Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-s2hrs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-16T14:59:14.210Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

AN ALGEBRAIC PROOF OF COMPLETENESS FOR MONADIC FUZZY PREDICATE LOGIC $\mathbf {MMTL}\boldsymbol {\forall }$

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  18 October 2023

JUNTAO WANG
Affiliation:
SCHOOL OF SCIENCE XI’AN SHIYOU UNIVERSITY XI’AN, SHAANXI 710065 CHINA E-mail: [email protected]
HONGWEI WU
Affiliation:
SCHOOL OF SCIENCE XI’AN SHIYOU UNIVERSITY XI’AN, SHAANXI 710065 CHINA E-mail: [email protected]
PENGFEI HE
Affiliation:
SCHOOL OF MATHEMATICS AND STATISTICS SHAANXI NORMAL UNIVERSITY XI’AN, SHAANXI 710119 CHINA E-mail: [email protected]
YANHONG SHE*
Affiliation:
SCHOOL OF SCIENCE XI’AN SHIYOU UNIVERSITY XI’AN, SHAANXI 710065 CHINA
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Monoidal t-norm based logic $\mathbf {MTL}$ is the weakest t-norm based residuated fuzzy logic, which is a $[0,1]$-valued propositional logical system having a t-norm and its residuum as truth function for conjunction and implication. Monadic fuzzy predicate logic $\mathbf {mMTL\forall }$ that consists of the formulas with unary predicates and just one object variable, is the monadic fragment of fuzzy predicate logic $\mathbf {MTL\forall }$, which is indeed the predicate version of monoidal t-norm based logic $\mathbf {MTL}$. The main aim of this paper is to give an algebraic proof of the completeness theorem for monadic fuzzy predicate logic $\mathbf {mMTL\forall }$ and some of its axiomatic extensions. Firstly, we survey the axiomatic system of monadic algebras for t-norm based residuated fuzzy logic and amend some of them, thus showing that the relationships for these monadic algebras completely inherit those for corresponding algebras. Subsequently, using the equivalence between monadic fuzzy predicate logic $\mathbf {mMTL\forall }$ and S5-like fuzzy modal logic $\mathbf {S5(MTL)}$, we prove that the variety of monadic MTL-algebras is actually the equivalent algebraic semantics of the logic $\mathbf {mMTL\forall }$, giving an algebraic proof of the completeness theorem for this logic via functional monadic MTL-algebras. Finally, we further obtain the completeness theorem of some axiomatic extensions for the logic $\mathbf {mMTL\forall }$, and thus give a major application, namely, proving the strong completeness theorem for monadic fuzzy predicate logic based on involutive monoidal t-norm logic $\mathbf {mIMTL\forall }$ via functional representation of finitely subdirectly irreducible monadic IMTL-algebras.

MSC classification

Type
Research Article
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Association for Symbolic Logic

1 Introduction

The reader is assumed to know basic facts on monadic fuzzy predicate logics and their Kripke semantics, including the most well-known fuzzy modal logic S5; on the other hand, he/she is also assumed to know t-norm based residuated fuzzy logic as presented in the most famous books [Reference Hájek26, Reference Noguera37]. Fuzzy logic is more suitable than classical logic to handle uncertain and fuzzy information, has become a subject of increasing interest as logics of vagueness [Reference Zadeh56]. Algebraic semantics underlying fuzzy logic involve various binary operations on the unit real interval $[0,1]$ , generalizing the classical Boolean truth functions on $\{0,1\}$ . For example, MV-algebras were introduced in [Reference Chang5] by Chang as algebraic semantics of the infinitely valued logic of Łukasiewicz , while BL-algebras were introduced in [Reference Hájek26] by Hájek as algebraic semantics of Basic fuzzy logic $\mathbf {BL}$ , a general framework in which tautologies of continuous t-norm and their residua can be captured [Reference Cignoli, Esteva, Godo and Torrens8]. Inspired by Hájek’s famous work, Esteva and Godo proposed in [Reference Esteva, Gispert, Godo and Montagan15] a new formal deductive system $\mathbf {MTL}$ , called monoidal t-norm based logic, and intended to cope with left-continuous t-norms and their residua [Reference Jenei and Montagan33]. These logical systems have been called t-norm based residuated fuzzy logics and can be suitably placed in a hierarchy of logic depending on their characteristic axioms, all of them being extensions of the logic $\mathbf {MTL}$ , which also shows that the logic $\mathbf {MTL}$ is the weakest t-norm based residuated fuzzy logic, and having classical logic as common extension [Reference Noguera37]. In the past two decades, studies in $\mathbf {MTL}$ and its formal extensions as well as on the algebraic semantics side draw attention to and establish strong connections between the fields [Reference Borzooei, Shoar and Ameri2, Reference Cignoli and Esteva7, Reference Cintula, Horčík and Noguera9, Reference Cintula and Noguera10, Reference Esteva, Gispert, Godo and Montagan15, Reference Esteva and Godo17, Reference Ghorbani20, Reference Gottwal and Jenei24, Reference Hájek27, Reference Pei39, Reference Zhang58].

Monadic (Boolean) algebra $(L,\exists )$ , in the sense of Halmos [Reference Halmos32], is a Boolean algebra L equipped with a closure operator $\exists $ , which abstracts algebraic properties of the standard existential quantifier “for some” [Reference Tharp46]. The name “monadic” comes from the connection with predicate logics for languages having one placed predicates and just a single quantifier. Subsequently, monadic MV-algebras, the algebraic counterpart of monadic Łukasiewicz predicate logic, were introduced and studied in [Reference Di Nola and Grigolia11, Reference Di Nola, Grigolia and Lenzi12, Reference Hájek, Paris and Shepherdson31, Reference Rach ů nek and Šalounová42, Reference Rutledge45]. In order to algebraize the monadic basic fuzzy predicate logic $\mathbf {mBL\forall }$ , three kinds of monadic BL-algebras have been introduced and studied successively, one by Drăgulici [Reference Drŭgulici13], one by Grigolia [Reference Grigolia25] and another by Castaño [Reference Castaño, Cimadamore, Verela and Rueda4]. Along with the same line of the above works, monadic residuated $\ell $ -monoids [Reference Rach ů nek and Švrček44], residuated lattices [Reference Rach ů nek and Šalounová43], bounded hoops [Reference Wang, He, Yang, Wang and He49], Heyting algebras [Reference Dzik and Wojtylak14, Reference Kurahashi34, Reference Olkhovikov and Badia38, Reference Poacik41] and other related monadic algebraic structures were introduced in [Reference Ghorbani21, Reference Wang, He and She48Reference Wang, Xin and He54]. However, it should be pointed out here that some monadic algebras of t-norm based fuzzy residuated logic abandon the naturally containing relations between corresponding algebras. Indeed, readers please refer to Sections 2 and 3 for details,

$$ \begin{align*} \mathbb{RL_\ell}=\mathbb{RL}+\textrm{DIV}, \text{ but } \mathbb{MRL_\ell}\neq\mathbb{MRL}+\textrm{DIV} \end{align*} $$

and

$$ \begin{align*} \mathbb{MV}=\mathbb{BL}+\textrm{INV}, \text{ but } \mathbb{MMV}\neq \mathrm{ Dr}\breve{\rm a}\mathrm{gulici's }\ \mathbb{MBL}+\textrm{INV}. \end{align*} $$

Thus the first aim of this paper is to make up this important drawback. In Section 2, we survey monadic algebras of t-norm based fuzzy residuated logic and revise some of their axiomatic systems, then showing that the relationships between monadic algebras of t-norm based fuzzy residuated logic completely conserve those between corresponding algebras of t-norm based fuzzy residuated logic.

In order to generalize fuzzy predicate logic $\mathbf {BL\forall }$ [Reference Hájek26, Reference Hájek28Reference Hájek30], Esteva and Godo introduced a weaker fuzzy predicate logic $\mathbf {MTL\forall }$ , which was built up from variables, predicate symbols, connectives $\sqcap $ (additive conjunction), $ \& $ (multiplicative conjunction), $\sqcup $ (additive disjunction), $\Rightarrow $ (multiplicative implication), the constant $\bar{0} $ , and the quantifiers $\exists $ and $\forall $ [Reference Esteva and Godo16, Reference Esteva, Godo and Noguera18]. From the application point of view, fuzzy predicate logic is one of the most important techniques for the representation of knowledge. A familiarity with fuzzy predicate logic is important for the following reasons. First of all, logic is a formal method for reasoning. Many concepts that can be verbalized can also be translated into symbolic representations that closely approximate the meaning of these concepts. These symbolic structures can then be manipulated in programs to deduce various facts to carry out a form of automated reasoning. Second, logic offers the only formal approach to reasoning that has a sound theoretical foundation. This is especially important in order to mechanize or automate the reasoning process in that inferences should be correct and logically sound [Reference Torsun47].

Subsequently, Montagna and Ono introduced a Kripke semantics for $\mathbf {MTL\forall }$ , and proved a completeness theorem of $\mathbf {MTL\forall }$ with respect to the above mentioned Kripke semantics [Reference Montagna and Ono36]. As an important monadic fragment of fuzzy predicate logic $\mathbf {MTL\forall }$ , monadic fuzzy predicate logic $\mathbf {mMTL\forall }$ , in which only a single individual variable occurs, has attracted an increasing amount of experts and scholars’ attention in recent years [Reference Hájek28, Reference Wang, He and She48Reference Wang, Xin and He54]. Along with the same lines of Hájek’s equivalence between monadic fuzzy predicate logic $\mathbf {mBL\forall }$ and fuzzy modal logic $\mathbf {S5(BL)}$ [Reference Hájek30], monadic fuzzy predicate logic $\mathbf {mMTL\forall }$ is actually equivalent to fuzzy modal logic $\mathbf {S5(MTL)}$ because there is a natural correspondence between formulas of both logics, and between corresponding models and between the corresponding truth degrees. Thus in this paper we will work in the language of the fuzzy modal logic $\mathbf {S5(MTL)}$ instead of in the monadic fuzzy predicate language of $\mathbf {mMTL{\forall }}$ . The logic $\mathbf {S5(MTL)}$ is defined semantically over the language of $\mathbf {MTL}$ augmented with the unary connectives and $\square $ , known as Kripke semantics, readers please refer to Section 4 for details. Several researchers initially were only interested in the tautologies of $\mathbf {S5(MTL)}$ and its axiomatic extensions, but in [Reference Hájek30], a global consequence relation $\models _{\mathbf {S5(MTL)}}$ , which is finitary since $\mathbf {mMTL\forall }$ is a fragment of a finitary logic $\mathbf {MTL\forall }$ , is considered.

Latterly, Zahiri and Borumand Saeid [Reference Zahiri and Borumand Saeid57] have also introduced monadic monoidal t-norm based logic $\mathbf {MMTL}$ , which is a system of many valued logic capturing the tautologies of monadic MTL-algebras. The logic $\mathbf {MMTL}$ is actually a Hilbert-style syntactic calculus in the language of $\mathbf {S5(MTL)}$ , which is a logic $\mathbf {MTL}$ also together with the following axioms:

  • ,

  • $(\square 2)$ $\square (\nu \Rightarrow \varphi )\Rightarrow (\nu \Rightarrow \square \varphi )$ ,

  • ,

  • $(\square 3)$ $\square (\nu \sqcup \varphi )\Rightarrow (\nu \sqcup \square \varphi )$ ,

  • ,

where $\varphi $ is any formula and $\nu $ is any propositional combination of formulas beginning with and $\square $ . The inference rules are Modus Ponens $\mathbf {MP}$ : $\varphi $ , $\varphi \Rightarrow \phi \vdash \phi $ and Necessitation Rule $\mathbf {Nec}: \varphi /\square \varphi $ and the consequence relation is denoted by $\vdash _{\mathbf {S5(MTL)}}$ .

The second main goal of this paper is to investigate the consistency of the syntactic and the semantic for the logic $\mathbf {mMTL\forall }$ . This aim can be equivalently transformed into studying the corresponding consistency of $\mathbf {S5(MTL)}$ by the equivalence of the logics $\mathbf {mMTL\forall }$ and $\mathbf {S5(MTL)}$ . In order to achieve this goal, we have to prove

$$ \begin{align*} \models_{\mathbf{S5(MTL)}} \text{ if and only if } \vdash_{\mathbf{S5(MTL)}}, \end{align*} $$

and thus prove the completeness theorem of the logic $\mathbf {S5(MTL)}$ . In Sections 3 and 4, we aim to prove this important result by using algebraic methods, and obtain some partial results towards this goal in Section 5.

This paper is organized as follows: Section 2 summarizes some notions about t-norm based residuated fuzzy logics and their corresponding monadic fuzzy logics. Section 3 surveys the present state of knowledge on monadic algebras of t-norm based fuzzy residuated logic. Section 4 proves the completeness theorem for the logic $\mathbf {mMTL\forall }$ and its axiomatic extensions. Section 5 proves the strong completeness theorem for the logic $\mathbf {mIMTL\forall }$ .

2 Preliminaries

In this section, we summarize some results about t-norm based residuated fuzzy logics and their corresponding monadic fuzzy predicate logics. In particular, all of t-norm based residuated fuzzy logics are extensions of the so-called monoidal logic ( $\mathbf {ML}$ for short) [Reference Gottwal, García-Cerdaña and Bou23], which is the extension of Full Lambek calculus with exchange and weakening. In order to make the paper as self-contained as possible, we begin with $\mathbf {ML}$ and concentrate on its most notable extensions.

Definition 2.1 [Reference Gottwal, García-Cerdaña and Bou23]

$\mathbf {ML}$ is the logic given by the Hilbert-style calculus with $\mathbf {MP}$ as its only inference rule and the following axioms:

  1. (1) $(\varphi \Rightarrow \phi )\Rightarrow ((\phi \Rightarrow \psi )\Rightarrow (\varphi \Rightarrow \psi ))$ ,

  2. (2) $(\varphi \& \phi )\Rightarrow \varphi $ ,

  3. (3) $(\varphi \& \phi )\Rightarrow (\phi \& \varphi )$ ,

  4. (4) $(\varphi \Rightarrow (\phi \Rightarrow \psi ))\Rightarrow (\varphi \& \phi \Rightarrow \psi )$ ,

  5. (5) $(\varphi \& \phi \Rightarrow \psi )\Rightarrow (\varphi \Rightarrow (\phi \Rightarrow \psi ))$ ,

  6. (6) $\varphi \sqcap \phi \Rightarrow \varphi $ ,

  7. (7) $\varphi \sqcap \phi \Rightarrow \phi \& \varphi $ ,

  8. (8) $\bar{0}\Rightarrow \varphi $ ,

  9. (9) $\varphi \Rightarrow \varphi \sqcup \phi $ ,

  10. (10) $\phi \Rightarrow \varphi \sqcup \phi $ ,

  11. (11) $(\varphi \Rightarrow \psi )\Rightarrow ((\phi \Rightarrow \psi )\Rightarrow (\varphi \sqcup \phi \Rightarrow \psi ))$ ,

  12. (12) $(\varphi \Rightarrow \phi )\Rightarrow ((\varphi \Rightarrow \psi )\Rightarrow (\varphi \Rightarrow \phi \sqcap \psi ))$ .

The usual connectives in $\mathbf {ML}$ can be derived from $ \& ,\Rightarrow ,\sqcap $ are as follows:

$$ \begin{align*} \overline{1}:=\varphi\Rightarrow\varphi, {\sim} \varphi:=\varphi\Rightarrow \overline{0}, \end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*} \varphi\equiv \phi:=(\varphi\Rightarrow \phi) \& (\phi\Rightarrow \varphi). \end{align*} $$

Outstanding logics up in the hierarchy of extensions of $\mathbf {ML}$ are presented.

Monoidal t-norm based logic $\mathbf {MTL}$ is $\mathbf {ML}$ plus the axiom of pre-linearity:

$$ \begin{align*} \mathbf{(PRE)}~~~(\varphi\Rightarrow\phi)\sqcup (\phi\Rightarrow\varphi). \end{align*} $$

Divisible monoidal logic $\mathbf {ML_\ell }$ is $\mathbf {ML}$ plus the axiom of divisibility:

$$ \begin{align*} \mathbf{(DIV)}~~~\varphi\sqcap \phi\Rightarrow\varphi \& (\varphi\Rightarrow \phi). \end{align*} $$

Involutive monoidal logic $\mathbf {IML}$ is $\mathbf {ML}$ plus the axiom of involution:

$$ \begin{align*} \mathbf{(INV)}~~~{\sim}{\sim}\varphi\Rightarrow\varphi. \end{align*} $$

Intuitionistic logic $\mathbf {IL}$ is $\mathbf {ML}$ plus the axiom of idempotence:

$$ \begin{align*} \mathbf{(IDE)}~~~\varphi\Rightarrow\varphi \& \varphi. \end{align*} $$

Basic fuzzy logic $\mathbf {BL}$ is $\mathbf {MTL}$ plus the axiom $\mathbf {(DIV)}$ .

Gödel logic $\mathbf {G}$ is $\mathbf {MTL}$ plus the axiom $\mathbf {(IDE)}$ .Footnote 1

Łukasiewicz logic is $\mathbf {MTL}$ plus the following axiom:Footnote 2

$$ \begin{align*} \mathbf{(MV)}~~~(\varphi\Rightarrow\phi)\Rightarrow\phi\Rightarrow(\phi\Rightarrow\varphi)\Rightarrow\varphi. \end{align*} $$

Involutive monoidal t-norm based logic $\mathbf {IMTL}$ is $\mathbf {MTL}$ plus the axiom $\mathbf {(INV)}$ .

Nilpotent minimum logic $\mathbf {NM}$ is $\mathbf {IMTL}$ plus the axiom $\mathbf {(WNM)}$ :Footnote 3

$$ \begin{align*} \mathbf{(WNM)}~~~{\sim}(\varphi \& \phi)\sqcup ((\varphi\sqcap \phi)\Rightarrow (\varphi \& \phi)). \end{align*} $$

Classical logic $\mathbf {CL}$ is $\mathbf {MTL}$ plus the axiom:

$$ \begin{align*} \mathbf{(EM)}~~~\varphi\sqcup \sim \varphi. \end{align*} $$

As the author pointed out in [Reference Noguera37], $\mathbf {ML}$ is an implicative logic in the sense of Blok and Pigozzi [Reference Blok and Pigozzi1], and so it is an algebraic logic whose equivalent algebraic semantics Alg $^*\mathbf {ML}$ is the variety of residuated lattices that we usually denote by $\mathbb {RL}$ .Footnote 4

Definition 2.2 [Reference Ward and Dilworth55]

An algebraic structure $(L,\wedge ,\vee ,\odot ,\rightarrow ,0,1)$ of type $(2,2,2,2,0,0)$ is called a residuated lattice if it satisfies the following conditions:

  1. (1) $(L,\wedge ,\vee ,0,1)$ is a bounded lattice.

  2. (2) $(L,\odot ,1)$ is a commutative monoid.

  3. (3) if and only if ,

for any $x,y,z\in L$ .

In what follows, by L we denote the universe of a residuated lattice $(L,\wedge ,\vee ,\odot ,{\rightarrow,}0,1)$ . In any residuated lattice L, we define

$$ \begin{align*} \neg x=x\rightarrow 0, x\oplus y=\neg(\neg x\odot \neg y), \end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*} \neg\neg x=\neg(\neg x), x^0=1 \text{ and } x^n=x^{n-1}\odot x \text{ for } n\geq 1. \end{align*} $$

As a result of the general theory of algebraizability, every axiomatic extension of $\mathbf {ML}$ is algebraizable and its equivalent algebraic semantics is a subvariety of $\mathbb {RL}$ . Namely, if $\mathbf {C}$ is an axiomatic extension of $\mathbf {ML}$ , then the equivalent algebraic semantics Alg $^*\mathbf {C}$ is the subvariety of $\mathbb {RL}$ determined by the equations of the form $\varphi \approx 1$ , where $\varphi $ ranges over the axiom schemata of $\mathbf {C}$ [Reference Metcalfe and Montagna35]. As a consequence of the general theory of algebraizability and Figure 1, Figure 2 is naturally obtained.

Figure 1 Relationships between t-norm based residuated fuzzy logics.

Figure 2 Relationships between algebras of t-norm based residuated fuzzy logic.

In particular:

  • The equivalent algebraic semantics for $\mathbf {ML_\ell }$ is the variety $\mathbb {RL_\ell }$ of residuated $\ell $ -monoids, those residuated lattices satisfying (DIV) $x\wedge y=x\odot (x\rightarrow y)$ .

  • The equivalent algebraic semantics for $\mathbf {IML}$ is the variety $\mathbb {IRL}$ of involutive residuated lattices, those residuated lattices satisfying (INV) $\neg \neg x=x$ .

  • The equivalent algebraic semantics for $\mathbf {MTL}$ is the variety $\mathbb {MTL}$ of MTL-algebras, those residuated lattices satisfying (PRL) $(x\rightarrow y)\vee (y\rightarrow x)=1$ .

  • The equivalent algebraic semantics for $\mathbf {IL}$ is the variety $\mathbb {HA}$ of Heyting algebras, those residuated lattices satisfying (IDE) $x\odot x=x$ .

  • The equivalent algebraic semantics for $\mathbf {IMTL}$ is the variety $\mathbb {IMTL}$ of IMTL-algebras, those MTL-algebras satisfying the algebraic equation (INV).

  • The equivalent algebraic semantics for $\mathbf {BL}$ is the variety $\mathbb {BL}$ of BL-algebras, those MTL-algebras satisfying the algebraic equation (PRL).

  • The equivalent algebraic semantics for is the variety $\mathbb {MV}$ of MV-algebras, those BL-algebras satisfying the algebraic equation (INV).

  • The equivalent algebraic semantics for $\mathbf {G}$ is the variety $\mathbb {GA}$ of Gödel algebras, those MTL-algebras satisfying the algebraic equation (IDE).

  • The equivalent algebraic semantics for $\mathbf {NM}$ is the variety $\mathbb {NM}$ of NM-algebras, those IMTL-algebras satisfying the algebraic equation (WNM) $\neg (x\odot y)\vee ((x\wedge y)\rightarrow (x\odot y))=1$ .

  • The equivalent algebraic semantics for $\mathbf {CL}$ is the variety $\mathbb {BA}$ of Boolean algebras, those MTL-algebras satisfying the algebraic equation (EM) $x\vee \neg x=1$ .

Here we review some notions about monadic fuzzy predicate logic $\mathbf {mMTL\forall }$ [Reference Hájek30].

Definition 2.3 [Reference Esteva and Godo16]

$\mathbf {MTL\forall }$ is a fuzzy predicate logic and has the following axioms:

(P) the axioms resulting from the axioms of $\mathbf {MTL}$ by the substitution of the propositional variables by the $\mathbf {\Gamma }$ -formulas:Footnote 5

  • $(\forall 1)$ $(\forall x)\varphi (x)\Rightarrow \varphi (t)$ , where t is substitutable for x in $\varphi $ ,

  • $(\exists 1)$ $\varphi (t)\Rightarrow (\exists x)\varphi (x)$ , where t is substitutable for x in $\varphi $ ,

  • $(\forall 2)$ $(\forall x)(\phi \Rightarrow \varphi )\Rightarrow (\phi \Rightarrow \forall (x)\varphi )$ , where x is not free in $\phi $ ,

  • $(\exists 2)$ $(\forall x)(\varphi \Rightarrow \phi )\Rightarrow ((\exists x)\varphi \Rightarrow \phi )$ , where x is not free in $\phi $ ,

  • $(\forall 3)$ $(\forall x)(\phi \sqcup \varphi )\Rightarrow \phi \sqcup \forall (x)\varphi )$ , where x is not free in $\phi $ .

The deduction rules are those of $\mathbf {MTL}$ and generalization: from $\varphi $ infer $(\forall x)\varphi $ .

Definition 2.4 [Reference Hájek28]

Monadic fuzzy predicate logic $\mathbf {mMTL\forall }$ is the monadic fragment of fuzzy predicate logic $\mathbf {MTL\forall }$ , consisting of the formulas with unary predicates and just one object variable.

3 Monadic algebras of t-norm based residuated fuzzy logic

In this section, we survey the present state of knowledge on monadic algebras of t-norm based residuated fuzzy logic, and show that the relationships between these monadic algebras completely inherit those between corresponding algebras. Considering the algebras of t-norm based residuated fuzzy logic are all particular case of residuated lattices, we review monadic residuated lattices in advance.

Definition 3.1 [Reference Rach ů nek and Šalounová43]

An algebraic structure $(L,\wedge ,\vee ,\odot ,\rightarrow ,\forall ,\exists ,0,1)$ is said to be a monadic residuated lattice if $(L,\wedge ,\vee ,\odot ,\rightarrow ,0,1)$ is a residuated lattice such that $\forall $ and $\exists $ satisfy the following identities:

  • $(\forall 1)$ $\forall x\rightarrow x=1$ ,

  • $(\exists 1)$ $x\rightarrow \exists x=1$ ,

  • $(\forall 2)$ $\forall (x\rightarrow \exists y)=\exists x\rightarrow \exists y$ ,

  • $(\forall 3)$ $\forall (\exists x\rightarrow y)=\exists x\rightarrow \forall y$ ,

  • $(\forall 4)$ $\forall (x\vee \exists y)=\forall x\vee \exists y$ ,

  • $(\forall 5)$ $\forall \forall x=x$ ,

  • $(\exists 2)$ $\exists \forall x=\forall x$ ,

  • $(\exists 3)$ $\exists (\exists x\odot \exists y)=\exists x\odot \exists y$ ,

  • $(\exists 4)$ $\exists (x\odot x)=\exists x\odot \exists x$ ,

for any $x,y\in L$ .

A monadic residuated lattice $(L,\wedge ,\vee ,\odot ,\rightarrow ,\forall ,\exists ,0,1)$ will be denoted simply by $(L,\forall ,\exists )$ . The class of monadic residuated lattices will be denoted by $\mathbb {MRL}$ . Clearly, in light of the above axiomatization, $\mathbb {MRL}$ forms a variety.

Remark 3.2 [Reference Wang, She, He and Ma51]

$(\exists 1)$ , $(\forall 5)$ , and $(\exists 3)$ are redundant in Definition 3.1.

Zahiri and Borumand Saeid introduced the variety $\mathbb {MMTL}$ of monadic MTL-algebras and gave some important representations of monadic MTL-algebras in [Reference Zahiri and Borumand Saeid57].

Definition 3.3 [Reference Zahiri and Borumand Saeid57]

An algebraic structure $(L,\wedge ,\vee ,\odot ,\rightarrow ,\forall ,\exists ,0,1)$ is said to be a monadic MTL-algebra if $(L,\wedge ,\vee ,\odot ,\rightarrow ,0,1)$ is an MTL-algebra such that $\forall $ and $\exists $ satisfy the following identities: $(\forall 1)$ , $(\exists 4)$ , and

$$ \begin{align*} (\forall6) \ \forall(x\rightarrow\forall y)&=\exists x\rightarrow\forall y,\\ (\forall7) \ \forall(\forall x\rightarrow y)&=\forall x\rightarrow\forall y,\\ (\forall8) \ \forall(\exists x\vee y)&=\exists x\vee\forall y. \end{align*} $$

The variety of monadic MTL-algebras is denoted by $\mathbb {MMTL}$ .

The notion of monadic residuated lattices is a natural generalization of that with respect to monadic MTL-algebras.

Theorem 3.4. Let L be an MTL-algebra and $\forall :L\rightarrow L$ and $\exists :L\rightarrow L$ be two unary operations on L. Then the sets

$$ \begin{align*} \text{G} = \{(\forall1), (\forall2), (\forall3), (\forall4), (\exists2), (\exists4)\}, \end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*} \text{W} = \{(\forall1), (\forall6), (\forall7), (\forall8), (\exists4)\} \end{align*} $$

are equivalent.

Proof. G $\Rightarrow $ W:

$(\forall 6)$ By $(\exists 2)$ and $(\forall 3)$ , we have

$$ \begin{align*} \forall(\forall x\rightarrow y)=\forall(\exists\forall x\rightarrow y)=\exists\forall x\rightarrow\forall y=\forall x\rightarrow\forall y. \end{align*} $$

$(\forall 7)$ By $(\exists 2)$ and $(\forall 2)$ , we have

$$ \begin{align*} \forall(x\rightarrow \forall y)=\forall(x\rightarrow \exists\forall y)=\exists x\rightarrow \exists\forall y=\exists x\rightarrow \exists y. \end{align*} $$

$(\forall 8)$ By $(\forall 4)$ and $(\exists 2)$ , we have

$$ \begin{align*} \forall(x\vee \forall y)=\forall(x\vee\exists\forall y)=\forall x\vee \exists\forall y=\forall x\vee \forall y, \end{align*} $$

and by the arbitrariness of $x,y$ , we also get

$$ \begin{align*} \forall(\forall x\vee y)=\forall(y\vee \forall x)=\forall y\vee \forall x=\forall x\vee \forall y. \end{align*} $$

Also, by $(\forall 4)$ and $(\exists 2)$ , we have

$$ \begin{align*} \forall(\exists x\vee y)=\forall(\forall\exists x\vee y)=\forall\exists x\vee \forall y=\exists x\vee \forall y. \end{align*} $$

W $\Rightarrow $ G:

The proofs of $(\forall 2), (\forall 3), (\forall 4)$ , and $(\exists 2)$ can be directly obtained from Lemma 3.1 (5), (15), (18), and (6), respectively, in [Reference Zahiri and Borumand Saeid57].

Theorem 3.4 actually gives us an idea of introducing the notion of monadic MTL-algebra in a different way, which implies the following result immediately.

Theorem 3.5. The subvariety of $\mathbb {MRL}$ determined by the equation

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{(PRL)}~~(x\rightarrow y)\vee (y\rightarrow x)=1 \end{align*} $$

is term-equivalent to the variety $\mathbb {MMTL}$ .

Several academics introduced three kinds of monadic BL-algebras and tried to provide a right algebraic semantics for Hájek’s monadic fuzzy logic $\mathbf {mBL\forall }$ [Reference Castaño, Cimadamore, Verela and Rueda4, Reference Drŭgulici13, Reference Grigolia25]. Here we will review Draŭgulici’s, Grigolia’s and Castaño’s axioms of monadic BL-algebras and discuss the relationship among them.

Definition 3.6 ((Draŭgulici’s axioms) [Reference Drŭgulici13])

A monadic BL-algebra is a triple $(L,\forall ,\exists )$ , where L is a BL-algebra, $\forall :L\rightarrow L$ and $\exists :L\rightarrow L$ are two unary operations on L satisfying the identities: $(\forall 1)$ , $(\exists 1)$ , $(\forall 4)$ , $(\forall 6)$ , $(\forall 7)$ and

$$ \begin{align*} (\forall9)\ \forall(\forall x\odot \forall y)=\forall x\odot \forall y, \end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*} (\forall10)\ \forall 1=1. \end{align*} $$

Remark 3.7. (1) $(\forall 9)$ , $(\exists 1)$ and $(\forall 10)$ are redundant in Draŭgulici’s axioms.

(2) The other one was introduced by Grigolia [Reference Grigolia25] as a triple $(L,\forall ,\exists )$ that satisfies the identities: $(\forall 1)$ , $(\exists 1)$ , $(\forall 2)$ , $(\forall 3)$ and $(\forall 4)$ . It is also easily verified that

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{Grigolia's\ axioms } = \mathrm{ Dr}\breve{\rm a}\mathrm{gulici's\ axioms } + \mathrm{(E2)}. \end{align*} $$

It is worth noticing in [Reference Hájek26] that the formula

$$ \begin{align*} (\exists x)(\alpha(x) \& \beta(x)))\equiv (\exists x)\alpha(x) \& (\exists x)\beta(x) \end{align*} $$

is a theorem in $\mathbf {BL\forall }$ , and also belongs to $\mathbf {mBL\forall }$ . However Example 3.8 shows that the last formula is independent of the axioms of Definition 3.6 and Remark 3.7(2).

Example 3.8. Let $L=[0,1]$ . Define binary operations $\wedge ,\vee ,\odot ,\rightarrow $ by

$$ \begin{align*} x\wedge y=\min\{x,y\},~~x\vee y=\max\{x,y\},~~\neg x=1-x, \end{align*} $$

Then $(L,\wedge ,\vee ,\rightarrow ,\odot ,0,1)$ is a BL-algebra, and is called the standard MV-algebra. If we define two unary operations $\forall :L\rightarrow L$ and $\exists :L\rightarrow L$ by

$$ \begin{align*} \forall x= \begin{cases} 1, & x=1, \\ 0, & x\neq1, \end{cases}{\qquad} \exists x= \begin{cases} 0, & x=0, \\ 1, & x\neq0, \end{cases} \end{align*} $$

then $\forall $ and $\exists $ satisfy the axioms of Definition 3.6 and Remark 3.7(2). However, the unary operation $\exists $ does not satisfy the above formula, since

$$ \begin{align*} \exists (\frac{1}{2}\odot \frac{1}{2})=\exists 0=0\neq 1=\exists \frac{1}{2}\odot \exists \frac{1}{2}. \end{align*} $$

In order to solve the above drawback, Castaño et al. revised the variety $\mathbb {MBL}$ of monadic BL-algebras and proved that are the equivalent algebraic semantics of the monadic fuzzy logic $\mathbf {mBL{\forall }}$ [Reference Castaño, Cimadamore, Verela and Rueda4].

Definition 3.9 [Reference Castaño, Cimadamore, Verela and Rueda4]

A monadic BL-algebra is a triple $(L,\forall ,\exists )$ , where L is a BL-algebra, $\forall :L\rightarrow L$ and $\exists :L\rightarrow L$ are two unary operations on L that satisfy $(\forall 1), (\forall 6), (\forall 7), (\forall 8)$ and $(\exists 4)$ .

Theorem 3.10. The subvariety of $\mathbb {MMTL}$ determined by the equation

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{(DIV)}~~x\wedge y=x\odot(x\rightarrow y) \end{align*} $$

is term-equivalent to the variety $\mathbb {MBL}$ .

Proof. Definitions 3.3 and 3.9 show that monadic BL-algebra and monadic MTL-algebra have the same axioms with respect to two quantifiers $\forall $ and $\exists $ .

Subsequently, in order to review the variety of monadic algebras of involutive monoidal t-norm based logic and their subvarieties, we study the variety $\mathbb {MIRL}$ of monadic involutive residuated lattices in advance.

Definition 3.11. A monadic involutive residuated lattice is a pair $(L,\forall )$ , where L is an involutive residuated lattice and $\forall :L\rightarrow L$ is an unary operation on L satisfying the following conditions: $(\forall 1),(\forall 7)$ and

$$ \begin{align*} (\forall11)~~\forall(x\vee \forall y)=\forall x\vee \forall y, \end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*} (\forall12)~~\forall(x\rightarrow\neg x)=\forall x\rightarrow\neg\forall x. \end{align*} $$

Theorem 3.12. The subvariety of $\mathbb {MRL}$ determined by the equation

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{(INV)}~~\neg\neg x=x \end{align*} $$

is term-equivalent to the variety $\mathbb {MIRL}$ , where $\exists =\neg \forall \neg $ .

Proof. Let $(L,\forall ,\exists )$ be a monadic residuated lattice that satisfies $\neg \neg x=x$ . Then L becomes an involutive residuated lattice. Here we will show that $(L,\forall )$ is a monadic involutive residuated lattice.

  • $(\forall 7)$ : The proof is similar to that of G $\Rightarrow $ W of Theorem 3.4.

  • $(\forall 11)$ : By $(\exists 2)$ and $(\forall 4)$ , we have

    $$ \begin{align*} \forall(\forall x\vee y)=\forall(\exists\forall x\vee y)=\exists\forall x\vee \forall y=\forall x\vee \forall y. \end{align*} $$
  • $(\forall 12)$ : By $(\exists 4)$ and $\neg \exists \neg x=\forall x$ , we have

    $$ \begin{align*} \forall(\neg x\rightarrow x)=\neg\exists\neg(\neg x\rightarrow x)\kern1.3pt{=}\kern1.3pt\neg\exists(\neg x\odot \neg x)\kern1.3pt{=}\kern1.3pt\neg(\exists \neg x\odot \exists\neg x)\kern1.3pt{=}\kern1.3pt\neg\forall x\kern1.3pt{\rightarrow}\kern1.3pt\forall x. \end{align*} $$
  • Conversely, let $(L,\forall )$ be a monadic involutive residuated lattice. Here we show that $(L,\forall ,\exists )$ is a monadic residuated lattice, where

    $$ \begin{align*} \exists x:=\neg\forall \neg x \end{align*} $$
    for any $x\in L$ . Actually, we only need to show that $(L,\forall ,\exists )$ satisfies the axioms of W by Theorem 3.4, which is indeed equivalent to the axioms of monadic residuated lattice defined in Definition 3.1.

    $(\forall 6)$ : By Propositions 3.9(5), we have

    $$ \begin{align*} \forall(x\rightarrow\forall y)=\forall(\neg\neg x\rightarrow \forall y)=\neg\forall \neg x\rightarrow\forall y=\exists x\rightarrow\forall y. \end{align*} $$
  • $(\forall 7)$ : By Propositions 3.9(5), we have

    $$ \begin{align*} \forall(\forall x\rightarrow y)=\forall(\exists\forall x\rightarrow y)=\exists\forall x\rightarrow \forall y=\forall x\rightarrow\forall y. \end{align*} $$
  • $(\forall 8)$ : By (M11) and Proposition 3.7(6), we have

    $$ \begin{align*} \forall(\exists x\vee y)=\forall(\forall\exists x\vee y)=\forall\exists x\vee \forall y=\exists x\vee\forall y. \end{align*} $$
  • $(\exists 4)$ Applying $(\forall 12)$ and $\neg \forall \neg x=\exists x$ , we have

    Therefore, $(L,\forall ,\exists )$ is a monadic residuated lattice.

Inspired by Theorem 3.12, we have the corresponding result of monadic IMTL-algebras and monadic MTL-algebras.

Theorem 3.13. The subvariety of $\mathbb {MMTL}$ determined by the equation

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{(INV)}~~\neg\neg x=x \end{align*} $$

is term-equivalent to the variety $\mathbb {MIMTL}$ , where $\exists =\neg \forall \neg $ .

Inspired by the above observation, we introduced the notion of monadic NM-algebras and proved that is the equivalent algebraic semantics of $\mathbf {mNM\forall }$ in [Reference Wang, He, Yang, Wang and He49].

Definition 3.14 [Reference Wang, He, Yang, Wang and He49]

A monadic NM-algebra is a pair $(L,\forall )$ , where L is an NM-algebra and $\forall :L\rightarrow L$ is an unary operation on L satisfying the following conditions: $(\forall 1),(\forall 7)$ , $(\forall 11)$ and $(\forall 12)$ .

Theorem 3.15. The subvariety of $\mathbb {MIMTL}$ determined by the equation

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{(WNM)}~~(x\odot y\rightarrow 0)\vee(x\wedge y\rightarrow x\odot y)=1 \end{align*} $$

is term-equivalent to the variety $\mathbb {MNM}$ .

Proof. The proof is trivial and hence we omit them.

The variety $\mathbb {MMV}$ of monadic MV-algebras were introduced by Rutledge [Reference Rutledge45] as an algebra $(L,\oplus ,\odot ,^\ast ,\forall ,0,1)$ satisfies the following identities: $(\forall 1)$ , $(\forall 9)$

$$ \begin{align*} (\forall 13)~~\forall(x\wedge y)=\forall x\wedge \forall y, \end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*} (\forall14)~~\forall\neg\forall x=\neg\forall x, \end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*} (\forall15)~~\forall(x\odot x)=\forall x\odot \forall x, \end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*} (\forall16)~~\forall(x\oplus x)=\forall x\oplus\forall x. \end{align*} $$

Remark 3.16. J. Rach ů nek and F. Švrček were first attempt to define unary operators with some properties of quantifiers for residuated $\ell $ -monoids using only the universal quantifier as the initial one, the resulting class of algebras called monadic residuated $\ell $ -monoids [Reference Rach ů nek and Švrček44]. The variety of monadic residuated $\ell $ -monoids is denoted by $\mathbb {MRL\ell }$ , which is analogously as for the variety $\mathbb {MMV}$ of monadic MV-algebras. But it seems to be more appropriate to introduce such monadic algebras similarly as the monadic residuated lattices, MTL-algebras and BL-algebras. The reason is that MV-algebras satisfy De Morgan and double negation laws, and thus in the definition of the corresponding monadic algebras, it is possible to use only one of the existential and universal quantifiers as primitive, the other being definable as the dual of the one defined, readers can refer to Proposition 4 in [Reference Rach ů nek and Šalounová42] for details. Namely, if $\exists $ is an existential quantifier and $\forall $ is a universal one on an MV-algebra L, then $\forall _\exists :L\rightarrow L$ and $\exists _\forall :L\rightarrow L$ such that for any $x\in L$ ,

$$ \begin{align*} \forall_\exists x=\neg(\exists\neg x) ~~\text{and}~~ \exists_\forall x=\neg(\forall\neg x), \end{align*} $$

is a universal and an existential quantifier on L, respectively, and moreover

$$ \begin{align*} \exists_{(\forall_\exists)}=\exists~~\text{and}~~\forall_{(\exists_\forall)}=\forall. \end{align*} $$

However, definitions of monadic BL-algebras, residuated lattices and residuated $\ell $ -monoids require the introduction of both kinds of quantifiers simultaneously, because these quantifiers are not mutually interdefinable. As a consequence of Theorems 3.4 and 3.10, monadic BL-algebra, MTL-algebra, residuated $\ell $ -monoid and residuated lattice have the same axioms, that is, a monadic residuated $\ell $ -monoid is indeed a triple $(L,\forall ,\exists )$ satisfying the identities: $(\forall 1),(\forall 6),(\forall 7),(\forall 8)$ and $(\exists 4)$ .

Figallo Orellano also gave a characterization of monadic MV-algebras in [Reference Figallo Orellano19].

Theorem 3.17 [Reference Figallo Orellano19]

Let L be an MV-algebra and $\forall $ a unary operation on L. Then $(L,\forall )$ is a monadic MV-algebra if and only if it satisfies $(\forall 1),(\forall 7),(\forall 12)$ .

Theorem 3.18. The subvariety of $\mathbb {MMTL}$ determined by the equation

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{(MV)}~~(x\rightarrow y)\rightarrow y=y\rightarrow (y\rightarrow x) \end{align*} $$

is term-equivalent to the variety $\mathbb {MMV}$ .

Proof. Let $(L,\forall ,\exists )$ be a monadic MTL-algebra satisfying the condition (MV). Then L becomes an MV-algebra, and by Definition 3.14 and Theorem 3.17, $(L,\forall )$ is a monadic MV-algebra.

Conversely, let $(L,\forall )$ be a monadic MV-algebra. Here we show that $(L,\forall ,\exists )$ is a monadic MTL-algebra, where

$$ \begin{align*} \exists x:=\neg\forall \neg x \end{align*} $$

for any $x\in L$ . It is noted first that $(\forall 11)$ hold. Indeed, for any $x,y\in L$ , we have

which implies . The reverse inequality holds trivially.

The rest of proof can be deduced directly form Theorem 3.13.

As a consequence of Theorem 3.18, the following results are obtained.

Corollary 3.19. The subvariety of $\mathbb {MIMTL}$ determined by the equation

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{(DIV)}~~x\wedge y=x\odot(x\rightarrow y) \end{align*} $$

is term-equivalent to the variety $\mathbb {MMV}$ .

Corollary 3.20. The subvariety of $\mathbb {MBL}$ determined by the equation

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{(INV)}~~\neg\neg x=x \end{align*} $$

is term-equivalent to the variety $\mathbb {MMV}$ .

Monadic Boolean algebras were introduced by Halmos [Reference Halmos32], as algebraic models for classical predicate logics for languages having one placed predicates and a single quantifier. More precisely, an algebra $(L,\wedge ,\vee ,\neg ,0,1,\exists )$ is said to be a monadic Boolean algebra if $(L,\wedge ,\vee ,\neg ,0,1)$ is a Boolean algebra and in addition $\exists $ satisfies the identities: $(\exists 1)$ ,

$$ \begin{align*} (\exists 5)~~ \exists 0=0, \end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*} (\exists 6)~~ \exists(\exists x\wedge y)=\exists x\wedge \exists y. \end{align*} $$

The variety of monadic Boolean algebras is denoted by $\mathbb {MBA}$ .

Theorem 3.21. The subvariety of $\mathbb {MRL}$ determined by adding the equation

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{(EM)}~~\neg x\vee x=1 \end{align*} $$

is term-equivalent to the variety $\mathbb {MBA}$ .

Figure 3 Relationships between monadic algebras of t-norm based residuated fuzzy logic.

Proof. Let $(L,\forall ,\exists )$ be a monadic residuated lattice satisfying the condition (EM). Then L becomes a Boolean algebra.

  • $(\exists 5)$ The proof is similar to that of Proposition 3.1(9) in [Reference Rach ů nek and Šalounová43].

  • $(\exists 6)$ Applying $(\forall 11)$ , for any $x,y\in L$ , we have

    and by the arbitrariness of $x,y$ , we also get $\exists (\exists x\wedge y)=\exists x\wedge \exists y$ .

Remark 3.22. Figures 2 and 3 show that the relationships between monadic algebras of t-norm based residuated fuzzy logic completely inherit those between corresponding algebras of t-norm based residuated fuzzy logic, which solve the drawback in the paragraph 2 in the Introduction.

4 Completeness for monadic fuzzy predicate logic $\mathbf {mMTL\forall }$

In this section, the main aim of us to show that the variety of monadic MTL-algebras is the equivalent algebraic semantics of monadic fuzzy predicate logic $\mathbf {mMTL\forall }$ , and give an algebraic proof of completeness for this logic.

Along with the same line of Hájek’s excellent work in [Reference Hájek30], similarly, we can prove that formulas of $\mathbf {S5(MTL)}$ are in the obvious one–one isomorphic correspondence with formulas of monadic fuzzy predicate calculus $\mathbf {mMTL\forall }$ with unary predicates and just one object variable x, the atomic formula $P_i(x)$ corresponding to propositional variable $p_i$ and modalities $\square $ and correspond to the quantifiers $(\forall x)$ and $(\exists x)$ . Kripke semantics correspond in the obvious way to semantics for $\mathbf {mMTL\forall }$ , the correspondence maps tautologies of the fuzzy modal logic to tautologies of the monadic fuzzy predicate logic and the same for standard tautologies. Using the above equivalence, we continue the algebraic tradition of naming monadic the algebraic semantics of monadic fragments of several logics (Boolean, intuitionistic, Łukasiewicz, etc.), and opt to call the algebras corresponding to the fuzzy modal logic $\mathbf {S5(MTL)}$ monadic MTL-algebras. However, in this section we will work in the language of the fuzzy modal logic $\mathbf {S5(MTL)}$ instead of in the monadic fuzzy language of $\mathbf {mMTL{\forall }}$ and prove that the variety of monadic MTL-algebras is the equivalent algebraic semantics of the logic $\mathbf {S5(MTL)}$ in advance.

Here we first study m-relatively complete subalgebras with respect to monadic MTL-algebras. In particular, we characterize those subalgebras of a given MTL-algebra that may be the range of the quantifiers $\forall $ and $\exists $ . As a consequence of this characterization, we build the most important examples of monadic MTL-algebras, which will be called functional monadic MTL-algebras.

Given an MTL-algebra L, we say that a subalgebra is m-relatively complete if the following conditions hold:

(S1) For every $a\in L$ , the subset has a greatest element and $\{s\in S\mid s\geq a\}$ has a least element.

(S2) For every $a\in L$ and $s_1,s_2\in S$ such that , there exists $s_3\in S$ such that and .

(S3) For every $a\in L$ and $s_1\in S$ such that , there exists $s_2\in S$ such that and .

Theorem 4.1. Consider an MTL-algebra L and an m-relatively complete subalgebra S. If we define on L the operation

then $(L,\forall ,\exists )$ is a monadic MTL-algebra such that $\forall L=\exists L=S$ . Conversely, if $(L,\forall ,\exists )$ is a monadic MTL-algebra, then $\forall L=\exists L$ is an m-relatively complete subalgebra of L.

Proof. Clearly condition (S1) guarantees the existence of $\forall x$ and $\exists x$ for any $x\in L$ . Then it remains to show that $(L,\forall ,\exists )$ satisfies axioms $(\forall 1),(\forall 6)$ $(\forall 8)$ and $(\exists 4)$ .

$(\forall 1)$ From the definition of $\forall x$ , it is clear that . Thus $\forall x\rightarrow x=1$ .

$(\forall 6)$ From , we get . Then . Let us see that . Indeed, if $s\in S$ , and , then . Then, by definition of $\exists x$ , we have . Thus , which implies that $\forall (x\rightarrow \forall y)=\exists x\rightarrow \forall y$ .

$(\forall 7)$ From , we get , In addition, if $s\in S$ and , then . Thus and . Hence we have shown that $\forall (\forall x\rightarrow y)=\forall x\rightarrow \forall y$ .

$(\forall 8)$ Since . Now, if $s\in S$ and , by condition (S2), there must be $s'\in S$ such that and . Then and . Thus, we have shown that $\forall (\exists x\vee y)=\exists x\vee \forall y$ .

$(\exists 4)$ Clearly, . In addition, if $s\in S$ and , by condition (S3), there is $s'\in S$ such that and . Then and . Thus $\exists (x\odot x)=\exists x\odot \exists x$ .

Conversely, let $(L,\forall ,\exists )$ be a monadic MTL-algebra. Then we have that $\forall L$ is a subalgebra of L. Now, let us show that conditions (S1)–(S3) hold.

(S1) Using the basic properties of monadic MTL-algebra, we have that if for some $s\in \forall L$ , then . Thus . Analogously $\exists x=\min \{s\in \forall L|s\geq x\}$ .

(S2) Assume for some $s_1,s_2\in \forall L$ , $x\in L$ . Then, using the basic properties of monadic MTL-algebras, we have and .

(S3) If for some $s\in \forall L$ and $x\in L$ , then and , $\exists x\in \forall L$ . This shows that $\forall L$ is an m-relatively complete subalgebra of L.

The following is the most important example of monadic MTL-algebras built according to the previous theorem.

Example 4.2. Considering a linearly ordered MTL-algebra L and a nonempty set X, we restrict our attention to those elements $f\in L^X$ such that

$$ \begin{align*} \inf\{f(x)\mid x\in X\},~~\sup\{f(x)|x\in X\} \end{align*} $$

both exist in L. We denote by M the subset of $L^X$ of these safe elements. For every $f\in M$ , we define

$$ \begin{align*} \forall_f(x)=\inf\{f(y)\mid y\in X\},~~\exists_f(x)=\sup\{f(y)\mid y\in X\}, \text{ for } x\in L \end{align*} $$

and $\forall _f$ and $\exists _f$ are both constant maps.

Remark 4.3. Let G be a subalgebra of $L^X$ contained in M such that for every f, $\forall _f,\exists _f\in G$ . We will prove that G has a natural structure of monadic MTL-algebra. Let S be the subset of constant maps of $L^X$ . Then we prove that $G\cap S$ is an m-relatively complete subalgebra of G. Indeed, since G and S are subalgebra of $L^X$ , it is clear that $G\cap S$ is a subalgebra of G.

(S1) If $f\in G$ , then $\forall _f\in G$ , so . Analogously, $\min \{s\in G\cap S|s\geq f\}=\exists _f\in G$ .

(S2) Since $G\cap S$ is totally ordered, we may check condition $(s_2)$ . If $1=s\vee f$ for some $f\in G$ and $s\in G\cap S$ . Putting $s(x)=s_0\in L,x\in X$ . Then $s_0\vee f(x)=1$ for every $x\in X$ . As L is linearly ordered, either $s_0=1$ or $f(x)=1$ for every $x\in X$ .

(S3) If for some $f\in G$ and $c\in G\cap S$ , then for any $x\in X$ . Moreover, for any $x,y\in X$ , since

Hence for a fixed $y\in X$ and any $x\in X$ . Thus , where $\exists _f=\sup \{f(y)|y\in X\}$ . Now, for any $y\in Y$ . Then and , which concludes the proof that $G\cap S$ is an m-relatively complete subalgebra of G.

Then it follows from Theorem 4.1 that $(G,\forall _f,\exists _f)$ is a monadic MTL-algebra. Monadic MTL-algebras of this form are called functional monadic MTL-algebras. Also, if L is $|X|$ -complete, then $S=L^X$ and $(L^X,\forall _f,\exists _f)$ is a functional monadic MTL-algebra.

Here we show that the variety of monadic MTL-algebras is the equivalent algebraic semantics of monadic fuzzy predicate logic $\mathbf {mMTL\forall }$ , which will be used to prove the main result of this section.

Definition 4.4. A Kripke model for $\mathbf {S5(MTL)}$ is a triple $K=(X,e,L)$ where X is a nonempty set of worlds, L is a linearly ordered MTL-algebra and $e:Prop\times X\rightarrow L$ is an evaluation map. The evaluation map extends to any formula:

  • $(e_1)$ $e(0,x)=0$ , $e(1,x)=1$ ,

  • $(e_2)$ $e(\varphi \sqcap \psi ,x)=e(\varphi ,x)\wedge e(\psi ,x)$ ,

  • $(e_3)$ $e(\varphi \sqcup \psi ,x)=e(\varphi ,x)\vee e(\psi ,x)$ ,

  • $(e_4)$ $e(\varphi \& \psi ,x)=e(\varphi ,x)\odot e(\psi ,x)$ ,

  • $(e_5)$ $e(\varphi \Rightarrow \psi ,x)=e(\varphi ,x)\rightarrow e(\psi ,x)$ ,

  • $(e_6)$ $e(\square \varphi ,x)=\inf \{e(\varphi ,y):y\in X\}$ ,

  • $(e_7)$ .

We can also define truth degree $\|\varphi \|_{K,\omega }$ of a formula $\varphi $ in K at the world $\omega $ , which is due done recursively on the structure of $\varphi $ . For propositional variables $p\in Prop$ , we have that $\|p\|_{K,\omega }=e(\omega ,p)$ . The definition of the truth value is then extended for the logical connectives of monoidal t-norm based logic in the usual way, and for the modal connectives by

$$ \begin{align*} \|\square\varphi\|=\inf_{w\in W}\|\varphi\|_{K,w}, \end{align*} $$

the infima and suprema above may not exist in general; hence, we restrict our attention only to safe structures, that is, structure K for which $\|\varphi \|_{K,\omega }$ is defined for every formula $\varphi $ at every world $\omega $ . However, we are only interested in the tautologies of this logic, but here considered albeit implicitly, a global consequence relation $\models _{\mathbf {S5(MTL)}}$ . Given a set of formulas $\Gamma $ we say that a safe structure $K=(X,e,L)$ is a model of $\Gamma $ if for every $\varphi \in \Gamma $ and every $\omega \in W$ we have that $\|\varphi \|_{K,\omega }=1$ . Thus, given a set of formulas $\Gamma $ and a formula $\varphi $ we write $\Gamma \models _{\mathbf {S5(MTL)}}\varphi $ if and only if for every safe model $K=(X,e,L)$ of $\Gamma $ we have that $\|\varphi \|_{K,\omega }=1$ for every $\omega \in W$ .

We already noted that $\mathbf {S5(MTL)}$ is actually equivalent to $\mathbf {mMTL\forall }$ because there is a natural correspondence between formulas of both logics, between corresponding models and between the corresponding truth degrees. Thus, since the latter is finitary (being a fragment of a finitary logic), the consequence relation $\mathbf {S5(MTL)}$ is also finitary.

Theorem 4.5. The fuzzy modal logic $\mathbf {S5(MTL)}$ is strongly complete with respect to its general semantics, that is, the following statements are equivalent for every set of formulas $\Gamma \cup \{\varphi \}$ :

  1. (1) $\Gamma \vdash \varphi $ ,

  2. (2) $K\models \varphi $ for every safe model K of $\Gamma $ .

Proof. The proof is similar to that of Theorem 2 in [Reference Hájek30].

Considering a safe Kripke model $K=(X,e,L)$ , we can turn the map $e:Prop\times X\rightarrow L$ into a map $\overline {e}:Prop\rightarrow L^X$ given by the relation $\overline {e}(p)(x)=e(p,x)$ . Since K is safe, $\overline {e}$ extends to formulas in the following way:

  • $(e_1)$ $\overline {e}(x)=0$ , $\overline {e}(1)=1$ ,

  • $(e_2)$ $\overline {e}(\varphi \sqcap \psi )=\overline {e}(\varphi )\wedge \overline {e}(\psi )$ ,

  • $(e_3)$ $\overline {e}(\varphi \sqcup \psi )=\overline {e}(\varphi )\vee \overline {e}(\psi )$ ,

  • $(e_4)$ $\overline {e}(\varphi \& \psi )=\overline {e}(\varphi )\odot \overline {e}(\psi )$ ,

  • $(e_5)$ $\overline {e}(\varphi \Rightarrow \psi )=\overline {e}(\varphi )\rightarrow \overline {e}(\psi )$ ,

  • $(e_6)$ $\overline {e}(\square \varphi )=\forall _f\overline {e}(\varphi )$ ,

  • $(e_7)$ .

Thus it is clear that $\{\overline {e}(\varphi ):\varphi $ formula $\}\subseteq L^X$ is the universe of a functional monadic MTL-algebra in Example 4.2.

Then we have the following result similar to Theorem 4.5.

Theorem 4.6. The following statements are equivalent for every set of formulas $\Gamma \cup \{\varphi \}$ :

  1. (1) $\Gamma \vdash \varphi $ ,

  2. (2) $\overline {e}(\varphi )=1$ for every $\overline {e}:Prop\rightarrow G$ , where $(G,\forall _f,\exists _f)$ is any functional monadic MTL-algebra and $\overline {e}(\gamma )=1$ for every $\gamma \in \Gamma $ .

Theorem 4.7. The variety $\mathbb {MMTL}$ is the equivalent algebraic semantics for the logic $\mathbf {S5(MTL)}$ .

Proof. It is enough to show that the next two conditions hold for set for formulas $\Gamma \cup \{\varphi ,\phi \}$ :

  1. (1) $\Gamma \vdash \varphi $ if and only if $\{\psi \equiv 1|\psi \in \Gamma \}\vdash _{\mathbb {MMTL}}\varphi \equiv 1$ ,

  2. (2) $\varphi \equiv \phi \models _{\mathbb {MMTL}}(\varphi \Rightarrow \phi )\sqcap (\phi \Rightarrow \varphi )\equiv 1$ .

Condition (2) is trivially verified. We only show the condition (1). For the forward implication, if $\Gamma \vdash \varphi $ , there exists a proof of $\varphi $ from $\Gamma $ and the axioms of $\mathbf {S5(MTL)}$ by successive application of the reference rules $\mathbf {MP}$ and $\mathbf {Nec}$ . Thus, it is enough to show that the equation $\varphi \equiv 1$ is valid in $\mathbb {MMTL}$ for every axiom $\varphi $ of $\mathbf {S5(MTL)}$ and that the inference rules preserve validity. The former statement follows from the basic properties of monadic MTL-algebras. The preservation of $\mathbf {MP}$ and $\mathbf {Nec}$ are also easily verified. For the converse implication, simply observe that, since $(G,\forall _f,\exists _f)$ is a monadic MTL-algebra, condition (2) of Theorem 4.6 holds.

Thus, from the general theory of Algebraic Logic, we get the next result.

Corollary 4.8. There is a one–one correspondence between axiomatic extensions of $\mathbf {S5(MTL})$ and subvarieties of $\mathbb {MMTL}$ .

Zahiri and Borumand Saeid give a Hilbert-style syntactic calculus in the language of $\mathbf {MMTL}$ , which is indeed equivalent to $\mathbf {S5(MTL)}$ whose consequence we denote by $\vdash _{\mathbf {S5(MTL)}}$ . The axioms of this calculus are the instantiations of the axioms schemata $\mathbf {MTL}$ for formulas in the language of $\mathbf {S5(MTL)}$ , plus the following axioms:

  • ,

  • $(\square 2)$ $\square (\nu \Rightarrow \varphi )\Rightarrow (\nu \Rightarrow \square \varphi )$ ,

  • ,

  • $(\square 3)$ $\square (\nu \sqcup \varphi )\Rightarrow (\nu \sqcup \square \varphi )$ ,

  • ,

where $\varphi $ is any formula and $\nu $ is any propositional combination of formulas beginning with $\square $ or . The inference rules are $\mathbf {MP}$ : $\varphi $ , $\varphi \Rightarrow \phi \vdash \phi $ and $\mathbf {Nec}: \varphi /\square \varphi $ .

Here we achieve the main aim of this section, namely, giving an algebraic proof of the completeness theorem for monadic fuzzy predicate logic $\mathbf {mMTL\forall }$ .

Theorem 4.9. The following statements are equivalent for every set of formulas $\Gamma \cup \{\varphi \}$ :

  1. (1) $\mathbf {S5(MTL)}$ is complete, i.e., the following two statements are equivalent:

    1. (i) $\Gamma \vdash _{\mathbf {S5(MTL)}}\varphi $ ,

    2. (ii) $\Gamma \models _{\mathbf {S5(MTL)}}\varphi $ .

  2. (2) The variety $\mathbb {MMTL}$ is generated by the functional monadic MTL-algebras.

Proof. We prove first that (2) implies (1). The soundness and implication is straightforward and does not depend on the hypothesis. Assume $\Gamma \models _{\mathbf {S5(MTL)}}\varphi $ and since $\varphi \models _{\mathbf {S5(MTL)}}$ is finitary, we may also assume that $\Gamma $ is finite. By way of contradiction, suppose $\Gamma \nvdash _{\mathbf {S5(MTL)}}\varphi $ . Then $\Gamma \nvDash _{\mathbf {S5(MTL)}}\varphi $ (this is the consequence relation associated with the variety of $\mathbb {MMTL}$ ), which is equivalent to saying that $\mathbb {MMTL}$ does not satisfy the quasi-equation

$$ \begin{align*} \gamma_1\approx \& \cdots \& \gamma_n\approx 1\Rightarrow \varphi\approx 1, \end{align*} $$

where . By hypothesis, there is a functional algebra $(M,\forall _f,\exists _f)\in \mathbb {MMTL}$ with and L is an MTL-algebra, and a valuation h into $(M,\forall _f,\exists _f)$ such that $h(\Gamma )\subseteq \{1\}$ but $h(\varphi )\neq 1$ . Consider the structure $K=(X,e,L)$ with $e(x,p)=h(p)(x)$ for $x\in X$ and $p\in Prop$ . For every $\gamma \in \Gamma $ and $x\in X$ we have that $\|\gamma \|_K,x=h(\gamma )(x)=1$ , but $\|\gamma \|_K,x=h(\gamma )(x)\neq 1$ for some $x\in X$ , which is a contradiction.

Conversely, we now prove that (1) implies (2). Assume $\mathbb {MMTL}$ is not generated by its functional members. Thus, there is an identity

$$ \begin{align*} \gamma_1\approx 1 \& \cdots \& \gamma_n\approx 1\Rightarrow \varphi\approx 1 \end{align*} $$

that is on every functional monadic MTL-algebra, but is not true on the variety $\mathbb {MTL}$ . From the properties of algebraizable logics, we get that . However, we claim that . Indeed, assume $K=(X,e,L)$ is a model of , where L is a linearly ordered MTL-algebra. Then $\|\gamma _i\|_K,x=h(\gamma _i)(x)=1$ for any $x\in X$ and . Let Fm be the set of propositional formulas in the language of $\mathbf {S5(MTL)}$ . For each $\psi \in Fm$ , we define $f_\psi :X\rightarrow L$ such that $f_\psi (x)=\|\psi \|_K,x$ for every $x\in X$ . Consider $B=\{f_\psi |\psi \in Fm\}$ . Then $B\subseteq L^X$ and, in addition, B is a subuniverse of the MTL-algebra $L^X$ . Moreover, it is straightforward to check that . Then $(L,\forall _f,\exists _f)$ is a functional monadic MTL-algebra. Consider now the interpretation $e':Fm\rightarrow L$ given by $e'(\psi )=f_\psi $ for any $\psi \in Fm$ . Then $e'(\gamma _i)=1$ for . By hypothesis, $e'(\varphi )=1$ , that is, $f_\varphi =1$ , so $\|\varphi \|_K,x=1$ for any $x\in X$ . This completes the proof that .

5 Strong completeness for monadic fuzzy predicate logic $\mathbf {mIMTL\forall }$

In this section, we obtain the completeness theorem of some axiomatic extensions for monadic fuzzy predicate logic $\mathbf {mMTL\forall }$ , and then give a major application, proving the strong completeness theorem for monadic fuzzy predicate logic $\mathbf {mIMTL\forall }$ .

Along with the same line of Section 4, we naturally extend some basic notions, including Kripke model and its related concepts, from the fuzzy modal logic $\mathbf {S5(MTL)}$ to a more general one, $\mathbf {S5(C)}$ which is indeed an S5-modal expansion of an axiomatic extension $\mathbf {C}$ of the logic $\mathbf {MTL}$ , and denote a global consequence relation by $\models _{\mathbf {S5(C)}}$ .

Here we also introduce a Hilbert-style syntactic calculus in the language of $\mathbf {S5(C)}$ whose consequence relation is denoted by $\vdash _{\mathbf {S5(C)}}$ . The axiom of this calculus are the instantiations of the axiom schemata of $\mathbf {C}$ for formulas in the language of $\mathbf {S5(C)}$ , plusing the axioms: , $(\square 2)$ , , $(\square 3)$ and . Moreover, Theorem 4.7 shows that the variety $\mathbb {MMTL}$ is the equivalent algebraic semantics of the logic $\mathbf {S5(MTL)}$ . As a consequence of the general theory of algebraizability all axiomatic extensions of $\mathbf {S5(MTL)}$ are algebraizable logics and their equivalent algebraic semantics are precisely the subvarieties of $\mathbb {MMTL}$ , see Corollary 4.8. In particular, given any axiomatic extension $\mathbf {C}$ of $\mathbf {MTL}$ , the logic $\mathbf {S5(C)}$ is an axiomatic extension of $\mathbf {S5(MTL)}$ with an equivalent algebraic semantics Alg $^\ast \mathbf {S5(C)}$ , denote also by $\mathbb {MMTL_C}$ . It is also worth noticing that $\mathbf {S5(C)}$ is actually equivalent to the monadic fragment in one variable (without constants) of the first-order logic $\mathbf {C\forall }$ because there is a natural correspondence between formulas of both logics, between corresponding models and between the corresponding truth degrees.

Given an axiomatic extension $\mathbf {C}$ of $\mathbf {MTL}$ , we say that a monadic MTL-algebra is $\mathbb {C}$ -functional if it is built in the previously defined way (Example 4.2 and Remark 4.3) from a linearly ordered MTL-algebra that belongs to Alg $\ast \mathbb {C}$ .

Along with the same line of Theorem 4.9, the following corollary naturally hold.

Corollary 5.1. Let $\mathbf {C}$ be an axiomatic extension of $\mathbf {MTL}$ . Then the following statements are equivalent:

  1. (1) For any formula $\varphi $ and any set of formulas $\Gamma $ , we have

    $$ \begin{align*} \Gamma\vdash_{\mathbf{S5(C)}}\varphi \text{ if and only if } \Gamma\models_{\mathbf{S5(C)}}\varphi. \end{align*} $$
  2. (2) The variety $\mathbb {MMTL_C}$ is generated, as a quasivariety, by its $\mathbb {C}$ -functional algebras

Theorem 3.13 shows that a monadic IMTL-algebra is a monadic MTL-algebra that satisfies the identity $\neg \neg x=x$ . In other words, a monadic IMTL-algebra is a monadic MTL-algebra whose MTL-reduct is an IMTL-algebra. This monadic algebra was first introduced in [Reference Wang and Xin53] as an equivalent algebraic semantic for monadic fuzzy predicate logic based on involutive monoidal t-norm logic $\mathbf {mIMTL\forall }$ .

Here we prove a representation theorem of monadic IMTL-algebras, and use it to derive strong completeness of the calculus with respect to the chain-based models. In order to make this section as self-contained as possible, we recall that some results about model theory in advance, which is indeed a straightforward application of model theoretic techniques [Reference Chang and Keisler6].

Let A be a structure in the first-order language $\mathcal {L}$ , and let $\{c_a:a\in A\}$ be a set of new constant symbols and put $\mathcal {L_A}=\mathcal {L}\cup \{c_a:a\in A\}$ . Given an $\mathcal {L}$ -structure B and a family $\{b_a:a\in A\}$ of elements of B, we denote by $(B,\{b_a\}_{a\in A})$ the expansion of B to the language $\mathcal {L_A}$ that results by defining $b_a$ as the interpretation of the constant $c_a$ for any $a\in A$ . The diagram of A, written diag(A), is the set of all atomic sentences and negations of atomic sentences in the language $\mathcal {L_A}$ which are true in $(A,\{b_a\}_{a\in A})$ .

Proposition 5.2 [Reference Chang and Keisler6]

Let $A,B$ be two $\mathcal {L}$ -structures and let $f:A\rightarrow B$ be a function. Then the following statements are equivalent:

  1. (1) f is an embedding of A into B,

  2. (2) $(B,\{f(a)\}_{a\in A})$ is a model of diag (A).

Let $\mathbb {K}$ be a class of structures in a first-order language. A V-formation in $\mathbb {K}$ is a 5-tuple $(A,A_1,A_2,\alpha _1,\alpha _2)$ consisting of three structures $A,A_1,A_2$ in $\mathbb {K}$ and two embeddings $\alpha _1:A\rightarrow A_1$ and $\alpha _2:A\rightarrow A_2$ . An amalgam in $\mathbb {K}$ of the V-formation is a triple $(B,\beta _1,\beta _2)$ consisting a structure B in $\mathbb {K}$ and two embeddings $\beta _1:A_1\rightarrow B$ and $\beta _2:A_2\rightarrow B$ satisfying $\beta _1\circ \alpha _1=\beta _2\circ \alpha _2$ .

The class $\mathbb {K}$ has the amalgamation property provided every V-formation in $\mathbb {K}$ has an amalgam in $\mathbb {K}$ . Here (Figure 4) we define a generalization of the notion of V-formation and amalgam. Given a set I, an I-formation in $\mathbb {K}$ is a triple $(A,(A_i)_{i\in I},\{a_i\}_{i\in I})$ where A and $A_i$ are a structure in $\mathbb {K}$ and each $\alpha _i:A\rightarrow A_i$ is an embedding. An amalgam in $\mathbb {K}$ of the I-formation is a pair $(B,\{\beta _i\}_{i\in I})$ , where B is a structure in $\mathbb {K}$ and $\beta _i:A_i\rightarrow B$ are embeddings such that $\beta _i\circ \alpha _i=\beta _j\circ \alpha _j$ for any $i,j\in I$ . Here we have that $\mathbb {K}$ has the amalgamation property over I if any I-formation in $\mathbb {K}$ has an amalgam in $\mathbb {K}$ , readers refer to [Reference Chang and Keisler6, Reference Gil-Férez, Jipsen and Metcalfe22, Reference Pierce40] for more details about results and examples of amalgamation.

Figure 4 An amalgamation diagram of $\mathbb {K}$ .

In particular, Pierce studied amalgamations of lattice ordered groups in [Reference Pierce40].

Example 5.3 [Reference Pierce40]

The class of totally ordered Abelian $\ell $ -groups has the amalgamation property.

Theorem 5.4 [Reference Chang and Keisler6]

Let $\mathbb {K}$ be a class of structures in a first-order language with the amalgamation property. Then $\mathbb {K}$ has the amalgamation property over any finite set I. If $\mathbb {K}$ is an elementary class, then $\mathbb {K}$ has the amalgamation property over any set I.

Theorem 5.4 can be applied to the class of totally ordered IMTL-algebras.

Corollary 5.5. The class of totally ordered IMTL-algebras has amalgamation property.

Proof. This result is a straightforward consequence of Example 5.3 by using Mundici’s well-known correspondence between totally ordered Abelian $\ell $ -groups and totally ordered IMTL-algebras in [Reference Esteva and Godo17].

As a consequence of Theorem 5.4, we get the following stronger result.

Theorem 5.6. The class of totally ordered IMTL-algebras has amalgamation property over any set.

With the aid of the general amalgamation property we prove here that finitely subdirectly irreducible monadic IMTL-algebras are isomorphic to $\mathcal {L}$ -functional algebras. As a consequence we derive the strong completeness theorem of monadic involutive monoidal t-norm based predicate logic.

Proposition 5.7. Let $(L,\forall ,\exists )$ be a finitely subdirectly irreducible monadic IMTL-algebra. Then for any $x\in L$ , there is a prime filter F of the IMTL-algebra L such that $x/F=\exists x/F$ and $F\cap \exists L=\{1\}$ .

Proof. Denote

$$ \begin{align*} \mathcal{F}=\{F\in F[L]\mid F\cap \exists L=\{1\},\exists x\rightarrow x\in F \}. \end{align*} $$

Here we now prove that there is a prime filter P in $\mathcal {F}$ .

Obviously $\mathcal {F}$ is non-empty since . Indeed, if , then $y\geq (\exists x\rightarrow x)^{2^n}$ for some positive integer. So

$$ \begin{align*} y=\exists y\geq \exists(\exists x\rightarrow x)^{2^n}=(\exists(\exists x\rightarrow x))^{2^n}=(\exists x\rightarrow \exists x)^{2^n}=1^{2^n}=1. \end{align*} $$

The union of a chain of filters in $\mathcal {F}$ is also a filter in $\mathcal {F}$ , and hence by Zorn’s Lemma, there is a maximal filter M in $\mathcal {F}$ . Here we show that M is indeed a prime filter. If M is not prime, then there are $x,y\in L$ such that $x\rightarrow y,y\rightarrow x \notin M$ . Thus M is properly contained in

By the maximality of M in $\mathcal {F}$ , we have that

If

then

Thus $z\vee w\in M\cap \exists L=\{1\}$ , that is, $z\vee w=1$ . Also, since $\exists L$ is totally ordered, $z=1$ or $w=1$ , which is a contradiction. This shows that M is a prime filter.

Proposition 5.8. Given a finite subdirectly irreducibleFootnote 6 monadic IMTL-algebra $(L,\forall ,\exists )$ , there exists a subdirect embedding

$$ \begin{align*} \alpha:L\rightarrow \prod\nolimits_{i\in I}L_i, \end{align*} $$

where each $L_i$ is a totally ordered IMTL-algebra and

$$ \begin{align*} \pi_i\circ \alpha|_{\exists L}:\exists L\rightarrow L_i \end{align*} $$

isFootnote 7 an embedding, where $\pi _i$ is the i-th projection map. Also, for any $x\in L$ , there are $i,j\in I$ such that

$$ \begin{align*} (\pi_i\circ \alpha)(\exists x)=(\pi_i\circ \alpha)(x),~~(\pi_j\circ \alpha)(\forall x)=(\pi_j\circ \alpha)(x). \end{align*} $$

Proof. It suffices to consider the subdirect representation of an IMTL-algebra L given by

$$ \begin{align*} L\rightarrow \prod\nolimits_{P\in \mathcal{P}}L/P, \end{align*} $$

where

$$ \begin{align*} \mathcal{P}=\{P\in PF[L]\mid P\cap \exists L=\{1\}\}. \end{align*} $$

Along with the same line of Theorem 16 in [Reference Di Nola and Grigolia11] that $\bigcap \mathcal {P}=\{1\}$ , so the representation is subdirect. The condition $P\cap \exists L=\{1\}$ guarantees that the projections on $L/P$ are one–one correspondence on $\exists L$ . Now, given $x\in L$ , there is $P\in \mathcal {P}$ such that $\exists x/P=x/P$ . Also, there is $P_1\in \mathcal {P}$ such that $\exists \neg x/P_1=\neg x/P_1$ , so $\forall x/P_1=\neg \exists \neg x/P_1=\neg \neg x/P_1=x/P_1$ .

Theorem 5.9. Every finitely subdirectly irreducible monadic IMTL-algebra $(L,\forall ,\exists )$ is isomorphic to an $\mathcal {L}$ -functional monadic IMTL-algebra, that is, there exist a totally ordered IMTL-algebra B, an index set I and an embedding $\alpha :L\rightarrow B^I$ such that

$$ \begin{align*} \alpha(\exists x)(i)=\sup\{\alpha(x)(j):j\in I\}, \alpha(\forall x)(i)=\inf\{\alpha(x)(j):j\in I\} \end{align*} $$

for any $x\in L$ and $i\in I$ .

Proof. Proposition 5.8 produces a family $\{L_i|i\in I\}$ of totally ordered IMTL-algebras and embedding

$$ \begin{align*} \alpha:L\rightarrow \prod\nolimits_{i\in I}L_i, \end{align*} $$

such that

$$ \begin{align*} \pi_i\circ \alpha|_{\exists L}:\exists L\rightarrow L_i \end{align*} $$

is an embedding for any $i\in I$ . Consider the I-formation $(\exists L,\{L_i|i\in I\},\pi _i\circ \alpha |\exists L|i\in I\}$ in the elementary class $\mathbb {K}$ of totally ordered IMTL-algebras. By Theorem 5.6, the I-information has an amalgam $(B,\{\beta _i|i\in I\})$ in $\mathbb {K}$ . Let

$$ \begin{align*} \beta:=\prod\beta_i:\prod\nolimits_{i\in I}L_i\rightarrow B^I \end{align*} $$

and note that

$$ \begin{align*} \beta\circ\alpha:A\rightarrow B^I \end{align*} $$

is an embedding. Here we prove that

$$ \begin{align*} (\beta\circ\alpha)(\exists x)(i)=\sup\{(\beta\circ\alpha)(x)(j):j\in I\}, \end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*} (\beta\circ\alpha)(\forall x)(i)=\inf\{(\beta\circ\alpha)(x)(j):j\in I\}, \end{align*} $$

for any $x\in L$ and $i\in I$ .

Indeed, because of the amalgamation of the I-formation, we have that

$$ \begin{align*} (\beta\circ\alpha)(\exists x)(i)&= \beta(\alpha(\exists x))(i)\\ &= \beta_i(\alpha(\exists x))(i)\\ &= \beta_i(\pi_i(\alpha(\exists x)))\\ &= \beta_j(\pi_j(\alpha(\exists x)))\\ &= \beta_j(\alpha(\exists x))(j)\\ &= \beta(\alpha(\exists x))(j)\\ &= (\beta\circ\alpha)(\exists x)(j), \end{align*} $$

for any $i,j\in I$ , and also know that there is $i_0\in I$ such that

$$ \begin{align*} (\pi_{i_0}\circ \alpha)(\exists x)=(\pi_{i_0}\circ \alpha)(x). \end{align*} $$

Then

$$ \begin{align*} (\beta\circ\alpha)(x)(i_0)&= (\beta\circ\alpha)(\exists x)(j)\\ &\geq (\beta\circ\alpha)(\exists x)(j)\\ &\geq (\beta\circ\alpha)(x)(j), \end{align*} $$

for any $j\in I$ , which shows that

$$ \begin{align*} (\beta\circ\alpha)(\exists x)(i_0)=\sup\{(\beta\circ\alpha)(x)(j)\mid j\in I\}. \end{align*} $$

The proof of $\forall x$ is similar to that of $\exists x$ .

Corollary 5.10. The variety of monadic IMTL-algebras is generated, as a quasivariety, by its $\mathcal {L}$ -functional members.

The last result of this section is a strong completeness theorem with respect to chain-based models.

Theorem 5.11. For any formula $\varphi $ and any set of formulas $\Gamma $ , we have

$$ \begin{align*} \Gamma\vdash_{S5\mathcal{(L)}}\varphi \text{ if and only if } \Gamma\models_{S5\mathcal{(L)}}\varphi. \end{align*} $$

6 Concluding remarks and future work

The motivation of this paper is to give an algebraic proof of completeness for monadic fuzzy predicate logic $\mathbf {mMTL\forall }$ and some of its axiomatic extensions. In order to achieve our aim, we first survey the present state of knowledge on monadic algebras of t-norm based residuated fuzzy logic and show that the relationships for monadic algebras of t-norm based fuzzy residuated logic completely inherit that for corresponding algebras of t-norm based fuzzy residuated logic. The results of Section 4 proved that the variety of monadic MTL-algebras is the equivalent algebraic semantics of the logic $\mathbf {mMTL\forall }$ and gave an algebraic proof of completeness for this logic. Along with the same line, we further obtained the completeness theorem of some axiomatic extensions of the logic $\mathbf {mMTL\forall }$ , and proved the strong completeness theorem of monadic fuzzy predicate logic $\mathbf {mIMTL\forall }$ via functional representation of finitely subdirectly irreducible algebras in Section 5.

Hopefully this first step will allow us to prove a strong result, namely the strong standard completeness for monadic fuzzy predicate logic $\mathbf {mIMTL\forall }$ that is equivalent to fuzzy modal logic $\mathbf {S5(IMTL)}$ , which is one of the topics in subsequent discussions.

Acknowledgments

The authors are extremely grateful to the editor and the referees for their valuable comments and suggestions which help to improve the presentation of this paper.

Funding

This work is supported by the National Natural Science Foundation of China (Grant Nos. 12331016, 12001423 and 61976244) and the Natural Science Basic Research Plan in Shaanxi Province of China (2023-JC-YB-027).

Footnotes

1 Gödel logic $\mathbf {G}$ is also obtained by adding to $\mathbf {BL}$ the axiom $\mathbf {(IDE).}$

2 Łukasiewicz logic is $\mathbf {BL}$ plus the axiom $\mathbf {(INV)}$ .

3 Weak nilpotent minimum logic $\mathbf {WNM}$ is $\mathbf {MTL}$ plus the axiom $\mathbf {(WNM)}$ .

4 Variety is a basic notion on Universal Algebra, which is a class of algebras that is closed under subalgebras, homomorphic images, and direct products, readers please refer to Definition 9.3 and its related basic notions in [Reference Burris and Sankappanavar3] for more details.

5 $\mathbf {\Gamma }$ is a predicate language $(\mathbf {P,F,A})$ , where $\mathbf {P}$ is a non-empty set of predicate symbols, $\mathbf {F}$ is a set of function symbols, and $\mathbf {A}$ is a function assigning to each predicate and function symbol a natural number called the arity of the symbol.

6 An algebra A is subdirectly irreducible if for every subdirect embedding

$$ \begin{align*} \alpha:A\rightarrow \prod\nolimits_{i\in I}A_i \end{align*} $$

there is an $i\in I$ such that

$$ \begin{align*} \pi_i\circ \alpha:A\rightarrow A_i \end{align*} $$

is an isomorphism. Readers please refer to Definition 8.3 in [Reference Burris and Sankappanavar3] for more details. Moreover, Proposition 5.8 shows that a monadic IMTL-algebra $(L,\forall ,\exists )$ is finite subdirectly irreducible if and only if $\exists L$ is totally ordered.

7 Which is equivalent to $\pi _i\circ \alpha |_{\forall L}:\forall L\rightarrow L_i$ since $\forall L=\exists L$ for any monadic IMTL-algebra $(L,\forall ,\exists ).$

References

Blok, W. J., & Pigozzi, D. (1989). Algebraizable logics. Memoirs of the American Mathematical Society, Vol. 77(396). Providence: American Mathematical Society.Google Scholar
Borzooei, R. A., Shoar, S. K., & Ameri, R. (2012). Some types of filters in MTL-algebras. Fuzzy Sets and Systems, 187, 92102.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burris, S., & Sankappanavar, M. P. (1981). A Course in Universal Algebra. New York: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Castaño, D., Cimadamore, C., Verela, J. P. D., & Rueda, L. (2017). Monadic BL-algebras: The equivalent algebraic semantics of Hájek’s monadic fuzzy logic. Fuzzy Sets and Systems, 320, 4059.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chang, C. C. (1958). Algebraic analysis of many-valued logics. Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, 88, 467490.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chang, C. C., & Keisler, H. J. (1990). Model Theory. Amsterdam: Elsevier.Google Scholar
Cignoli, R., & Esteva, F. (2009). Commutative integral bounded residuated lattices with an added involution. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 161, 150160.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cignoli, R., Esteva, F., Godo, L., & Torrens, A. (2000). Basic fuzzy logic is the logic of continuous t-norms and their residua. Soft Computing, 4, 106112.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cintula, P., Horčík, R., & Noguera, C. (2013). Non-associative substructural logics and their semilinear extensions: A xiomatization and completeness properties. The Review of Symbolic Logic, 6, 394423.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cintula, P., & Noguera, C. (2015). A Henkin-style proof of completeness for first-order algebraizable logics. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 80, 341358.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Di Nola, A., & Grigolia, R. (2004). On monadic MV-algebras. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 128, 125139.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Di Nola, A., Grigolia, R., & Lenzi, G. (2019). Topological spaces of monadic MV- algebras. Soft Computing, 23, 375381.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Drŭgulici, D. D. (2001). Quantifiers on BL-algebras. Analele Universitatill Bucuret Mathematica Informatica, 50, 2942.Google Scholar
Dzik, W., & Wojtylak, P. (2019). Unification in superintuitionistic predicate logics and its applications. The Review of Symbolic Logic, 12, 3761.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Esteva, F., Gispert, J., Godo, L., & Montagan, F. (2002). On the standard and rational completeness of some axiomatic extensions of monoidal t-norm based logic. Studia Logica, 71, 199226.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Esteva, F., & Godo, L. (2001). Monoidal t-norm based logic: Towards a logic for left-continuous t-norms. Fuzzy Sets and Systems, 124, 271288.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Esteva, F., & Godo, L. (2007). Towards the generalization of Mundici’s Γ functor to IMTL-algebras: The linearly ordered case. In Algebraic and Proof-Theoretic Aspects of Non-Classical Logics: Papers in Honor of Daniele Mundici on the Occasion of his 60th Birthday. Berlin–Heidelberg: Springer, pp. 127137.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Esteva, F., Godo, L., & Noguera, C. (2009). First-order t-norm based fuzzy logics with truth-constants: Distinguished semantics and completeness properties. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 161, 185202.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Figallo Orellano, A. (2017). A topological duality for monadic MV-algebras. Soft Computing, 21, 71197123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ghorbani, S. (2018). Logic for abstract hoop twist-structures. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 169, 981996.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ghorbani, S. (2019). Monadic pseudo equality algebras. Soft Computing, 23, 14991510.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gil-Férez, J., Jipsen, P., & Metcalfe, G. (2020). Structure theorems for idempotent residuated lattices. Algebra U niversalis, 28, 125.Google Scholar
Gottwal, S., García-Cerdaña, A., & Bou, F. (2003). Axiomatizing monoidal logic — a correction. Journal of Multiple-Valued Logic and Soft Computing, 9, 427433.Google Scholar
Gottwal, S., & Jenei, S. (2001). On a new axiomatization for involutive monoidal t-norm based logic. Fuzzy Sets and Systems, 124, 303308.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grigolia, R. (2006). Monadic BL-algebras. Georgian Mathematical Journal, 13, 267276.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hájek, P. (1998). Metamathematics of Fuzzy Logic. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hájek, P. (2002). Observations on the monoidal t-norm logic. Fuzzy Sets and Systems. 132, 107112.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hájek, P. (2002). Monadic fuzzy predicate logic. Studia Logica, 71, 165175.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hájek, P. (2009). Arithmetical complexity of fuzzy predicate logics—a survey II. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 161, 212219.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hájek, P. (2010). On fuzzy modal logics S5(C). Fuzzy Sets and Systems, 161, 23892396.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hájek, P., Paris, J., & Shepherdson, J. (2000). Rational Pavelka predicate logic is a conservative extension of Łukasiewicz predicate logic. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 65, 669682.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Halmos, R. P. (1955). Algebraic logic, I. Monadic Boolean algebras. Composition Mathematica, 12, 217249.Google Scholar
Jenei, S., & Montagan, F. (2002). A proof of standard completeness for Esteva and Godo’s logic. Studia Logica, 70, 183192.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kurahashi, T. (2013). Arithmetical interpretations and K ripke frames of predicate modal logic of provability. The Review of Symbolic Logic, 6, 129146.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Metcalfe, G., & Montagna, F. (2007). Substructural fuzzy logics. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 72, 834864.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Montagna, F., & Ono, H. (2002). Kripke semantics, undecidability and standard completeness for Esteva and Godo’s logic MTL∀. Studia Logica, 71, 227245.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Noguera, C. (2006). Algebraic study of axiomatic extensions of triangular norm based fuzzy logics. PhD Thesis, IIIA-CSIC.Google Scholar
Olkhovikov, G. K., & Badia, G. (2023). Craig interpolation theorem fails in bi-intuitionistic predicate logic. The Review of Symbolic Logic, 123. https://doi.org/10.1017/S1755020322000296 Google Scholar
Pei, D. W. (2003). On equivalent forms of fuzzy logic systems NM and IMTL. Fuzzy Sets and Systems, 138, 187195.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pierce, K. R. (1972). Amalgamations of lattice ordered groups. Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, 172, 249260.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Poacik, T. (1998). Propositional quantification in the monadic fragment of intuitionistic logic. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 63, 269300.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rach ů nek, J., & Šalounová, D. (2008). Monadic GMV-algebras. Archive for Mathematical Logic, 47, 277297.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rach ů nek, J., & Šalounová, D. (2013). Monadic bounded residuated lattices. Order, 30, 195210.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rach ů nek, J., & Švrček, F. (2008). Monadic bounded residuated ℓ-monoids. Order, 25, 157175.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rutledge, J. D. (1959). A preliminary investigation of the infinitely many-valued predicate calculus. PhD Thesis, Cornell University.Google Scholar
Tharp, L. H. (1983). The characterization of monadic logic. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 38, 481488.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Torsun, I. S. (1995). Foundations of Intelligent Knowledge-Based Systems. London: Academic Press.Google Scholar
Wang, J. T., He, P. F., & She, Y. H. (2019). Monadic NM-algebras. Logic Journal of the IGPL, 27, 812835.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wang, J. T., He, P. F., Yang, J., Wang, M., & He, X. L. (2022). Monadic NM-algebras: A n algebraic approach to monadic predicate nilpotent minimum logic. Journal of Logic and Computation, 32, 741766.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wang, J. T., He, X. L., & Wang, M. (2022). An algebraic study of the logic S5’(BL). Mathematica Slovaca, 72, 14471462.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wang, J. T., She, Y. H., He, P. F., & Ma, N. N. (2023). On categorical equivalence of weak monadic residuated distributive lattices and weak monadic c-differential residuated distributive lattices. Studia Logica, 111, 361390.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wang, J. T., Wang, M., & She, Y. H. (2023). Algebraic semantics of similarity in monadic substructural predicate logics. Acta Electronica Sinica, 51, 956964.Google Scholar
Wang, J. T., & Xin, X. L. (2022). Monadic algebras of an involutive monoidal t-norm based logic. Iranian Journal of Fuzzy Systems, 19, 187202.Google Scholar
Wang, J. T., Xin, X. L., & He, P. F. (2018). Monadic bounded hoops. Soft Computing, 22, 17491762.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ward, M., & Dilworth, R. P. (1938). Residuated lattices. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 24, 162164.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Zadeh, L. A. (2015). Fuzzy logic—a personal perspective. Fuzzy Sets and Systems, 281, 420.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zahiri, S., & Borumand Saeid, A. (2022). A new model of fuzzy logic: Monadic monoidal t-norm based logic. Research Square. https://doi.org/10.21203/rs.3.rs-948685/v1 Google Scholar
Zhang, J. L. (2011). Topological properties of prime filters in MTL-algebras and fuzzy set representations for MTL-algebras. Fuzzy Sets and Systems, 178, 3853.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Figure 0

Figure 1 Relationships between t-norm based residuated fuzzy logics.

Figure 1

Figure 2 Relationships between algebras of t-norm based residuated fuzzy logic.

Figure 2

Figure 3 Relationships between monadic algebras of t-norm based residuated fuzzy logic.

Figure 3

Figure 4 An amalgamation diagram of $\mathbb {K}$.