tilde {e}_i|\underline {\lambda }^t,\underline {s}\rangle =|\underline {\mu }^t,\underline {s}\rangle $ for $i\in \mathbb {Z}/e\mathbb {Z}$ . If there is no such i-colored edge terminating at $|\underline {\lambda }^t,\underline {s}\rangle $ , then we declare $\tilde {e}_i|\underline {\lambda }^t,\underline {s}\rangle =0$ . As is customary, we drop the notation of $\underline {s}$ when it is understood and write $\tilde {e}_i(\underline {\lambda }^t)=\underline {\mu }^t$ , but we emphasize that this also depends on $\underline {s}$ . If $\tilde {e}_i(\underline {\lambda }^t)=\underline {\mu }^t$ , then $\tilde {f}_i(\underline {\mu }^t)=\underline {\lambda }^t$ , and $\tilde {f}_i$ adds the good addable i-box of $\underline {\mu }^t$ .

Example 2.5 Let $e=6$ and $\underline {s}=(0,1)$ . Take $\underline {\lambda }=((2^3,1^2),(1^2))$ , so $\underline {\lambda }^t=((5,3),(2))$ . Then, $\underline {\lambda }^t$ has just three removable boxes, and their charged contents mod $6$ are distinct. The removable and addable boxes, colored according to their charged contents mod $6$ , are pictured below:

We have $\mathsf {E}_{\color {Fuchsia}{\bf 4}}\Delta (\underline {\lambda })=\Delta ((2^3,1),(1^2))$ and $(\tilde {e}_{\color {Fuchsia}{\bf 4}}(\underline {\lambda }^t))^t=((2^3,1),(1^2))$ ; $\mathsf {E}_{\color {Emerald}{\bf 2}}\Delta (\underline {\lambda })=\Delta ((2^3,1^2),(1))$ and $\tilde {e}_{\color {Emerald}{\bf 2}}(\underline {\lambda }^t)=0$ , because the addable ${\color {Emerald}2}$ -box in the second row of $(\lambda ^1)^t$ cancels the removable ${\color {Emerald}2}$ -box; $\mathsf {E}_{\color {Dandelion}{\bf 1}}\Delta (\underline {\lambda })=\Delta ((2^2,1^3),(1^2))$ and $(\tilde {e}_{\color {Dandelion}{\bf 1}}(\underline {\lambda }^t))^t=((2^2,1^3),(1^2))$ . Note that because the charged contents mod $6$ of the removable boxes are all distinct, this example is easier than usual. When there are multiple removable boxes of the same charged content i mod e, the rule is more subtle.

Example 2.6 Let $e=3$ , $\underline {s}=(0,1)$ , and $\underline {\lambda }^t=((2^2,1^2),(2,1^2))$ . The removable and addable boxes of charged contents ${\color {CarnationPink}{\bf 0}}$ , ${\color {LimeGreen}{\bf 1}}$ , and ${\color {CornflowerBlue}{\bf 2}}$ mod $3$ are indicated in the picture below. There are two removable $0$ -boxes, of which the box of charged content $-3$ is the good removable $0$ -box. There are two removable $2$ -boxes, but neither is a good removable box. We have $\tilde {e}_{\color {CarnationPink}{\bf 0}}(\underline {\lambda }^t)=((2^2,1)(2,1^2))$ , $\tilde {e}_{\color {LimeGreen}{\bf 1}}(\underline {\lambda }^t)=0$ , and $\tilde {e}_{\color {CornflowerBlue}{\bf 2}}(\underline {\lambda }^t)=0$ .

We will need two easy lemmas.

Lemma 2.7 Let $|\underline {\lambda }^t,\underline {s}\rangle \in \mathcal {F}^2_{e,\underline {s}}$ .

  1. (1) Suppose b is a removable box of $(\lambda ^1)^t$ and $a'$ is an addable box of $(\lambda ^2)^t$ such that $\widetilde {\mathrm {ct}}(a')=\widetilde {\mathrm {ct}}(b)+e$ . Let $i=\widetilde {\mathrm {ct}}(b)\mod e$ . Then, b is not a good removable i-box.

  2. (2) Suppose $b'$ is a removable box of $(\lambda ^2)^t$ and a is an addable box of $(\lambda ^1)^t$ such that $\widetilde {\mathrm {ct}}(a)=\widetilde {\mathrm {ct}}(b')$ . Let $i=\widetilde {\mathrm {ct}}(b')\mod e$ . Then, $b'$ is not a good removable i-box.

Proof In the total order on addable and removable i-boxes in $|\underline {\lambda }^t,\underline {s}\rangle $ , $b<a'$ and $b'<a$ , and there cannot exist any i-box f either addable or removable such that $b<f<a'$ or $b'<f<a$ .▪

Lemma 2.8 Suppose that for any two removable boxes $b_1,b_2$ of $|\underline {\lambda }^t,\underline {s}\rangle $ , $\widetilde {\mathrm {ct}}(b_1)\neq \widetilde {\mathrm {ct}}(b_2)\mod e$ . Then, ${{}^{\mathcal {O}}\operatorname {Res}}^n_{n-1}L(\underline {\lambda })$ is semisimple or $0$ .

Proof We have ${{}^{\mathcal {O}}\operatorname {Res}}^n_{n-1}=\bigoplus \limits _{i\in \mathbb {Z}/e\mathbb {Z}}\mathsf {E}_i$ , so it suffices to show that $\mathsf {E}_iL(\underline {\lambda })$ is either irreducible or $0$ for every $i\in \mathbb {Z}/e\mathbb {Z}$ .

By assumption, $|\underline {\lambda }^t,\underline {s}\rangle $ has at most one removable i-box for any $i\in \mathbb {Z}/e\mathbb {Z}$ . If $|\underline {\lambda }^t,\underline {s}\rangle $ has no removable i-box, then $\mathsf {E}_i$ acts by $0$ on $\Delta (\underline {\lambda })$ and $L(\underline {\lambda })$ . So suppose that $|\underline {\lambda }^t,\underline {s}\rangle $ has a removable i-box $b^t$ , corresponding under the transpose map to the box $b\in \underline {\lambda }$ . Because $b^t$ is the only removable i-box, $\mathsf {E}_i\Delta (\underline {\lambda })=\Delta (\underline {\lambda }\setminus b)$ . If $b^t$ is not good removable, then $\tilde {e}_i(\underline {\lambda }^t)=0$ , so $\mathsf {E}_iL(\underline {\lambda })=0$ and there is nothing to show. If $b^t$ is good removable, then $(\tilde {e}_i(\underline {\lambda }^t)^t)=\underline {\lambda }\setminus b$ . By exactness of $\mathsf {E}_i$ , there is a surjective homomorphism $\mathsf {E}_i\Delta (\underline {\lambda })=\Delta (\underline {\lambda }\setminus b)\twoheadrightarrow \mathsf {E}_i L(\underline {\lambda })$ . Pre-composing this with the surjection $\mathsf {E}_iL(\underline {\lambda })\twoheadrightarrow L(\tilde {e}_i(\underline {\lambda }^t)^t)=L(\underline {\lambda }\setminus b)$ , we obtain a surjection $\Delta (\underline {\lambda }\setminus b)\twoheadrightarrow L(\underline {\lambda }\setminus b)$ factoring through $\mathsf {E}_iL(\underline {\lambda })$ . Because $\Delta (\underline {\lambda }\setminus b)$ contains $L(\underline {\lambda }\setminus b)$ exactly once as a composition factor, $\mathsf {E}_i L(\underline {\lambda })$ also contains $L(\underline {\lambda }\setminus b)$ exactly once as a composition factor. But the head of $\mathsf {E}_iL(\underline {\lambda })$ is isomorphic to its socle, and $L(\underline {\lambda }\setminus b)$ is the head of $\mathsf {E}_iL(\underline {\lambda })$ . It follows that $\mathsf {E}_iL(\underline {\lambda })$ is irreducible and equal to $L(\underline {\lambda }\setminus b)$ .▪

2.3 The $\mathfrak {sl}_{\infty }$ -crystal

A direct combinatorial rule for computing the arrows in the $\mathfrak {sl}_{\infty }$ -crystal was given in [Reference Gorsky, Simental and Vazirani15] and builds off of previous results by Gerber [Reference Gerber and Norton13, Reference Ginzburg, Guay, Opdam and Rouquier14] and Losev [Reference Montarani23]. The rule uses abacus combinatorics. We define the abacus $\mathcal {A}(\underline {\lambda })$ via the $\beta $ -numbers of the charged bipartition $|((\lambda ^1)^t,(\lambda ^2)^t),\underline {s}\rangle $ as $\mathcal {A}(\underline {\lambda }):=\left (\{\beta ^1_1,\beta ^1_2,\beta ^1_3,\dots \},\{\beta ^2_1,\beta ^2_2,\beta ^2_3,\dots \}\right )$ , where $\beta ^j_i:=(\lambda ^j)^t_i+s_j-i+1$ if $i\leq r_j$ where $r_j$ is the number of parts of $(\lambda ^j)^t$ , i.e., the number of columns of $\lambda ^j$ , and $\beta ^j_i=s_j-i+1$ if $i>r_j$ . (As in Convention 2.1, we have taken the transposes of $\lambda ^1$ and $\lambda ^2$ , because the convention of [Reference Fishel, Griffeth and Manosalva11, Reference Jacon and Lecouvey19] for labeling irreducible representations by bipartitions is the componentwise transpose of the convention in [Reference Gerber and Norton13Reference Gorsky, Simental and Vazirani15] for the level $2$ Fock space.) Note that the number of runners in the abacus is equal to the number of partitions, namely $2$ , making up $\underline {\lambda }$ , and is independent of e. This is in contrast to the perhaps more familiar e-abacus encoding the e-quotient of a partition.

It is convenient to visualize the abacus $\mathcal {A}(\underline {\lambda })$ as an array of beads and spaces assembled in two horizontal rows and infinitely many columns indexed by $\mathbb {Z}$ ; the bottom row corresponds to $\lambda ^1$ and the top row to $\lambda ^2$ , with a bead in row j and column $\beta ^j_i$ for each $i\in \mathbb {N}$ and each $j=1,2$ , and spaces otherwise. Far to the left, the abacus consists only of beads, far to the right only of spaces, so computations always occur in a finite region. The beads in $\mathcal {A}(\underline {\lambda })$ which have some space to their left correspond to the nonzero columns of $\underline {\lambda }$ . We emphasize that the abacus $\mathcal {A}(\underline {\lambda })$ is really the same thing as the charged bipartition $|\underline {\lambda }^t,\underline {s}\rangle $ —the former is just a visual way of working with the latter. Because we have a running convention of taking the transpose when going from $\mathcal {P}^2$ to $\mathcal {F}_{e,\underline {s}}$ , we will try to use the phrase and notation “the abacus $\mathcal {A}(\underline {\lambda })$ ” for $\underline {\lambda }\in \mathcal {P}^2$ labeling $L(\underline {\lambda })\in \mathcal {O}_{e,\underline {s}}$ , and to use the phrase “the abacus associated to $|\underline {\lambda }^t,\underline {s}\rangle $ ” for the same abacus, but now defined with reference to a charged bipartition in $\mathcal {F}_{e,\underline {s}}$ .

Example 2.9 Let $\underline {\lambda }=((5,4,2,2),(4,3,2,2))$ , $\underline {s}=(0,3)$ . Then, $\underline {\lambda }^t = ((4,4,2,2,1), (4,4,2,1)))$ , and we have $\mathcal {A}(\underline {\lambda })=(\{4,3,0,-1,-3,-5,-6,-7,\ldots \},\{7,6,3,1,-1,-2, -3,\ldots \})$ , visualized as the following abacus diagram (the beads are understood to extend infinitely to the left, the spaces infinitely to the right):

Following [Reference Losev, Beliakova and Lauda21, Definition 2.2], given $\mathcal {A}(\underline {\lambda })$ the abacus associated to $|\underline {\lambda }^t,\underline {s}\rangle $ , we say that $\mathcal {A}(\underline {\lambda })$ has an e-period if there exist $\beta ^{j_1}_{i_1},\beta ^{j_2}_{i_2},\dots ,\beta ^{j_e}_{i_e}\in \mathcal {A}(\underline {\lambda })$ such that $j_1\geq j_2\geq \dots \geq j_e$ , $\beta ^{j_{m+1}}_{i_{m+1}}=\beta ^{j_m}_{i_m}-1$ for each $m=1,\dots ,e-1$ , $\beta ^{j_1}_{i_1}$ is in the rightmost column of $\mathcal {A}(\underline {\lambda })$ containing a bead, and for each $m=1,\dots ,e$ , if $j_m=2$ , then $\beta ^2_{i_m}$ has an empty space below it. If $\mathcal {A}(\underline {\lambda })$ has an e-period, then it is unique. Let $\mathrm {Per}^1=\{\beta ^{j_1}_{i_1},\beta ^{j_2}_{i_2},\dots ,\beta ^{j_e}_{i_e}\}\subset \mathcal {A}(\underline {\lambda })$ denote the e-period of $\mathcal {A}(\underline {\lambda })$ if it exists, and call it the first e-period. The kth e-period $\mathrm {Per}^k$ of $\mathcal {A}(\underline {\lambda })$ is defined recursively as the e-period of $\left (\dots \left (\mathcal {A}({\lambda })\setminus \mathrm {Per^1}\right )\setminus \mathrm {Per^2}\dots \right )\setminus \mathrm {Per}^{k-1}$ if it exists and $\mathrm {Per}^1,\dots ,\mathrm {Per}^{k-1}$ exist. We say that $\mathcal {A}(\underline {\lambda })$ is totally e-periodic if $\mathrm {Per}^k$ exists for any $k\in \mathbb {N}$ (see [Reference Losev, Beliakova and Lauda21, Definition 5.4]). This is equivalent to requiring that after replacing all beads with spaces in the first k periods for some $k\in \mathbb {N}$ , we are left with the abacus of $(\emptyset ,\emptyset )$ for some charge $\underline {s'}$ [Reference Losev, Beliakova and Lauda21, Lemma 5.3].

Example 2.10 Let $\underline {\lambda }=((6,6,6,6),\emptyset )$ , $\underline {s}=(0,3)$ , and $e=5$ . Thus, $\underline {\lambda }^t=((4,4,4,4,4,4),\emptyset )$ , and the abacus $\mathcal {A}(\underline {\lambda })$ is drawn below with its first five $5$ -periods. We see that $\mathcal {A}(\underline {\lambda })$ is totally $5$ -periodic:

The first e-period $\mathrm {Per}^1$ consists of the five rightmost beads in Row $1$ , the second e-period $\mathrm {Per}^2$ consists of the four rightmost beads in Row $2$ , and the sixth bead from the right in Row $1$ , and so on.

The charged bipartition $|\underline {\lambda }^t,\underline {s}\rangle $ is a source vertex for the $\widehat {\mathfrak {sl}}_e$ -crystal on $\mathcal {F}^2_{e,\underline {s}}$ if and only if $\mathcal {A}(\underline {\lambda })$ is totally e-periodic [Reference Losev, Beliakova and Lauda21, Theorem 5.9]. In [Reference Gorsky, Simental and Vazirani15], we gave a criterion for checking if $|\underline {\lambda }^t,\underline {s}\rangle $ is a source vertex in the $\mathfrak {sl}_{\infty }$ -crystal in terms of a pattern avoidance condition on $\mathcal {A}(\underline {\lambda })$ [Reference Gorsky, Simental and Vazirani15, Theorem 7.13]. In particular, any “log jam” as in Example 2.10 where no e-period can “physically move to the left” is always a source vertex in the $\mathfrak {sl}_{\infty }$ -crystal.

The rule for edges in the $\mathfrak {sl}_{\infty }$ -crystal in a totally e-periodic abacus is in terms of shifting e-periods to the left and the right. In the case that an abacus $\mathcal {A}$ is not totally e-periodic, the rule is more complicated, and we refer the reader to [Reference Gorsky, Simental and Vazirani15] for the general case. We now explain the rule in the totally e-periodic case. First, we give examples of shifting e-periods to the left and the right in an abacus.

Example 2.11 Let $\mathcal {A}$ be the abacus in Example 2.10. The only e-period that can be shifted to the right is $\mathrm {Per}^1$ . Doing so, we obtain the following abacus:

Example 2.12 Let $e=3$ , $\underline {s}=(0,2)$ , and $\underline {\lambda }^t=((3^3,2),(3^3,2^2))$ . We shift $\mathrm {Per}^3$ to the left as follows:

Theorem 2.13 [Reference Gorsky, Simental and Vazirani15]

Let $\mathcal {A}$ be a totally e-periodic abacus, and let $\mathrm {Per}^k$ , $k\geq 1$ , be the e-periods of $\mathcal {A}$ . Suppose $\mathrm {Per}^k$ can be shifted to the right for some k, and let $\mathcal {A}'$ be the abacus obtained from $\mathcal {A}$ by shifting $\mathrm {Per}^k$ to the right. Then, there is an edge from $\mathcal {A}$ to $\mathcal {A}'$ in the $\mathfrak {sl}_{\infty }$ -crystal if and only if the right shift of $\mathrm {Per}^k$ is the kth e-period of $\mathcal {A}'$ . All edges in the $\mathfrak {sl}_{\infty }$ -crystal on the totally e-periodic abaci arise in this way.

Corollary 2.14 Shifting the e-period $\mathrm {Per}^k$ to the left in a totally e-periodic abacus $\mathcal {A}$ to obtain a new abacus $\mathcal {A}'$ describes an edge in the $\mathfrak {sl}_{\infty }$ -crystal if and only if the left shift of $\mathrm {Per}^k$ is the kth e-period of $\mathcal {A}'$ .

Example 2.15 Let $e=3$ and consider the following totally $3$ -periodic abacus with $\underline {\lambda }^t=((1^3),\emptyset )$ and $\underline {s}=(0,1)$ , drawn with its $3$ -periods:

Then, shifting $\mathrm {Per}^1$ to the left does not describe an edge in the $\mathfrak {sl}_{\infty }$ -crystal, because the left shift of $\mathrm {Per}^1$ would not be the first e-period of the new abacus. Because no other e-period can shift to the left, the abacus is a source vertex in the $\mathfrak {sl}_{\infty }$ -crystal. Because the abacus is totally $3$ -periodic, it is a source vertex in the $\widehat {\mathfrak {sl}}_3$ -crystal. We conclude by Theorem 2.4 that $L((3),\emptyset )$ is a finite-dimensional irreducible representation of the rational Cherednik algebra of $B_3$ with parameters $c=\frac {1}{3}$ and $d=-\frac {1}{6}$ (see equation (2.2)).

Consider a totally e-periodic abacus, and let $\Upsilon _k^-$ be the $\mathfrak {sl}_{\infty }$ -crystal operator that shifts $\mathrm {Per}^k$ to the left if doing so yields the kth e-period of the new abacus, and otherwise sends the abacus to $0$ [Reference Gorsky, Simental and Vazirani15]. Similarly, define $\Upsilon _k^+$ for the right shift of $\mathrm {Per}^k$ . The $\mathfrak {sl}_{\infty }$ -crystal and the $\widehat {\mathfrak {sl}}_e$ -crystal operators commute [Reference Gerber and Norton13]. (Therefore, we may always compute the $\mathfrak {sl}_{\infty }$ -crystal on an abacus by applying a sequence $\tilde {e}_{i_1},\ldots ,\tilde {e}_{i_r}$ of $\widehat {\mathfrak {sl}}_e$ -crystal operators that remove boxes to arrive at a totally e-periodic abacus, then applying the $\mathfrak {sl}_{\infty }$ -operators to the totally e-periodic abacus by the rule above, then applying the reverse sequence $\tilde {f}_{i_r}\ldots ,\tilde {f}_{i_1}$ of $\widehat {\mathfrak {sl}}_e$ -crystal operators that add boxes.)

For an abacus $\mathcal {A}$ associated to the charged bipartition $|\underline {\lambda }^t,\underline {s}\rangle \in \mathcal {F}_{e,\underline {s}}$ and a partition $\sigma $ , define $\tilde {a}_{\sigma }\mathcal {A}$ to be the abacus obtained from $\mathcal {A}$ by shifting $\mathrm {Per}^1$ (recursively) to the right $\sigma _1$ times, then shifting $\mathrm {Per}^2$ (recursively) to the right $\sigma ^2$ times, and so on [Reference Gerber and Norton13]. That is, if $\sigma =(\sigma _1,\ldots ,\sigma _r)$ , then $\tilde {a}_\sigma =(\Upsilon ^+_{r})^{\sigma _r}\ldots (\Upsilon ^+_{1})^{\sigma _1}$ . If $\mathcal {A}$ is the abacus associated to $|\underline {\lambda }^t,\underline {s}\rangle \in \mathcal {F}_{e,\underline {s}}^2$ and $|\underline {\mu }^t,\underline {s}\rangle \in \mathcal {F}_{e,\underline {s}}^2$ is the charged bipartition associated to $\tilde {a}_{\sigma }\mathcal {A}$ , we will write $\underline {\mu }^t=\tilde {a}_{\sigma }(\underline {\lambda }^t)$ . The crystal operator $\tilde {a}_{\sigma }$ is categorified by a functor $A_\sigma $ related to parabolic induction (see [Reference Montarani23, Reference Shan and Vasserot29]). When $\mathcal {A}$ is a source vertex in the $\mathfrak {sl}_{\infty }$ -crystal, we will refer to $\sigma $ as the position of $\tilde {a}_{\sigma }\mathcal {A}$ in the $\mathfrak {sl}_{\infty }$ -crystal, and call $|\sigma |$ the depth of $\tilde {a}_\sigma \mathcal {A}$ in the $\mathfrak {sl}_{\infty }$ -crystal.

On the bipartition $\underline {\lambda }^t$ , the operator $\Upsilon _i^-$ removes a certain “good vertical strip” of e boxes of successive charged contents from the rim of $\underline {\lambda }^t$ or acts by $0$ (and thus on $\underline {\lambda }$ , this results in the removal of a certain horizontal strip) [Reference Ginzburg, Guay, Opdam and Rouquier14]. Similarly, $\Upsilon _k^+$ either acts by $0$ or adds a “good vertical strip” to $\underline {\lambda }^t$ (respectively, results in the addition of a horizontal strip to $\underline {\lambda }$ ). The strip may be broken into two pieces, one piece in the first component and the other in the second component [Reference Ginzburg, Guay, Opdam and Rouquier14].

Example 2.16 In Example 2.12, shifting $\mathrm {Per}^3$ to the left describes an edge in the $\mathfrak {sl}_{\infty }$ -crystal. On the Young diagram of $\underline {\lambda ^t}$ , $\Upsilon _3^-$ removes the vertical $3$ -strip consisting of the three shaded boxes:

On the Young diagram of $\underline {\lambda }$ , this results in the removal of the horizontal $3$ -strip consisting of the three shaded boxes:

Example 2.17 Let $e=4$ , $\underline {\lambda }=((3^2),(1^2))$ , and $\underline {s}=(0,1)$ . Then, $|\underline {\lambda }^t,\underline {s}\rangle $ as an abacus is

In the $\mathfrak {sl}_{\infty }$ -crystal, we may shift $\mathrm {Per}^1$ to the left two times to obtain the empty bipartition. On the Young diagram of $\underline {\lambda }^t$ , shifting $\mathrm {Per}^1$ to the left once removes the rightmost, darker-shaded vertical strip of boxes, then shifting $\mathrm {Per}^1$ to the left again removes the remaining, lighter-shaded vertical strip:

On the Young diagram of $\underline {\lambda }$ , shifting $\mathrm {Per}^1$ to the left once removes the bottom-most, darker-shaded horizontal strip of boxes, then shifting $\mathrm {Per}^1$ to the left again removes the remaining, lighter-shaded horizontal strip:

We have $\underline {\lambda }^t=\tilde {a}_{(2)}(\emptyset ,\emptyset )$ .

The general rule for $\tilde {a}_{(m)}(\emptyset ,\emptyset )$ is easily seen to be the following. Let $\underline {s}=(0,s)$ . For $0<s<e$ , we have $\tilde {a}_{(m)}(\emptyset ,\emptyset )=(((e-s)^m),(s^m))^t$ . For $s\geq e$ , we have $\tilde {a}_{(m)}(\emptyset ,\emptyset )=(\emptyset ,(e^m))^t$ . For $s\leq 0$ , we have $\tilde {a}_{(m)}(\emptyset ,\emptyset )=((e^m),\emptyset )^t$ .

3 Parabolic restriction of unitary representations in $\mathcal {O}_{e, \underline {s}}(n)$

In this section, we will prove Theorem 1.4 and deduce Corollary 1.5. Theorem 1.4 follows from two propositions. Proposition 3.1 proves that the annihilation operators $\tilde {e}_i$ and $\Upsilon _k^-$ in the $\widehat {\mathfrak {sl}}_e$ - and $\mathfrak {sl}_{\infty }$ -crystals on $\mathcal {F}_{e,\underline {s}}^2$ preserve the combinatorial conditions of unitarity, and Proposition 3.8 proves that the functor $\mathsf {E}_i$ sends unitary irreducible representations to irreducible representations or $0$ . From the proof of Proposition 3.1, we deduce Corollaries 3.2 and 3.3, yielding Corollary 1.5 and the second statement of Theorem 1.4. Corollary 3.2 classifies the unitary representations by their positions in the $\mathfrak {sl}_{\infty }$ - and $\widehat {\mathfrak {sl}}_e$ -crystals.

We also discuss some consequences of Corollary 3.2 and Theorem 1.4 in Section 3.2.1: many (asymptotically, one could say most) of the unitary representations $L(\underline {\lambda })$ in $\mathcal {O}_{e,\underline {s}}(n)$ are concentrated in a single component and are simply built from a rectangle $(q^r)$ labeling a finite-dimensional unitary representation as in Theorem 1.1 with a partition $\tau $ stacked underneath it such that $L(\tau )\in \mathcal {O}_{\frac {1}{e}}(S_{|\tau |})$ is unitary. The supports of these types of unitary irreducible representations are then just read off from the supports of its two pieces, i.e., the support of such a unitary representation $L(\underline {\lambda })$ is $B_{|\underline {\lambda }|}\mathfrak {h}^{W'}$ where $W'=B_{rq}\times W^{''}$ such that $W''$ yields the support of $L(\tau )$ .

3.1 The crystals and the unitarity conditions

As previously, let $(e,\underline {s})$ be a parameter for the level $2$ Fock space, so $e\geq 2$ is an integer and $\underline {s}\in \mathbb {Z}^2$ . Let $\mathcal {O}_{e,\underline {s}}(n)$ be the category $\mathcal {O}$ of the rational Cherednik algebra of $B_n$ with parameters $c=\frac {1}{e}$ and $d=-\frac {1}{2}+\frac {s}{e}$ where $s=s_2-s_1$ and $\mathcal {O}_{e,\underline {s}}=\bigoplus _{n\geq 0}\mathcal {O}_{e,\underline {s}}(n)$ . We can and will assume that $s_1=0$ and $s_2=s$ . Define $\mathcal {U}_{e,\underline {s}}^2\subset \mathcal {P}^2$ to be the set of all bipartitions $\underline {\lambda }$ such that $L(\underline {\lambda })\in \mathcal {O}_{e,\underline {s}}$ is unitary. Later, during discussion of the results, we will start casually referring to elements of $\mathcal {U}_{e,\underline {s}}^2$ as “unitary bipartitions.” During the proof, we will be more formal. Recall that we identify $\underline {\lambda }=(\lambda ^1,\lambda ^2)\in \mathcal {P}^2$ with the charged bipartition $|\underline {\lambda }^t,\underline {s}\rangle \in \mathcal {F}_{e,\underline {s}}^2$ , where $\underline {\lambda }^t=((\lambda ^1)^t,(\lambda ^2)^t)$ .

The combinatorial conditions for unitarity of $L(\underline {\lambda })$ are given by [Reference Jacon and Lecouvey19, Corollaries 8.4 and 8.5] in terms of certain boxes $b_i$ in the Young diagram of $\underline {\lambda }$ . In order to compute the crystals, we will also consider $\lambda ^t$ with boxes $b_i^t$ corresponding to the boxes $b_i$ under the transpose map. In Case (i) of our proofs, we will consider $\underline {\lambda }=(\lambda ,\emptyset )$ as in [Reference Jacon and Lecouvey19, Corollary 8.4]. In this case, particular boxes are marked in $\lambda $ and $\lambda ^t$ as follows.

The box $b_1$ is the box of largest content in $\lambda $ , $b_2$ is the removable box of largest content, $b_4$ is the removable box of second-largest content, $b_3$ is the largest box in the same column as $b_4$ such that the vertical strip from $b_3$ to $b_4$ can be removed from $\lambda $ , and $b_5$ is the box of smallest content in $\lambda $ . Thus, $b_1^t$ is the box of smallest content in $\lambda ^t$ , $b_5^t$ is the box of largest content in $\lambda ^t$ , and so on.

In Case (ii) of our proofs, we will consider $\underline {\lambda }=(\lambda ^1,\lambda ^2)$ where $\lambda ^1\neq \emptyset $ and $\lambda ^2\neq \emptyset $ , as in [Reference Jacon and Lecouvey19, Corollary 8.5]. In this case, particular boxes are marked in $\underline {\lambda }$ and $\underline {\lambda }^t$ following the notation of [Reference Jacon and Lecouvey19] (the box $b_3$ is omitted, because it will not be needed):

In $\lambda ^1$ , $b_1$ is the box of largest content, $b_2$ is the removable box of largest content, and $b_4$ is the box of smallest content; in $\lambda ^2$ , $b_1'$ is the box of largest content, $b_2'$ is the removable box of largest content, and $b_4'$ is the box of smallest content.

Proposition 3.1 Let $\underline {\lambda }\in \mathcal {U}_{e,\underline {s}}^2$ , that is, suppose that $L(\underline {\lambda })\in \mathcal {O}_{e,\underline {s}}$ is a unitary irreducible representation. Then, either $\tilde {e}_i(\underline {\lambda }^t)=0$ or $(\tilde {e}_i(\underline {\lambda }^t))^t\in \mathcal {U}_{e,\underline {s}}^2$ for all $i\in \mathbb {Z}/e\mathbb {Z}$ , and either $\Upsilon ^-_k(\lambda ^t)=0$ or $(\Upsilon ^-_k(\lambda ^t))^t\in \mathcal {U}_{e,\underline {s}}^2$ for all $k\in \mathbb {N}$ . That is, the operators in the $\widehat {\mathfrak {sl}}_e$ - and $\mathfrak {sl}_{\infty }$ -crystals that remove boxes preserve the combinatorial conditions for unitarity.

Proof We break the proof into two main cases: (i) when $\underline {\lambda }=(\lambda ,\emptyset )$ for some $\lambda \in \mathcal {P}$ and (ii) when $\underline {\lambda }=(\lambda ^1,\lambda ^2)$ with both $\lambda ^1,\lambda ^2\neq \emptyset $ . The case that $\underline {\lambda }=(\emptyset ,\lambda )$ follows from that for $\underline {\lambda }$ as in [Reference Jacon and Lecouvey19, Corollary 8.4]. In Case (i), we check the cases from [Reference Jacon and Lecouvey19, Corollary 8.4] for unitarity of $L(\lambda ,\emptyset )$ . In Case (ii), we check the cases from [Reference Jacon and Lecouvey19, Corollary 8.5] for unitarity of $L(\lambda ^1,\lambda ^2)$ .

$\underline{\textit{Case\ (i):}\ {\lambda }=(\lambda ,\emptyset )\ \textit{for}\ \textit{some}\ \textit{partition}\ \lambda\ \textit{of}\ n.}$

According to [Reference Jacon and Lecouvey19, Corollary 8.4], $L((1^n),\emptyset )$ is unitary if and only if either $d\leq \frac {1}{2}$ or $d+\ell c=\frac {1}{2}$ for some $-n+1\leq \ell \leq -1$ . If $d\leq \frac {1}{2}$ , then this is independent of n, so the condition is preserved by removing a box. If $d+\ell c=\frac {1}{2}$ , then with Fock space parameters we have $\ell =e-s$ , yielding $n-1+e\geq s\geq e+1$ . If $n\geq s-e+1$ , then the condition is preserved by removing a box. If $n=s-e+1$ , then $L(\underline {\lambda },\emptyset )$ is a finite-dimensional unitary representation by Theorem 1.1, so $\tilde {e}_i$ acts on it by $0$ . We conclude that when $L((1^n),\emptyset )$ is unitary, $((1^n),\emptyset ))^t=((n),\emptyset )$ is taken by $\tilde {e}_i$ to $((n-1),\emptyset )$ only when $L((1^{n-1}),\emptyset )$ is unitary, and otherwise $\tilde {e}_i$ sends it to $0$ . No vertical strip of length bigger than $1$ can be removed from $(1^n)^t=(n)$ , so $\Upsilon ^-_k((n),\emptyset )=0$ for all $k\in \mathbb {N}$ .

From now on, assume $\lambda \neq (1^n)$ .

$\underline{\textit{Case (i)(a)}}$ . Writing [Reference Jacon and Lecouvey19, Corollary 8.4, Case (a)] in terms of Fock space parameters yields:

$$ \begin{align*} &\mathrm{ct}(b_1)-\mathrm{ct}(b_5)+1\leq e,\\ &\mathrm{ct}(b_1)\leq e-s. \end{align*} $$

$\underline {\mbox {Check that }\tilde {e}_i \mbox { preserves unitarity}}.$ If $b_1=b_5$ , that is, if $\lambda =(1)$ , then there is nothing to show, so we assume that $b_1\neq b_5$ . The operator $\tilde {e}_i$ is actually removing a box from $\lambda ^t$ , but let us examine the effect on $\lambda $ . Obviously the inequalities are preserved if the box removed is not $b_1$ or $b_5$ . Because $b_1$ is the box of largest content, $\mathrm {ct}(b_1)\geq 0$ . If $b_1$ is removed, then the box of largest content in $\lambda \setminus b_1$ has content $\mathrm {ct}(b_1)-1$ , and all inequalities are preserved. Because $\mathrm {ct}(b_5)$ is the box of smallest content, $\mathrm {ct}(b_5)\leq 0$ . If $b_5$ is removed, then the box of smallest content in $\lambda \setminus b_5$ has content $\mathrm {ct}(b_5)+1$ , and all inequalities are preserved.

$\underline {\mbox {Check that }\Upsilon _k^- \mbox {preserves unitarity}}.$ The quantity $\mathrm {ct}(b_1)-\mathrm {ct}(b_5)+1$ is the maximum hooklength of a box in $\lambda $ , equivalently in $\lambda ^t$ . Therefore, the only way a vertical strip of length e can be removed from $|(\lambda ^t,\emptyset ),\underline {s}\rangle $ is if $\lambda ^t=(1^e)$ , that is, if $\lambda =(e)$ . Otherwise, all $\Upsilon ^-_k$ act by $0$ . Suppose $\lambda =(e)$ . Then, $\mathrm {ct}(b_1)=e-1$ , so the second inequality is satisfied if and only if $s\leq 1$ . If $s\leq 0$ , then, considering $|(\lambda ^t,\emptyset ),\underline {s}\rangle $ , we see that $\Upsilon ^-_1(\underline {\lambda }^t)=\emptyset $ , that is, $\Upsilon ^-_1$ acts by removing all the boxes of $\lambda $ , while $\Upsilon ^-_k(\underline {\lambda }^t)=0$ for $k>1$ . If $s=1$ , then by Theorem 1.1, $L((e),\emptyset )$ is a unitary finite-dimensional representation, so all $\Upsilon _k^-$ act on $|\underline {\lambda }^t,\underline {s}\rangle $ by $0$ .

$\underline{\textit{Case (i)(b)}}$ . Writing [Reference Jacon and Lecouvey19, Corollary 8.4, Case (b)] in terms of Fock space parameters yields:

$$ \begin{align*} &\mathrm{ct}(b_2)-\mathrm{ct}(b_5)+1\leq e,\\ &\mathrm{ct}(b_1)\leq e-s. \end{align*} $$

$\underline {\mbox {Check that }\tilde {e}_i \mbox { preserves unitarity}}.$ By the proof of Case (i)(a), if any box besides $b_2$ is removed, then the boxes of the resulting partition satisfy the given inequalities. Now, $b_2$ is the removable box of largest content, and if it is not equal to $b_1$ , then the removable box of largest content in $\lambda \setminus b_2$ has content $\mathrm {ct}(b_2)+1$ . This could only pose a problem if $\mathrm {ct}(b_2)-\mathrm {ct}(b_5)+1=e$ and $b_2$ is removed from $\lambda $ . However, considering $|\lambda ^t,\underline {s}\rangle $ in order to compute the crystal rule, we see that in this situation $\lambda ^t$ has an addable box to the right of $b_5^t$ of content $-\mathrm {ct}(b_5)+1=-\mathrm {ct}(b_2)+e$ . Then, $b_2^t$ is not good removable, because it is cancelled either by this addable box or by the addable box in Component $2$ of $\underline {\lambda }^t$ .

$\underline {\mbox {Check that }\Upsilon _k^- \mbox {preserves unitarity}}.$ The condition that $\mathrm {ct}(b_2)-\mathrm {ct}(b_5)+1\leq e$ is the same condition that appears for type A unitary representations at parameter $\frac {1}{e}$ , because it is presented in [Reference Bowman and Cox2]. It says that the bottom border of $\lambda $ has length at most e, as illustrated below:

In $\lambda ^t$ , we then have the following picture, with the shaded right border of $\lambda ^t$ being required to have length at most e:

The only way a vertical strip of length e can be removed from $\lambda ^t$ , then, is if the shaded border strip is a vertical strip of length e, that is, if $\lambda ^t$ is a rectangle with e rows. Otherwise, all $\Upsilon _k^-$ act by $0$ . Now, $\lambda ^t$ is a rectangle with e rows if and only if $\mathrm {ct}(b_2)-\mathrm {ct}(b_5)+1=e$ and $\mathrm {ct}(b_1)=e-1$ . Imposing the condition $\mathrm {ct}(b_1)\leq e-s$ , we see that it must hold that $s\leq 1$ .

Let us suppose, then, that $\lambda =(e^m)$ for some $m\geq 1$ , so $\lambda ^t=(m^e)$ . The $\beta $ -numbers yielding the abacus of $|(\lambda ^t,\emptyset ),\underline {s}\rangle $ are $\beta ^1=\{m,m-1,\ldots ,m-e+2,m-e+1,-e,-e-1,-e-2,\ldots \}$ and $\beta ^2=\{s,s-1,s-2,\ldots \}$ . The abacus is totally e-periodic with $\mathrm {Per}^1$ given by the first e elements of $\beta ^1$ , as illustrated below for $s=0$ , $e=8$ , and $m=6$ :

As this is true for any $m\geq 1$ , shifting $\mathrm {Per}^1$ to the left when $m>1$ produces the first e-period of $|((m-1)^e,\emptyset ),\underline {s}\rangle $ , and therefore describes the action of $\Upsilon ^-_1$ . In the case $m=1$ , shifting $\mathrm {Per}^1$ produces the first e-period of the abacus of the empty bipartition if $s\leq 0$ , and therefore describes the action of $\Upsilon _1^-$ . If $s=1$ , then shifting $\mathrm {Per}^1$ to the left when $m=1$ does not describe an edge in the $\mathfrak {sl}_{\infty }$ -crystal, and $L((e),\emptyset )$ is a finite-dimensional unitary representation, as given by Theorem 1.1. See Example 2.15 for a picture of this abacus when $e=3$ . We conclude that if $s\leq 0$ , then $|((m^e),\emptyset ),\underline {s}\rangle =\tilde {a}_{(m)}|(\emptyset ,\emptyset ),\underline {s}\rangle $ for $m\geq 1$ , whereas if $s=1$ , then $|((m^e),\emptyset ),(0,1)\rangle =\tilde {a}_{(m-1)}|((1^e),\emptyset ),(0,1)\rangle $ for $m\geq 2$ . And, in particular, the operators $\Upsilon ^-_k$ preserve the conditions of Case (i)(b).

$\underline{\textit{Case (i)(c)}}$ . Writing [Reference Jacon and Lecouvey19, Corollary 8.4, Case (b)] in terms of Fock space parameters yields:

$$ \begin{align*} &\mathrm{ct}(b_2)<e-s\leq \mathrm{ct}(b_1),\\ &-\mathrm{ct}(b_5)\leq s. \end{align*} $$

$\underline {\mbox {Check that }\tilde {e}_i \mbox { preserves unitarity}}.$ By assumption, $b_2\neq b_1$ , so $b_1$ is not removable. If any removable box besides $b_5,b_2$ is removed, then obviously the inequalities are preserved. If $b_5$ is removed, this increases the content of the box of smallest content, hence the inequalities are preserved. If $b_2$ is removed, then there could only be a problem if $\mathrm {ct}(b_2)=e-s-1$ . But then, we are in Case (i)(d), so we refer to the argument in that case.

$\underline {\mbox {Check that }\Upsilon _k^- \mbox { preserves unitarity}}.$ If $\Upsilon ^-_k$ does not act on $|(\lambda ^t,\emptyset ),\underline {s}\rangle $ by $0$ , then $\lambda ^t$ must contain a vertical strip of length e in its right border. This implies $\mathrm {ct}(b_1)\geq e-1$ . On the other hand, adding inequalities gives $\mathrm {ct}(b_2)-\mathrm {ct}(b_5)+1\leq e$ . As in Case (i)(b), then $\lambda $ must be a rectangle with e columns. Then, $\lambda $ has $s+1$ rows and $s\geq 1$ . If we consider $\mathrm {Per}^1$ of $|(s^e),\emptyset ),(0,s)\rangle $ , we see that its beads correspond to the e rows of $(s^e)$ . Then, $\tilde {a}_{(1)}$ applied to $|(s^e),\emptyset ),(0,s)\rangle $ adds a box to every row, yielding $\tilde {a}_{(1)}|(s^e),\emptyset ),(0,s)\rangle =|(\lambda ^t,\emptyset ),(0,s)\rangle $ . Thus, $\Upsilon ^-_1|(\lambda ^t,\emptyset ),(0,s)\rangle =|((e^s),\emptyset )^t,(0,s)\rangle $ , which labels a finite-dimensional unitary representation by Theorem 1.1. All $\Upsilon ^-_k$ for $k>1$ act by $0$ .

$\underline{\textit{Case (i)(d)}}$ . Writing [Reference Jacon and Lecouvey19, Corollary 8.4, Case (d)] in terms of Fock space parameters yields:

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{ct}(b_2)=e-s. \end{align*} $$

In addition, if $\lambda $ is not a rectangle or if $b_4\neq b_5$ , then either (a) for some $\ell $ such that $\mathrm {ct}(b_4)\leq \ell <\mathrm {ct}(b_3)$ , it holds that $e=\ell -\mathrm {ct}(b_5)+1,$ or (b) $e\geq \mathrm {ct}(b_3)-\mathrm {ct}(b_5)+1$ . Combining these last two conditions into one, we have that if $\lambda $ is not a rectangle or if $b_4\neq b_5$ , then

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{ct}(b_4)-\mathrm{ct}(b_5)+1\leq e. \end{align*} $$

Let $b_2^t$ be the box in $\lambda ^t$ corresponding to $b_2$ under the transpose map. Then, $\mathrm {ct}(b_2^t)=-\mathrm {ct}(b_2)=s-e$ . By Lemma 2.7, $b_2^t$ is canceled by the unique addable box in Component $2$ of $|\underline {\lambda }^t,\underline {s}\rangle $ , so $b_2^t$ is not a good removable box of $|\underline {\lambda }^t,\underline {s}\rangle $ .

$\underline {\mbox {Check that }\tilde {e}_i \mbox { and }\Upsilon _k^- \mbox { preserve unitarity when }b_4=b_5}.$ If $\lambda =(q^r)$ is a rectangle, then $b_2=b_4=b_5$ , and the unique removable box has content $s-e$ . Then, by Theorem 1.1, $L(\underline {\lambda })$ is finite-dimensional, and therefore $|\underline {\lambda }^t,\underline {s}\rangle $ is sent to $0$ by all $\tilde {e}_i$ and $\Upsilon _k^-$ . If $b_4=b_5\neq b_2$ , then $\lambda =(q^r,1^j)$ for some positive integers $q,r$ such that $r-q=s-e$ and for some $j\in \mathbb {N}$ . For any $i\in \mathbb {Z}/e\mathbb {Z}$ , we see that $b_5^t$ is always a good removable i-box of $|\underline {\lambda },\underline {s}\rangle $ , because it has the largest content of any removable box in $\lambda ^t$ , and has larger content than any addable box in $\lambda ^t$ of the same residue mod e, and the unique addable box in Component $2$ cannot cancel it, because that addable box cancels the box $b_2^t$ . We deduce that $\tilde {e}_i$ acts by $0$ unless $i=-\mathrm {ct}(b_5)\mod e$ in which case $\tilde {e}_i$ removes $b_5^t$ from $|\underline {\lambda }^t,\underline {s}\rangle .$ This implies that $|\underline {\lambda }^t,\underline {s}\rangle =\tilde {f}_{r+j-1}\ldots \tilde {f}_{r+2}\tilde {f}_{r+1}\tilde {f}_{r}|(r^q),\underline {s}\rangle $ where the indices are taken mod e. For example, when $e=3$ , $\underline {s}=(0,4)$ , $r=5$ , $q=4$ , and $\lambda =(4^5,1^4)$ , we have:

Because $|((r^q),\emptyset ),\underline {s}\rangle $ is a source vertex in both the $\widehat {\mathfrak {sl}}_e$ - and $\mathfrak {sl}_{\infty }$ -crystals, we have identified the position of $|\underline {\lambda }^t,\underline {s}\rangle $ in the two crystals: it has depth $0$ in the $\mathfrak {sl}_{\infty }$ -crystal, and therefore $\Upsilon _k^-$ acts on it by $0$ for all $k\geq 1$ .

$\underline {\mbox {Check that }\tilde {e}_i \mbox { preserves unitarity when }b_4\neq b_5}.$ Because $b_2^t$ is not a good removable box of $|\underline {\lambda }^t,\underline {s}\rangle $ , applying $\tilde {e}_i$ preserves the condition $\mathrm {ct}(b_2)=e-s$ . The condition $\mathrm {ct}(b_4)-\mathrm {ct}(b_5)+1\leq e$ continues to hold so long as any box is removed except $b_4$ . In the case of $b_4$ , removing it messes up the inequality if $\mathrm {ct}(b_4)-\mathrm {ct}(b_5)+1=e$ . But then, $-\mathrm {ct}(b_5)+1=-\mathrm {ct}(b_4)+e$ , so $b_4^t$ is not a good removable box of $|\underline {\lambda }^t,\underline {s}\rangle $ (because $\lambda ^2=\emptyset $ ). We illustrate this situation with a picture of such a $\lambda ^t$ for $e=2$ :

$\underline {\mbox {Check that }\Upsilon _k^- \mbox { preserves unitarity when }b_4\neq b_5.}$ Because $\mathrm {ct}(b_4)-\mathrm {ct}(b_5)+1\leq e$ and $b_4$ is the second-largest removable box of $\lambda $ , there are at most two vertical e-strips that can be removed from $\lambda ^t$ . We illustrate this scenario for $e=2$ :

However, even if $b_2^t$ sits at the bottom of a vertical strip of length e, removing that strip never yields an edge in the $\mathfrak {sl}_{\infty }$ -crystal. This is because $\mathrm {ct}(b_2^t)=s-e$ , so in the abacus associated to $|(\lambda ^t,\emptyset ),(0,s)\rangle $ , the corresponding chain of e beads on the bottom row of the abacus lies entirely underneath a chain of e beads in the top row of the abacus. Such a chain of e beads can never be shifted to the left by an operator $\Upsilon _k^-$ in the $\mathfrak {sl}_{\infty }$ -crystal [Reference Gorsky, Simental and Vazirani15]. It follows that $\Upsilon _k^-$ acts on $|\underline {\lambda }^t,\underline {s}\rangle $ by $0$ unless $k=1$ and $\mathrm {ct}(b_4)-\mathrm {ct}(b_5)+1=e$ .

Let us examine the scenario that $\mathrm {ct}(b_4)-\mathrm {ct}(b_5)+1=e$ and $b_5^t$ , $b_4^t$ are the top and bottom boxes of a vertical strip in the border of $\lambda ^t$ . Then, $b_2$ and $b_4$ are the only removable boxes of $\lambda $ , so $\lambda =(q^r,e^m)$ for some positive integers $q,r,m$ satisfying $q>e$ and $r-q=s-e$ . We then have $|(\lambda ^t,\emptyset ),(0,s)\rangle =\tilde {a}_{(m)}|((r^q),\emptyset ),(0,s)\rangle $ . In particular, $\Upsilon ^-_1|\underline {\lambda }^t,\underline {s}\rangle =|((r+m-1)^e,r^{q-e}),(0,s)\rangle $ and corresponds to removing the bottom row of e boxes from $\lambda $ yielding $(q^r,e^{m-1})$ . The partition $(q^r,e^{m-1})$ again falls under Case (i)(d).

$\underline{\textit{Case (i)(e)}}$ . Writing [Reference Jacon and Lecouvey19, Corollary 8.4, Case (e)] in terms of Fock space parameters yields:

$$ \begin{align*} &\mathrm{ct}(b_2)+1\leq e-s\leq \mathrm{ct}(b_1)-1,\\ &\mathrm{ct}(b_2)-\mathrm{ct}(b_5)+1\leq e\leq e-s-\mathrm{ct}(b_5). \end{align*} $$

$\underline {\mbox {Check that }\tilde {e}_i \mbox { preserves unitarity}}.$ If $b_1$ is removed and $\mathrm {ct}(b_1)=e-s+1$ , then the resulting partition belongs to Case (i)(b). If $b_5$ is removed and $s=-\mathrm {ct}(b_5)$ , then the resulting partition belongs to Case (i)(c). If $b_2$ is removed, $\mathrm {ct}(b_2)+1=e-s$ , and $s\neq -\mathrm {ct}(b_5)$ , then the resulting partition belongs to Case (i)(d). Finally, as in Case (i)(b), if $\mathrm {ct}(b_2)-\mathrm {ct}(b_5)+1= e$ , then $b_2^t$ is not a good removable box of $|\underline {\lambda }^t,\underline {s}\rangle $ .

$\underline {\mbox {Check that }\Upsilon _k^- \mbox { preserves unitarity}}.$ As in Case (i)(b), the $\mathfrak {sl}_{\infty }$ -crystal operators $\Upsilon _k^-$ act by $0$ unless $\lambda $ is a rectangle of width e. This follows from the requirement that $\mathrm {ct}(b_2)-\mathrm {ct}(b_5)+1\leq e$ . So suppose that $\lambda =(e^m)$ . Then, $\mathrm {ct}(b_1)-1=e-1$ , so $s\geq 1$ . From the requirement $\mathrm {ct}(b_2)<e-s$ , we deduce that $m>s$ . Reasoning as in Part (i)(d), we compute that $|(\lambda ^t,\emptyset ),(0,s)\rangle =\tilde {a}_{m-s}|((s^e),\emptyset ),(0,s)\rangle $ . Thus, successively removing the bottom row of $\lambda $ describes the effect of repeated iterations of $\Upsilon _1^-$ on $\lambda $ until the rectangle $(e^s)$ is reached. In particular, Case (i)(e) is preserved by applying $\Upsilon _1^-$ if $m>s+1$ , whereas for $m=s+1$ , applying $\Upsilon _1^-$ lands the resulting partition in Case (i)(d). All other $\Upsilon ^-_k$ act by $0$ , because $|(\lambda ^t,\emptyset ),(0,s)\rangle =\tilde {a}_{m-s}|((s^e),\emptyset ),(0,s)\rangle $ .

We illustrate the situation $|(\lambda ^t,\emptyset ),(0,s)\rangle =\tilde {a}_{m-s}|((s^e),\emptyset ),(0,s)\rangle $ in the last paragraph when $e=3$ , $s=2$ , and $m=6$ . The e-period $\mathrm {Per}^1$ can repeatedly shift to the left yielding the iterated action of $\Upsilon _1^-$ until it “docks” under the top row of beads. Thus, it can shift to the left under the action of $\Upsilon _1^-$ exactly four times. Once $\mathrm {Per}^1$ is completely covered by beads in the top row, shifting it to the left no longer describes an edge in the $\mathfrak {sl}_{\infty }$ -crystal, thus $(\Upsilon ^-_1)^5$ acts by $0$ . As is consistent with Theorem 1.1.

$\underline{\textit{Case (ii)}: {\lambda }=(\lambda ^1,\lambda ^2) \textit{ with both } \lambda ^1,\lambda ^2\neq \emptyset}$ .

It is sufficient to check the conditions for unitarity in Cases (a), (b), and (f) of [Reference Jacon and Lecouvey19, Corollary 8.5]. The other cases (c)–(e) and (g) are obtained from these by switching parameter c with $-c$ or parameter d with $-d$ , which have the effect of sending $\underline {\lambda } $ to $\underline {\lambda }^t$ or to $(\lambda ^2,\lambda ^1)$ , respectively.

$\underline{\textit{Case (ii)(a)}}$ . Writing [Reference Jacon and Lecouvey19, Corollary 8.5, Case (a)] in terms of Fock space parameters yields:

$$ \begin{align*} &-s\leq \mathrm{ct}(b_1)-\mathrm{ct}(b_4')+1\leq e-s,\\ &s-e\leq \mathrm{ct}(b_1')-\mathrm{ct}(b_4)+1\leq s. \end{align*} $$

$\underline {\mbox {Check that }\tilde {e}_i \mbox { preserves unitarity}}.$ Note that $\mathrm {ct}(b_1),\mathrm {ct}(b_1')\geq 0$ and $\mathrm {ct}(b_4),\mathrm {ct}(b_4')\leq 0$ always and thus $\mathrm {ct}(b_1)-\mathrm {ct}(b_4')+1> 0$ and $\mathrm {ct}(b_1')-\mathrm {ct}(b_4)+1>0$ always. The two right-hand inequalities then imply $0<s<e$ , making the two left-hand inequalities irrelevant. Removing any box of $\underline {\lambda }$ , the quantities $\mathrm {ct}(b_1)-\mathrm {ct}(b_4')+1$ and $\mathrm {ct}(b_1')-\mathrm {ct}(b_4)+1$ either stay the same or decrease by $1$ . It follows that $(\tilde {e}_i(\underline {\lambda }^t))^t$ also satisfies the conditions of Case (a) so long as both of its components are nonempty.

Next, suppose that $\lambda ^2=(1)$ and $\tilde {e}_i$ removes the unique box of $(\lambda ^2)^t$ . Then, $b_1'=b_4'$ and $\mathrm {ct}(b_1')=0$ . Then, $\mathrm {ct}(b_1)<e-s$ and $\mathrm {ct}(b_1)-\mathrm {ct}(b_4)+1<e$ , so [Reference Jacon and Lecouvey19, Corollary 8.4, Case (a)] holds for $(\tilde {e}_i(\underline {\lambda })^t)^t$ . On the other hand, if $\lambda ^1=(1)$ , then switching $\lambda ^1$ with $\lambda ^2$ and setting $s'=e-s$ (i.e., replacing d by $-d$ ), we make the same argument.

$\underline {\mbox {Check that }\Upsilon _k^- \mbox { preserves unitarity}}.$ Adding the two inequalities, we have $(\mathrm {ct}(b_1)-\mathrm {ct}(b_4)+1)+(\mathrm {ct}(b_1')-\mathrm {ct}(b_4')+1)\leq e$ . The quantity $\mathrm {ct}(b_1)-\mathrm {ct}(b_4)+1$ is the maximum hooklength of a box in $\lambda ^1$ , and $\mathrm {ct}(b_1')-\mathrm {ct}(b_4')+1$ is the maximum hooklength of a box in $\lambda ^2$ . It follows that the abacus of $|\underline {\lambda }^t,\underline {s}\rangle $ has an e-period that can shift to the left only if $(\lambda ^1)^t$ and $(\lambda ^2)^t$ are columns, in which case $b_1=b_2$ , $b_1'=b_2'$ , and we are in Case (ii)(f). Otherwise, $\Upsilon _k^-$ acts by $0$ for all $k\in \mathbb {N}$ . We now refer to the proof of Case (ii)(f) in the situation that $(\lambda ^1)^t$ and $(\lambda ^2)^t$ are columns and $|\underline {\lambda }|=e$ .

$\underline{\textit{Case (ii)(b)}}$ . Writing [Reference Jacon and Lecouvey19, Corollary 8.5, Case (b)] in terms of Fock space parameters yields:

$$ \begin{align*} &\mathrm{ct}(b_2)-\mathrm{ct}(b_4')+1\leq e-s\leq \mathrm{ct} (b_1)-\mathrm{ct}(b_4')+1,\\ &\mathrm{ct}(b_1')-\mathrm{ct}(b_4)+1\leq s. \end{align*} $$

$\underline {\mbox {Check that }\tilde {e}_i \mbox { preserves unitarity}}.$ First, we assume that both components of $\tilde {e}_i(\underline {\lambda }^t)$ are nonempty. Removing any box of $\underline {\lambda }$ preserves the bottom inequality, removing any box different from $b_2$ preserves the top-left inequality, and removing any box different from $b_1$ or $b_4'$ preserves the top-right inequality. If the top-right inequality is not preserved, then $e-s=\mathrm {ct}(b_1)-\mathrm {ct}(b_4')+1$ and $\tilde {e}_i$ removes $b_1^t$ or $b_4^{\prime t}$ from $\underline {\lambda }^t$ , but then Case (ii)(a) holds. The top-left inequality must be preserved unless $\mathrm {ct}(b_2)-\mathrm {ct}(b_4')+1=e-s$ and $b_2\neq b_1$ . Writing $\widetilde {\mathrm {ct}}(b_4^{\prime t})+1=-\mathrm {ct}(b_4')+s+1=-\mathrm {ct}(b_2)+e=\widetilde {\mathrm {ct}}(b_2^t)+e$ , we see that by Lemma 2.7, $b_2^t$ is not a good removable box. Therefore, $\tilde {e}_i$ preserves the top-left inequality.

Suppose that $\lambda ^2=(1)$ and that $\tilde {e}_i$ removes the unique box of $\lambda ^2=(\lambda ^2)^t$ . Then, $\mathrm {ct}(b_4')=\mathrm {ct}(b_1')=0$ , so $\mathrm {ct}(b_2)+1\leq e-s\leq \mathrm {ct}(b_1)+1$ and $-\mathrm {ct}(b_4)+1\leq s$ . Then, $(\lambda ^1,\emptyset )=(\tilde {e}_i(\underline {\lambda }^t))^t$ satisfies [Reference Jacon and Lecouvey19, Corollary 8.4, Case (c)] if $e-s\leq \mathrm {ct}(b_1)$ . If $e-s=\mathrm {ct}(b_1)+1$ , then $\mathrm {ct}(b_1)<e-s$ and $\mathrm {ct}(b_2)-\mathrm {ct}(b_4)+1<e$ , so $(\lambda ^1,\emptyset )$ then satisfies [Reference Jacon and Lecouvey19, Corollary 8.4, Case (b)].

Suppose that $\lambda ^1=(1)$ and that $\tilde {e}_i$ removes the unique box of $\lambda ^1=(\lambda ^1)^t$ . Then, $\mathrm {ct}(b_4)=\mathrm {ct}(b_1)=\mathrm {ct}(b_2)=0$ , so $-\mathrm {ct}(b_4')+1= e-s$ and $\mathrm {ct}(b_1')+1\leq s$ . Because $L(\emptyset ,\lambda ^2)$ for parameters $(c,d)$ is unitary if and only if $L(\lambda ^2,\emptyset )$ is unitary for parameters $(c,-d)$ , we see that $L(\emptyset ,\lambda ^2)$ is unitary by [Reference Jacon and Lecouvey19, Corollary 8.4, Case (a)].

$\underline {\mbox {Check that }\Upsilon _k^- \mbox { preserves unitarity}}.$ The same analysis holds as in Case (ii)(a). The abacus $|\underline {\lambda }^t,\underline {s}\rangle $ has an e-period that can shift to the left only if $|\underline {\lambda }|=e$ and $(\lambda ^1)^t$ , $(\lambda ^2)^t$ are both columns. This situation falls under Case (ii)(f). Otherwise, $\Upsilon _k^-$ acts by $0$ for all $k\in \mathbb {N}$ .

$\underline{\textit{Case (ii)(f)}}$ . Writing [Reference Jacon and Lecouvey19, Corollary 8.5, Case (f)] in terms of Fock space parameters yields:

$$ \begin{align*} &\mathrm{ct}(b_2)-\mathrm{ct}(b_4')+1\leq e-s\leq \mathrm{ct}(b_1)-\mathrm{ct}(b_4')+1,\\ &\mathrm{ct}(b_2')-\mathrm{ct}(b_4)+1\leq s\leq \mathrm{ct}(b_1')-\mathrm{ct}(b_4)+1. \end{align*} $$

$\underline {\mbox {Check that }\tilde {e}_i \mbox { preserves unitarity}}.$ First, we assume that both components of $\tilde {e}_i(\underline {\lambda }^t)$ are nonempty. The two right-hand inequalities are preserved by removing any boxes except when $e-s= \mathrm {ct}(b_1)-\mathrm {ct}(b_4')+1$ or $s= \mathrm {ct}(b_1')-\mathrm {ct}(b_4)+1.$ However, in either of those cases, then we are in Case (ii)(b) or [Reference Jacon and Lecouvey19, Corollary 8.5, Case (c)], which follows from Case (ii)(b) as discussed at the beginning of the proof. We have the same analysis of the top-left inequality as in Case (ii)(b). A similar argument applies to the bottom-left inequality: it must be preserved by removing any box unless $b_2'\neq b_1'$ and $\widetilde {\mathrm {ct}}(b_2^{\prime t})=-\mathrm {ct}(b_2')+s=-\mathrm {ct}(b_4)+1=\widetilde {\mathrm {ct}}(b_4^t)+1$ . But in this case, $b_2^{\prime t}$ is not a good removable box of $|\underline {\lambda }^t,\underline {s}\rangle $ by Lemma 2.7. Therefore, $\tilde {e}_i$ always preserves the bottom-left inequality.

The case where $\lambda ^j=(1)$ and that box is removed is the same as the argument in Case (ii)(b), except that [Reference Jacon and Lecouvey19, Corollary 8.4, Case (b)] now arises when $\lambda ^1=(1)$ and $s<\mathrm {ct}(b_1')+1$ .

$\underline {\mbox {Check that }\Upsilon _k^-\mbox { preserves unitarity}}.$ Adding the two leftmost inequalities for Case (ii)(f), the number of boxes in the right border strip of $\underline {\lambda }^t$ , as shaded in the diagram below, is at most e:

On the other hand, if $\Upsilon _k^-$ does not act by $0$ on $\underline {\lambda }^t$ , then it removes some vertical strip of e boxes from the right border strip of $\underline {\lambda }^t$ , a subset of the shaded region. This can only happen, therefore, if the shaded region is a vertical strip of e boxes, as illustrated below for $e=7$ :

We then have that $\lambda ^1$ and $\lambda ^2$ are rectangles, and $\widetilde {\mathrm {ct}}(b_4^{\prime t})+1=-\mathrm {ct}(b_4')+s+1=-\mathrm {ct}(b_2)+e=\widetilde {\mathrm {ct}}(b_2^t)+e$ and $\widetilde {\mathrm {ct}}(b_4^t)+1=-\mathrm {ct}(b_4)+1=-\mathrm {ct}(b_2')+s=\widetilde {\mathrm {ct}}(b_2^t)$ . By Lemma 2.7, the two removable boxes of $\underline {\lambda }^t$ are not good removable, so $|\underline {\lambda }^t,\underline {s}\rangle $ is totally e-periodic. The $\beta $ -numbers are $\beta ^1=\{-\mathrm {ct}(b_4)+1,-\mathrm {ct}(b_4),\ldots ,-\mathrm {ct}(b_2)+2,-\mathrm {ct}(b_2)+1,-\mathrm {ct}(b_1)-1,-\mathrm {ct}(b_1)-2,-\mathrm {ct}(b_1)-3,\ldots \}$ and $\beta ^2=\{-\mathrm {ct}(b_4')+s+1,-\mathrm {ct}(b_4')+s,\ldots ,-\mathrm {ct}(b_2')+s+2,-\mathrm {ct}(b_2')+s+1,-\mathrm {ct}(b_1')+s-1,-\mathrm {ct}(b_1')+s-2, -\mathrm {ct}(b_1')+s-3,\ldots \}$ . In a picture:

The only e-period which can shift to the left is $\mathrm {Per}^1$ which consists of the $\beta $ -numbers recording the nonzero parts of $\underline {\lambda }^t$ . Shifting $\mathrm {Per}^1$ to the left yields the action of $\Upsilon ^-_1$ and $\Upsilon ^-_k$ acts by $0$ for all $k\geq 2$ . Meanwhile, $\Upsilon ^-_1(\underline {\lambda }^t)$ replaces every part $(\lambda ^j)^t_i$ of $\underline {\lambda }^t$ with $(\lambda ^j)_i^t-1$ , i.e., it removes the shaded vertical strip which is the whole right border strip of $\underline {\lambda }^t$ . If both components of $\Upsilon ^-_1(\underline {\lambda }^t)$ are nonzero, then it satisfies Case (ii)(f), so then $(\Upsilon ^-_1(\underline {\lambda }^t))^t\in \mathcal {U}_{e,\underline {s}}^2$ . If $(\lambda ^1)^t$ or $(\lambda ^2)^t$ is a column but the other is not, then $\Upsilon ^-_1(\underline {\lambda }^t)=(\lambda ^t,\emptyset )$ or $(\emptyset ,\lambda ^t)$ labels a finite-dimensional unitary representation. If both $(\lambda ^1)^t$ and $(\lambda ^2)^t$ are columns, then $\Upsilon ^-_1(\underline {\lambda }^t)=(\emptyset ,\emptyset )$ , which labels the trivial representation of $\mathbb {C}=H_{c,d}(B_0)$ .▪

3.2 Classification of the supports of the unitary representations

For $\underline {\mu }\in \mathcal {P}^2$ , set $\tilde {a}_{(0)}\underline {\mu }=\underline {\mu }$ . For $I=(i_r,i_{r-1},\ldots ,i_1)$ , a sequence of elements $i_j\in \mathbb {Z}/e\mathbb {Z}$ , set $\tilde {f}_I=\tilde {f}_{i_r}\tilde {f}_{i_{r-1}}\ldots \tilde {f}_{i_1}$ . To unburden the notation, for fixed $\underline {s}$ , we will write $\underline {\lambda }^t$ in the following statement instead of $|\underline {\lambda }^t,\underline {s}\rangle \in \mathcal {F}^2_{e,\underline {s}}$ .

Corollary 3.2 Let $\underline {\lambda }\in \mathcal {U}^2_{e,\underline {s}}$ . Then, $\underline {\lambda }^t$ satisfies exactly one of the following six possibilities, unless $\underline {\lambda }^t$ has depth $0$ in both the $\widehat {\mathfrak {sl}}_e$ - and $\mathfrak {sl}_{\infty }$ -crystals in which case $\underline {\lambda }^t$ satisfies either (1) and (2), or (3) and (4), or (5) and (6), taking I to be the empty sequence.

  1. (1) $\underline {\lambda }^t=\tilde {f}_I(\emptyset ,\emptyset )$ for an appropriate sequence I of elements in $\mathbb {Z}/e\mathbb {Z}$ ,

  2. (2) $\underline {\lambda }^t=\tilde {a}_{(m)}(\emptyset ,\emptyset )$ for some $m\in \mathbb {N}\cup \{0\}$ ,

  3. (3) $\underline {\lambda }^t=\tilde {f}_I((r^q),\emptyset )$ for an appropriate sequence I of elements in $\mathbb {Z}/e\mathbb {Z}$ and some $r,q\in \mathbb {N}$ satisfying $r-q=s-e$ ,

  4. (4) $\underline {\lambda }^t=\tilde {a}_{(m)}((r^q),\emptyset )$ for some $m\in \mathbb {N}\cup \{0\}$ and some $r,q\in \mathbb {N}$ satisfying $r-q=s-e$ ,

  5. (5) $\underline {\lambda }^t=\tilde {f}_I(\emptyset ,(r^q))$ for an appropriate sequence I of elements in $\mathbb {Z}/e\mathbb {Z}$ and some $r,q\in \mathbb {N}$ satisfying $r-q=-s$ ,

  6. (6) $\underline {\lambda }^t=\tilde {a}_{(m)}(\emptyset ,(r^q))$ for some $m\in \mathbb {N}\cup \{0\}$ and some $r,q\in \mathbb {N}$ satisfying $r-q=-s$ .

Moreover, for a fixed n, all these situations are realized by some $\underline {\lambda }\in \mathcal {U}_{e,\underline {s}}^2(n)$ when it is numerically possible, i.e.: (1) occurs for any n; (2) occurs for any n divisible by e; (3) occurs whenever $rq\leq n$ and $r-q=s-e$ ; if, in addition, $n-rq$ is also divisible by e, then (4) occurs; whenever $rq\leq n$ and $r-q=-s$ , then (5) occurs; and if $n-rq$ is also divisible by e, then (6) occurs. In particular, Corollary 1.5 holds.

Proof The statements (1)–(6) and the examples of existence of all cases follow from the case-by-case examinations in the proof of Proposition 3.1 together with Theorem 1.1. Theorem 1.5 is the same statement in the language of supports by [Reference Montarani23].▪

We do not address here which sequences I occur in Cases (1), (3), and (5). Observe that if $\underline {\lambda }\in \mathcal {U}_{e,\underline {s}}^2$ , then $\underline {\lambda }^t$ cannot have nonzero depth in both the $\widehat {\mathfrak {sl}}_e$ - and $\mathfrak {sl}_{\infty }$ -crystals. Moreover, we see that the position $\sigma $ of $\underline {\lambda }^t$ in the $\mathfrak {sl}_{\infty }$ -crystal is always given by $\sigma =(m)$ for $m\in \mathbb {N}$ if $\underline {\lambda }\in \mathcal {U}_{e,\underline {s}}^2$ .

Corollary 3.3 Suppose $L(\underline {\mu })\in \mathcal {O}_{e,\underline {s}}(n+me)$ is a unitary irreducible representation with support equal to $B_{n+me}\mathfrak {h}^{W'}$ for $W'=B_n\times S_e^m$ . Then, (i) ${{}^{\mathcal {O}}\operatorname {Res}}^{B_{n+em}}_{B_{n+e(m-1)}\times S_e}L(\underline {\mu })$ is irreducible and equal to $L((\tilde {a}_{(m-1)}\underline {\lambda }^t)^t)\otimes L(e)$ , and (ii) ${{}^{\mathcal {O}}\operatorname {Res}}^{B_{n+em}}_{B_n\times S_e^{\times m}}L(\underline {\mu })$ is irreducible and equal to $L(\underline {\lambda })\otimes L(e)^{\otimes m}$ , where $\underline {\lambda }=((q^r),\emptyset )$ with $r-q=s-e$ or $\underline {\lambda }=(\emptyset ,(q^r))$ with $r-q=-s$ .

Proof By Corollary 3.2, $\underline {\mu }=(\tilde {a}_{(m)}\underline {\lambda }^t)^t$ for some $\underline {\lambda }$ labeling a unitary finite-dimensional representation, that is, $\underline {\mu }^t$ has depth m in the $\mathfrak {sl}_{\infty }$ crystal, its position $\sigma $ in its connected component of that crystal is given by the partition $\sigma =(m)$ , and the source vertex of its connected component is either $\underline {\lambda }^t=((r^q),\emptyset )$ with $r-q=s-e$ or $\underline {\lambda }^t=(\emptyset ,(r^q))$ with $r-q=-s$ (by Theorem 1.1). The statement now follows from [Reference Rouquier24, Proposition 4.3] and adjointness.▪

The supports of unitary representations are now classified as a set, but we can further unpack the implications of the proof of Proposition 3.1 by identifying which supports occur for which kinds of bipartitions in $\mathcal {U}_{e,\underline {s}}$ , and for which values of s. We see a very similar pattern to what happens for the partitions labeling unitary representations in type A, as we explain next.

Let us recall the condition for $L(\tau )\in \mathcal {O}_{\frac {1}{e}}(S_n)$ to be unitary. Take $b_4$ to be the removable box of $\tau $ of largest content, and take $b_5$ to be the box of $\tau $ of smallest content. Then, $L(\tau )$ is unitary if and only if $b_4-b_5+1\leq e$ . That is to say, the bottom border of $\tau $ as shaded in the diagram below must contain at most e boxes:

This follows from the classification given in [Reference Fishel, Griffeth and Manosalva11] and is a rephrasing of the e-abacus condition given in [Reference Bowman and Cox2, Section 4]. In particular, a partition $\tau $ such that $L(\tau )$ is unitary has at most e columns, and such $\tau $ has e columns if and only if $\tau =(e^m)$ for some $m\in \mathbb {N}$ . Set $\mathcal {O}_e=\bigoplus _{n\geq 0}\mathcal {O}_{\frac {1}{e}}(S_n)$ , and set $\mathcal {U}_e=\{\tau \in \mathcal {P}\mid L(\tau )\in \mathcal {O}_e \text { is unitary}\}$ .

If $\tau $ has less than e columns, then $L(\tau )$ always has cuspidal support $(L(1),\{1\})$ , i.e., $L(\tau )$ has full support [Reference Wilcox31]. On the other hand, if $\tau =(e^m)$ , then the cuspidal support of $L(\tau )$ is $(L(e)^{\otimes m}, S_e^{\times m})$ [Reference Wilcox31]. The $\mathfrak {sl}_{\infty }$ - and $\widehat {\mathfrak {sl}}_e$ -crystals on the set of all partitions $\mathcal {P}$ , which is equal to the level $1$ Fock space, are defined similarly as on $\mathcal {F}^2_{e,\underline {s}}$ . (However, in level $1$ , there is a shift by $1$ in the $\mathfrak {sl}_{\infty }$ -crystal, because the finite-dimensional representation $L(e)$ has depth $1$ , not depth $0$ , in the $\mathfrak {sl}_{\infty }$ -crystal: $(e)^t=\tilde {a}_{(1)}\emptyset $ .) The two crystals describe the supports of $L(\tau )\in \mathcal {O}_{\frac {1}{e}}(S_n)$ . If $\tau \in \mathcal {U}_e$ and $\tau \neq (e^m)$ , then $\tau ^t=\tilde {f}_I\emptyset $ for an appropriate sequence I of n elements of $\mathbb {Z}/e\mathbb {Z}$ . If $\tau =(e^m)\in \mathcal {U}_e$ , then $\tau ^t=\tilde {a}_{(m)}\emptyset $ .

3.2.1. Unitary bipartitions with type B support

We are going to look at which types of bipartitions in $\mathcal {U}_{e,\underline {s}}$ can have type B support or a mix of type B and type A supports. As we saw in the proof of Proposition 3.1, taking $I=(r+j,r+j-1,\ldots ,r)$ for any $j\geq 1$ and applying $\tilde {f}_I$ to a rectangle labeling a finite-dimensional unitary representation produces an instance of situation (5) above. But more generally, [Reference Jacon and Lecouvey19, Corollary 8.4, Case (d)], i.e., Case (i)(d) in the proof of Proposition 3.1, deals with partitions $\lambda $ such that $\lambda ^t=(r^q)+\tau ^t:=(r+(\tau ^t)_1, r+(\tau ^t)_2,\ldots , r+(\tau ^t)_q, (\tau ^t)_{q+1},\ldots )$ for some partition $\tau $ with at most $q-1$ columns. It says that $L(\lambda ,\emptyset )\in \mathcal {O}_{e,\underline {s}}$ is unitary if and only if $r-q=s-e$ and $L(\tau )\in \mathcal {O}_{\frac {1}{e}}(S_{|\tau |})$ is unitary. This occurs for any parameter $(e,\underline {s})$ .

In [Reference Jacon and Lecouvey19, Corollary 8.4, Case (d)], $\lambda $ consists of a rectangle $(q^r)$ labeling a finite-dimensional unitary representation with a type A unitary partition $\tau $ stacked underneath. The cuspidal support of $L(\lambda ,\emptyset )$ is then read directly off of $\lambda $ from the cuspidal supports of its two pieces: the cuspidal support consists of $L((q^r),\emptyset )\in \mathcal {O}_{e,\underline {s}}(rq)$ times the cuspidal support of $L_{\frac {1}{e}}(\tau )\in \mathcal {O}_{\frac {1}{e}}(S_{|\tau |})$ . If $\lambda \neq (q^r)$ , then we have $(\lambda ^t,\emptyset )=\tilde {f}_I((r^q),\emptyset )$ for an appropriate sequence I of elements of $\mathbb {Z}/e\mathbb {Z}$ . It is easy to see that each such sequence I is the shift of a sequence producing $\tau $ in the level $1$ crystal on $\mathcal {P}$ ; that is, the sequence $I-r:=(i_{|\tau |}-r,\ldots , i_1-r)$ satisfies $\tilde {f}_{I-r}\emptyset =\tau $ .

Example 3.4 Let $\underline {s}=(0,3)$ (so $s=3$ ) and $e=5$ . We look at the types of supports occurring in Case (i)(d) of the proof of Proposition 3.1, i.e., in [Reference Jacon and Lecouvey19, Corollary 8.4, Case (d)], taking the “cuspidal rectangle” $\lambda =(q^r)=(6^4)$ and stacking a “type A unitary partition” $\tau $ beneath it. We have $r-q=-2=s-e$ , so $L(\lambda ,\emptyset )$ is unitary and finite-dimensional by Theorem 1.1.

(a) Let $\underline {\lambda }=(\lambda ,\emptyset )=((6^4),\emptyset )$ . Then, $L(\underline {\lambda })\in \mathcal {O}_{e,\underline {s}}(24)$ is a finite-dimensional unitary representation.

The partition $\tau $ below the rectangle is the empty partition. The cuspidal support of $L(\underline {\lambda })$ is $(L(\underline {\lambda }),B_{24})$ . The depth of $\underline {\lambda }^t=((4^6),\emptyset )$ in the $\mathfrak {sl}_{\infty }$ - and $\widehat {\mathfrak {sl}}_5$ -crystals is $0$ .

(b) Let $\underline {\lambda }=(\lambda ,\emptyset )=((6^4,1^2),\emptyset )$ , so that $b_4=b_5$ . We break $\lambda $ into two pieces, the “cuspidal rectangle” on top of the “type A unitary partition” $(1^2)$ :

The cuspidal support of $L(\underline {\lambda })$ is $(L((6^4),\emptyset )\otimes L(1)^{\otimes 2},B_{24}\times S_1^2)\simeq (L((6^4),\emptyset ),B_{24})$ and $\underline {\lambda }^t=\tilde {f}_5\tilde {f}_4((4^6),\emptyset )$ .

(c) Let $\underline {\lambda }=(\lambda ,\emptyset )=((6^4,3^3,2,1),\emptyset )$ . Then, $\mathrm {ct}(b_4)-\mathrm {ct}(b_5)+1=5=e$ . We break $\lambda $ into two pieces, the “cuspidal rectangle” on top of the “type A unitary”:

We then read off the cuspidal support of $L(\underline {\lambda })$ from the two pieces: it is equal to $(L((6^4),\emptyset ), B_{24})$ times the cuspidal support of $L(3^3,2,1)\in \mathcal {O}_{\frac {1}{5}}(S_{12}).$ Because $\tau $ is not a rectangle of width $5$ , we conclude that the cuspidal support of $L(\underline {\lambda })$ is $(L((6^4),\emptyset )\otimes L(1)^{\otimes 12},B_{24}\otimes S_1^{ 12})\simeq (L((6^4),\emptyset ),B_{24})$ and that $\underline {\lambda }^t=\tilde {f}_I((4^6),\emptyset )$ for any sequence $I=(i_{12},\ldots , i_1)$ such that $ \tilde {f}_{i_{12}-4}\ldots \tilde {f}_{i_1-4}\emptyset =\tau ^t$ in the $\widehat {\mathfrak {sl}}_5$ -crystal on $\mathcal {P}$ .

(d) Let $\underline {\lambda }=((6^4,5^3),\emptyset )$ . Then, $\mathrm {ct}(b_4)-\mathrm {ct}(b_5)+1=5=e$ . We break $\lambda $ into two pieces, the “cuspidal rectangle” on top of the “type A unitary”:

Because $\tau $ is a rectangle of width $5=e$ and height $3$ , $\tau $ has depth $3$ in the $\mathfrak {sl}_{\infty }$ -crystal on $\mathcal {P}$ and is obtained as $\tilde {a}_{(3)}(\emptyset )=\tau ^t$ . In the $\mathfrak {sl}_{\infty }$ -crystal on $\mathcal {F}_{e,\underline {s}}^2$ , we have $\underline {\lambda }^t=\tilde {a}_{(3)}((4^6),\emptyset )$ . The cuspidal support of $L(\underline {\lambda })$ is $(L((6^4),\emptyset )\otimes L(5)^{\otimes 3},B_{24}\times S_5^3)$ .

In Case (i)(e), a similar phenomenon can occur, but with the width of $\tau $ allowed to be equal to the width q of the “cuspidal rectangle” $(q^r)$ on top of it for $q\leq e$ .

Example 3.5 Let $e=7$ and $\underline {s}=(0,6)$ . Then, for any rectangle $(q^r)$ with $q-r=1$ , $L((q^r),\emptyset )\in \mathcal {O}_{e,\underline {s}}(qr)$ is finite-dimensional and unitary. Let $\underline {\lambda }=((3^6,1),\emptyset )$ . The cuspidal support of $L(\underline {\lambda })$ is $(L((3^2),\emptyset )\otimes L(1)^{13},B_{6}\times S_1^{13})\simeq (L((3^2),\emptyset ),B_6)$ :

Next, let us discuss the necessary and sufficient conditions for $L(\underline {\lambda })$ , $\underline {\lambda }=(\lambda ^1,\lambda ^2)\in \mathcal {U}_{e,\underline {s}}$ with both $\lambda ^1,\lambda ^2$ nonempty, to have part of its support be of type B. First, consider the case that the depth of $\underline {\lambda }^t$ in the $\widehat {\mathfrak {sl}}_e$ -crystal is nonzero (so that its depth in the $\mathfrak {sl}_{\infty }$ -crystal is $0$ ). We saw in the proof that if $\underline {\lambda }=(\lambda ^1,\lambda ^2)$ with $\lambda ^j=(1)$ for $j=1 $ or $j=2$ and both $\lambda ^1,\lambda ^2\neq \emptyset $ , then the cases that arise when removing the unique box from $\lambda ^j$ are [Reference Jacon and Lecouvey19, Corollary 8.4, Cases (a) and (b)]. Assume that $\lambda ^2=(1)$ is removed by some $\tilde {e}_i$ , the other case $\lambda ^1=(1)$ being similar. Recall that [Reference Jacon and Lecouvey19, Corollary 8.4, Cases (a) and (b)] require $\mathrm {ct}(b_1)\leq e-s$ . It is impossible for any $(\lambda ,\emptyset )$ belonging to these cases to arise as $(\lambda ,\emptyset )^t=\tilde {f}_I((r^q),\emptyset )$ with $r-q=s-e$ , except when $\lambda =(e-s+1)$ is a row of length at most e with $0<s\leq e$ . It follows that if both components $\lambda ^1$ and $\lambda ^2$ of $\underline {\lambda }$ are nonempty, $\underline {\lambda }\in \mathcal {U}_{e,\underline {s}}$ , and the depth of $\underline {\lambda }^t$ in the $\mathfrak {sl}_{\infty }$ -crystal is $0$ , then one of the following holds:

  • $\underline {\lambda }^t=\tilde {f}_I(\emptyset ,\emptyset )$ for an appropriate sequence I.

  • $0<s\leq e$ and $\underline {\lambda }^t=\tilde {f}_I(1^{e-s+1},\emptyset )$ for an appropriate sequence I.

  • $0\leq s<e$ and $\underline {\lambda }^t=\tilde {f}_I(\emptyset , 1^{s+1})$ for an appropriate sequence I.

The latter two situations do occur.

Example 3.6 Take $e=5$ and $\underline {s}=(0,3)$ . Let $\underline {\lambda }=((3),\emptyset ).$ Then, $L(\underline {\lambda })$ is unitary and finite-dimensional. Applying $\tilde {f}_3\tilde {f}_4\tilde {f}_0\tilde {f}_1$ to $\underline {\lambda }^t$ , we get $\tilde {f}_I\underline {\lambda }^t=((2^3),(1))$ for $I=(3,4,0,1)$ . Then, $((2^3),(1))^t=((3^2),(1))\in \mathcal {U}_{e,\underline {s}}$ by [Reference Jacon and Lecouvey19, Corollary 8.5, Case (b)].

We have already looked at the case of nonzero depth in the $\mathfrak {sl}_{\infty }$ -crystal in detail in Case (ii)(f) of the proof of Proposition 3.1. Let $r-q=s-e$ . Let $\underline {\lambda }^t=\tilde {a}_{(m)}((r^q),\emptyset )$ . Then, $\underline {\lambda }$ will have its second component $\lambda ^2$ nonempty if and only if $\mathrm {Per}^1$ of the abacus $|((r^q),\emptyset ),\underline {s}\rangle $ contains beads from the top row of the abacus. This is the case if and only if $e>q$ .

Example 3.7 Let $\underline {\lambda }=((4^{14}),(1^2))$ . If $e=5$ and $\underline {s}=(0,13)$ , then $\underline {\lambda }^t=\tilde {a}_{(2)}|((12^4),\emptyset ),\underline {s}\rangle $ . The cuspidal support of $L(\underline {\lambda })\in \mathcal {O}_{e,\underline {s}}$ is $(L((12^4),\emptyset )\otimes L(5)^{\otimes 2},B_{48}\times S_5^{\times 2})$ .

3.3 Semisimplicity and restriction

We now return to establishing Theorem 1.4.

Proposition 3.8 Let $L(\underline {\lambda })\in \mathcal {O}_{e,\underline {s}}(n)$ be a unitary irreducible representation. Then, either ${{}^{\mathcal {O}}\operatorname {Res}}^n_{n-1}L(\underline {\lambda })$ is semisimple or it is $0$ .

Proof As in Proposition 3.1, we break the proof into two main cases: (i) when $\underline {\lambda }=(\lambda ,\emptyset )$ for some $\lambda \in \mathcal {P}(n)$ and (ii) when $\underline {\lambda }=(\lambda ^1,\lambda ^2)$ with both $\lambda ^1,\lambda ^2\neq \emptyset $ . The case that $\underline {\lambda }=(\emptyset ,\lambda )$ follows from that for $\underline {\lambda }$ as in [Reference Jacon and Lecouvey19, Corollary 8.4]. In Case (i), we check the cases from [Reference Jacon and Lecouvey19, Corollary 8.4] for unitarity of $L(\lambda ,\emptyset )$ . In Case (ii), we check the cases from [Reference Jacon and Lecouvey19, Corollary 8.5] for unitarity of $L(\lambda ^1,\lambda ^2)$ .

$\underline{\textit{Case (i): } {\lambda }=(\lambda ,\emptyset ) \textit{ for some partition } \lambda \textit{ of n}.}$

If $\lambda =(1^n)$ , then $\lambda $ has only one removable box, so Lemma 2.8 says that ${{}^{\mathcal {O}}\operatorname {Res}}^n_{n-1}L(\underline {\lambda })$ is irreducible or $0$ . From now on, assume $\lambda \neq (1^n)$ .

$\underline{\textit{Cases (i)(a)}-\textit{(c),(e)}}$ . Because $\mathrm {ct}(b_2)\leq \mathrm {ct}(b_1)$ , in Cases (a), (b), and (e), it holds that $\mathrm {ct}(b_2)-\mathrm {ct}(b_5)+1\leq e$ . In Case (c), we have $\mathrm {ct}(b_5)\geq -s$ and $\mathrm {ct}(b_2)<e-s$ , yielding $\mathrm {ct}(b_2)-\mathrm {ct}(b_5)+1\leq e$ as well in this case. The contents of removable boxes in $\lambda $ belong to the interval of integers $[-\mathrm {ct}(b_5),\mathrm {ct}(b_2)]$ which contains $\mathrm {ct}(b_2)-\mathrm {ct}(b_5)+1$ distinct integers. Thus, no $i\in \mathbb {Z}/e\mathbb {Z}$ appears more than once as $\mathrm {ct}(b)\mod e$ for a removable box $b\in \lambda $ . By Lemma 2.8, then ${{}^{\mathcal {O}}\operatorname {Res}}^n_{n-1}L(\underline {\lambda })$ is semisimple or $0$ .

$\underline{\textit{Case (i)(d)}}$ . In Case (d), it is required that $\mathrm {ct}(b_2)=e-s$ . If $\lambda $ is a rectangle or $b_4=b_5$ , then this is the only condition. We deal with these subcases first. If $\lambda $ is a rectangle, then it labels a finite-dimensional representation by Theorem 1.1, hence ${{}^{\mathcal {O}}\operatorname {Res}}^n_{n-1}L(\underline {\lambda })=0$ by [Reference Bowman, Cox and Hazi3]. If $b_4=b_5$ and $\mathrm {ct}(b_2)\neq \mathrm {ct}(b_5)\mod e$ , then we may apply Lemma 2.8 to conclude that ${{}^{\mathcal {O}}\operatorname {Res}}^n_{n-1}L(\underline {\lambda })$ is semisimple or $0$ (in fact, it is either irreducible or $0$ , because $b_2^t$ is not a good removable box in $|\underline {\lambda }^t,\underline {s}\rangle $ , as we see next).

Now, assume $b_4=b_5$ , $\mathrm {ct}(b_2)= \mathrm {ct}(b_5)\mod e$ , and $b_2\neq b_4$ , that is, $\lambda $ has exactly two removable boxes and the box of smallest content in $\lambda $ is one of them. Because $\mathrm {ct}(b_2)=e-s$ , in $\lambda ^t$ , the box $b_2^t$ has content $s-e$ , so by Lemma 2.7, it is not a good removable s-box, because it cancels with the addable s-box in Component $2$ of $|\underline {\lambda }^t,\underline {s}\rangle $ . The box $b_5^t$ is also an s-box of $|\underline {\lambda }^t,\underline {s}\rangle $ by assumption. There is no addable s-box of larger charged content. Therefore, $b_5^t$ is the good removable s-box of $|\underline {\lambda }^t,\underline {s}\rangle $ , and $\tilde {e}_s(\underline {\lambda }^t)=\underline {\lambda }^t\setminus b_5^t$ . It remains to show that ${{}^{\mathcal {O}}\operatorname {Res}}^n_{n-1}L(\underline {\lambda })$ is irreducible, because a priori it could be an extension. We have ${{}^{\mathcal {O}}\operatorname {Res}}^n_{n-1}L(\underline {\lambda })\twoheadrightarrow L((\tilde {e}_s(\underline {\lambda }^t))^t)=L(\underline {\lambda }\setminus b_5)$ . By exactness of ${{}^{\mathcal {O}}\operatorname {Res}}^n_{n-1}$ , then ${{}^{\mathcal {O}}\operatorname {Res}}^n_{n-1}\Delta (\underline {\lambda })\twoheadrightarrow L(\underline {\lambda }\setminus b_5)$ . Because $\lambda $ has no removable boxes besides $b_2$ and $b_5$ , $[{{}^{\mathcal {O}}\operatorname {Res}}^n_{n-1}\Delta (\underline {\lambda })]=[\Delta (\underline {\lambda }\setminus b_5)]+[\Delta (\underline {\lambda }\setminus b_2)]$ [Reference Bowman, Cox and Hazi3]. Observe that $c_{\underline {\lambda }\setminus b_5}>c_{\underline {\lambda }\setminus b_2}$ . Therefore, $[\Delta (\underline {\lambda }\setminus b_2):L(\underline {\lambda }\setminus b_5)]=0$ , so $[{{}^{\mathcal {O}}\operatorname {Res}}^n_{n-1}\Delta (\underline {\lambda }):L(\underline {\lambda }\setminus b_5)]=[\Delta (\underline {\lambda }\setminus b_5):L(\underline {\lambda }\setminus b_5)]=1$ . We deduce that $[{{}^{\mathcal {O}}\operatorname {Res}}^n_{n-1}L(\underline {\lambda }):L(\underline {\lambda }\setminus b_5)]=1$ . Because the socle of ${{}^{\mathcal {O}}\operatorname {Res}}^n_{n-1}L(\underline {\lambda })$ is equal to the head of ${{}^{\mathcal {O}}\operatorname {Res}}^n_{n-1}L(\underline {\lambda })$ , we conclude that ${{}^{\mathcal {O}}\operatorname {Res}}^n_{n-1}L(\underline {\lambda })=L(\underline {\lambda }\setminus b_5)$ .

Next, we consider the case $b_4\neq b_5$ . Then, in addition to $\mathrm {ct}(b_2)=e-s$ , it is required that $\mathrm {ct}(b_3)-\mathrm {ct}(b_5)+1\leq e$ or $e=\ell -\mathrm {ct}(b_5)+1$ for some $b_4\leq \ell <b_3$ . These two alternative conditions are equivalent to a single condition: $\mathrm {ct}(b_4)-\mathrm {ct}(b_5)+1\leq e$ . Let R be the set of removable boxes of $\lambda $ . It follows that for all $b\neq b'\in R\setminus b_2$ , $\mathrm {ct}(b)\neq \mathrm {ct}(b')\mod e$ . Then, we argue as in Lemma 2.8 that $\mathsf {E}_iL(\underline {\lambda })$ is irreducible or $0$ for all $i\neq s\mod e$ . If some box $b\in R$ has the same content mod e as $b_2$ , then we argue as in the previous paragraph that $\mathsf {E}_sL(\underline {\lambda })=L(\underline {\lambda }\setminus b)$ .

$\underline{\textit{Case(ii):}\ {\lambda }=(\lambda ^1,\lambda ^2)\ \textit{with both}\ \lambda ^1,\lambda ^2\neq \emptyset.}$

As in Proposition 3.1, it is sufficient to check the conditions for unitarity in Cases (a), (b), and (f) of [Reference Jacon and Lecouvey19, Corollary 8.5]. For any $\underline {\lambda }\in \mathcal {P}^2$ , it holds that $\mathrm {ct}(b_4)\leq \mathrm {ct}(b_2)\leq \mathrm {ct}(b_1)$ and $\mathrm {ct}(b_4')\leq \mathrm {ct}(b_2')\leq \mathrm {ct}(b_1')$ . In all three cases (a), (b), and (f), we then have $\mathrm {ct}(b_2)-\mathrm {ct}(b_4')+1\leq e-s$ and $\mathrm {ct}(b_2')-\mathrm {ct}(b_4)+1\leq s$ . It follows that $-\mathrm {ct}(b_2)\leq -\mathrm {ct}(b_4)<-\mathrm {ct}(b_2')+s\leq -\mathrm {ct}(b_4')+s<-\mathrm {ct}(b_2)+e$ . Therefore, each $i\in \mathbb {Z}/e\mathbb {Z}$ occurs at most once as $\widetilde {\mathrm {ct}}(b)\mod e$ for a removable box b of $|\underline {\lambda }^t,\underline {s}\rangle $ . By Lemma 2.8, ${{}^{\mathcal {O}}\operatorname {Res}}^n_{n-1}L(\underline {\lambda })$ is semisimple or $0$ .▪

Acknowledgment

I would like to thank C. Bowman, P. Etingof, T. Gerber, S. Griffeth, and J. Simental for useful discussions. I would like to especially thank J. Simental for bringing to my attention Montarani’s work in [Reference Ruff25]. I would also like to thank the anonymous referees for their helpful feedback to improve the exposition of this paper.

Footnotes

Part of this work was carried out under the auspices of the grant SFB-TRR 195.

References

Berest, Y., Etingof, P., and Ginzburg, V., Finite-dimensional representations of rational Cherednik algebras. Int. Math. Res. Not. IMRN 19(2003), 10531088.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berkesch Zamaere, C., Griffeth, S., and Sam, S. V., Jack polynomials as fractional quantum Hall states and the Betti numbers of the $\left(k+1\right)$ -equals ideal. Comm. Math. Phys. 330(2014), no. 1, 415434.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bezrukavnikov, R. and Etingof, P., Parabolic induction and restriction functors for rational Cherednik algebras. Selecta Math. (N.S.). 14(2009), nos. 3–4, 397425.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bowman, C. and Cox, A. G., Modular decomposition numbers of cyclotomic Hecke and diagrammatic Cherednik algebras: a path theoretic approach. Forum Math. Sigma. 6(2018), e11.Google Scholar
Bowman, C., Cox, A. G., and Hazi, A., Path isomorphisms between quiver Hecke and diagrammatic Bott–Samelson endomorphism algebras. Preprint, 2021. arXiv:2005.02825 Google Scholar
Bowman, C., Hazi, A., and Norton, E., The modular Weyl–Kac character formula. Preprint, 2020. arXiv:2004.13082 Google Scholar
Bowman, C., Norton, E., and Simental, J., Characteristic-free bases and BGG resolutions of unitary simple modules for quiver Hecke and Cherednik algebras. Preprint, 2018. arXiv:1803:08736 Google Scholar
Chuang, J. and Miyachi, H., Runner removal Morita equivalences. In Representation theory of algebraic groups and quantum groups, Progr. Math., 284, Birkhäuser/Springer, New York, (editor: Gyoja, Akihiko, Nakajima, Hiraku, Shinoda, Ken-ichi, Shoji, Toshiaki, Tanisaki, Toshiyuki) 2010, pp. 5579.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chuang, J. and Rouquier, R., Derived equivalences for symmetric groups and ${sl}_2$ -categorifications. Ann. Math. (2). 167(2008), no. 1, 245298.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Etingof, P. and Ginzburg, V., Symplectic reflection algebras, Calogero–Moser space, and deformed Harish–Chandra homomorphism. Invent. Math. 147(2002), no. 2, 243348.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Etingof, P. and Stoica, E., Unitary representations of rational Cherednik algebras. Represent. Theory. 13(2009), 349370, With an appendix by S. Griffeth.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fishel, S., Griffeth, S., and Manosalva, E., Unitary representations of the rational Cherednik algebra: $V$ -homology. Math. Z. 299(2021), 22152255 Preprint, 2020. arXiv:2008.04412 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gerber, T., Triple crystal action in Fock spaces. Adv. Math. 329(2018), 916954.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gerber, T., Heisenberg algebra, wedges and crystals. J. Algebraic Combin. 49(2019), no. 1, 99124.Google Scholar
Gerber, T. and Norton, E., The ${sl}_{\infty }$ -crystal combinatorics of higher level Fock spaces. J. Comb. Algebra. 2(2018), no. 2, 103145.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ginzburg, V., Guay, N., Opdam, E., and Rouquier, R., On the category $\mathcal{O}$ for rational Cherednik algebras. Invent. Math. 154(2007), 617651.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gorsky, E., Simental, J., and Vazirani, M., Parabolic Hilbert schemes via the Dunkl–Opdam subalgebra. Preprint, 2020. arXiv:2004.14873 Google Scholar
Griffeth, S., Orthogonal functions generalizing Jack polynomials. Trans. Amer. Math. Soc. 362(2010), no. 11, 61316157.Google Scholar
Griffeth, S., Unitary representations of cyclotomic rational Cherednik algebras. J. Algebra. 512(2018), 310356.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Griffeth, S., Gusenbauer, A., Juteau, D., and Lanini, M., Parabolic degeneration of rational Cherednik algebras. Selecta Math. 23(2017), no. 4, 27052754.Google Scholar
Jacon, N. and Lecouvey, C., A combinatorial decomposition of higher level Fock spaces. Osaka J. Math. 50(2013), no. 4, 897920.Google Scholar
Jimbo, M., Misra, K. C., Miwa, T., and Okado, M., Combinatorics of representations of ${U}_q(\hat{sl(n)})$ at q = 0. Comm. Math. Phys. 136(1991), no. 3, 543566.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Losev, I., Rational Cherednik algebras and categorification . In: Beliakova, A. and Lauda, A. (eds.), Categorification and higher representation theory, Contemp. Math. 683, Amer. Math. Soc., Providence, RI, 2017, 141.Google Scholar
Losev, I., Supports of simple modules in cyclotomic Cherednik categories O. Advances in Mathematics 377(2021), 107491 Preprint, 2020. arXiv:1509.00526 Google Scholar
Montarani, S., On some finite dimensional representations of symplectic reflection algebras associated to wreath products. Comm. Algebra. 35(2007), no. 5, 14491467.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rouquier, R., q-Schur algebras and complex reflection groups. Mosc. Math. J. 8 (2008), no. 1, 119158, 184.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ruff, O., Completely splittable representations of symmetric groups and affine Hecke algebras. J. Algebra. 305(2006), no. 2, 11971211.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shan, P., Crystals of Fock spaces and cyclotomic rational double affine Hecke algebras. Ann. Sci. Éc. Norm. Supér. 44(2011), 147182.Google Scholar
Shan, P. and Vasserot, E., Heisenberg algebras and rational double affine Hecke algebras. J. Amer. Math. Soc. 25(2012), no. 4, 9591031.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shelley-Abrahamson, S., The Dunkl weight function for rational Cherednik algebras. Selecta Math. 26(2020), 8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilcox, S., Supports of representations of the rational Cherednik algebra of type A. Adv. Math. 314(2017), 426492.CrossRefGoogle Scholar