Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-s2hrs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-20T04:48:45.936Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The prohibition of forced or compulsory labour and conditional welfare under the United Kingdom's Universal Credit Scheme

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  27 April 2023

Ahmed Almutawa*
Affiliation:
Royal Academy of Police, Bahrain
Bashayer Almajed
Affiliation:
Kuwait University College of Law, Kuwait
*
*Corresponding author e-mail: [email protected]
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

To address the issue of persistent unemployment, the UK Government implemented a conditional welfare scheme. Prompted by Mantouvalou's argument that the scheme forces people into exploitative work, this paper addresses the ‘pressing’ question of whether the scheme is compatible with the prohibition on ‘forced or compulsory labour’ under Article 4(2) of the European Convention on Human Rights. It is argued that, whether the scheme imposes the menace of a penalty, is involuntary, seriously exploitative or a normal civic obligation, ultimately depends on different understandings of the demands of distributive justice. Given the politically contested nature of those demands, Article 4(2) is a poor weapon to use when challenging the UK's conditional welfare scheme.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Society of Legal Scholars

Introduction

In the context of stagnated markets, precarious employment and ‘slow economic growth’, the management of ‘persistently high un(der)employment’ is a perennial problem for the UK and other states in the ‘Global North’.Footnote 1 Since 1971, UK unemployment has varied between 3.4% and 11.9%.Footnote 2 To reduce unemployment, and its negative impact on financial security, health, and wellbeing,Footnote 3 the UK's Universal Credit (UC) scheme implements a policy that makes benefit payments conditional on the recipient's active engagement with the labour market. The approach may be justified consequentially by its potential to reduce the overall cost of benefit payments, increase economic output, and improve the financial security of individuals and their families. However, such policies remain controversial and are heavily criticised for being unjust or for violating human rights.Footnote 4

One compelling critique is Mantouvalou's argument that, when situated within the context of precarious, ‘non-standard work’, the UK's scheme creates a form of ‘structural injustice’. This injustice prejudices the unemployed and low-paid by ‘coercing’ them ‘into conditions of in-work poverty and exploitation through the menace and imposition of severe sanctions’.Footnote 5 For Mantouvalou, this raises ‘pressing questions about compliance with human rights law’.Footnote 6

One such ‘pressing’ question is whether the UK scheme, which ‘forces’ people into exploitative work, ‘is compatible with Article 4’ of the European Convention on Human Rights (ECHR).Footnote 7 The imperative for ‘reopen[ing]’ this question finds support in Dermine's earlier doctrinal analysis of activation policies and the prohibition on forced labour in international law. Dermine argues that the reasoning in some of the case law implicitly acknowledges that conditional welfare activation policies ‘might contravene the prohibition of forced labour’. Consequently, lawyers should bring such cases to court, which should ‘confront’ the substantive injustices of conditional welfare policies ‘with the defining criteria of forced labour’.Footnote 8

In this paper, the prospects of such a confrontation are assessed by considering whether the UK's conditional welfare scheme could, or should, amount to a violation of Article 4 of the ECHR. This issue is timely in the wake of Brexit and the Covid-19 pandemic,Footnote 9 and given the worrying increase in the costs of living.Footnote 10 It is also worth addressing in some depth, given Mantouvalou's and Dermine's similar conclusions regarding the relevance of Article 4 to conditional welfare schemes. The idea that conditional welfare schemes ‘may contravene the prohibition of forced labour’ is gaining some traction.Footnote 11 Furthermore, Mantouvalou has recently reiterated her arguments. She maintains that the threat of destitution from punitive sanctions, which ‘force and trap people into zero-hours and other precarious work’, creates ‘structures of exploitation’ sufficient to violate ‘the prohibition of forced and compulsory labour’. For Mantouvalou, the compatibility of such schemes with Article 4 must be ‘revisit[ed]’.Footnote 12

The primary aim of this paper is to examine the potential for Article 4 to be used as a legal tool to challenge conditional welfare policies. As an arguably unjust system that imposes harsh sanctions and may require benefit claimants to accept precarious employment,Footnote 13 the UK conditional welfare scheme provides a good example for this analysis. Through this analysis, the paper also contributes to any wider discussion regarding the role and limitations of legal human rights in challenging social welfare policy.Footnote 14

The paper begins by describing the scheme and its underlying policy. Whether the scheme amounts to forced labour is assessed by considering whether the UK scheme violates Article 4 of the ECHR.Footnote 15 The analysis is organised under the four interrelated elements that determine the meaning of ‘forced or compulsory labour’ as prohibited by Article 4(2). While it may plausibly be argued that the scheme violates Article 4(2), the counterarguments are stronger. Given the principle of subsidiarity, it is argued that the European Court of Human Rights (the Court) should not, and most likely would not, decide that the UK scheme violates Article 4. The distributive (in)justice of the UK's conditional welfare scheme should be addressed as an issue of politics rather than human rights law.

Although an in-depth focus on Article 4 is worthwhile, its narrow focus limits the scope of the enquiry. The relevance of Article 3 is briefly discussed, but the impact of the UK scheme on the benefit claimant's Article 8 right to a private and family life is not considered. The impact of the scheme on the human rights of specific groups such as the disabled, single parents, and women is also not addressed. Single mothers,Footnote 16 for example, may be disproportionately impacted by the scheme's conditional welfare and harsh sanctions.Footnote 17 Addressing such issues would require an analysis of the Court's approach to discrimination under Article 14.Footnote 18 This is beyond the scope of the paper, but it is notable that the Court has held that compulsory labour justified as a normal civic obligation under Article 4(3), may nevertheless breach Article 14 where it is imposed in a way that unjustifiably discriminates between men and women.Footnote 19

1. The UK's approach to conditional welfare

As a labour market activation policy, the UK's approach to welfare under the UC system is intended to address the ‘culture of benefit dependency’ and reduce unemployment either by ‘encourag[ing] direct employment' or by ‘enhanc[ing] employability’ through ‘training and education’.Footnote 20 This ‘good’ idea is complicated by the policies of distinguishing between deserving and undeserving claimants and mandating labour-market participation.Footnote 21 The resulting system of sanction-backed, conditional welfare has understandably attracted significant criticism.Footnote 22

The conditional elements of the UC system are centred on the claimant commitment, which must be accepted as a basic condition of entitlement to benefits.Footnote 23 The claimant commitment is the formal record of the claimant's work-related responsibilities agreed with the claimant's work coach.Footnote 24 Depending on individual circumstance,Footnote 25 claimants will be assigned to one of four groups that impose either no work-related requirements or oblige them to participate in up to four work-related requirements:Footnote 26 work-focused interview, work preparation, work search and work availability (being ‘able and willing immediately to take up paid work’, more or better-paid work).Footnote 27

Work coaches are instructed by the Department for Work and Pensions (DWP) to give ‘consideration' to the ‘public law principles of fairness’, which require that claimants are sufficiently well informed ‘to make informed and meaningful representations’Footnote 28 regarding a work requirement.Footnote 29 Claimants must be informed of any imposed requirements and the ‘consequences of failing to comply’, which includes the imposition of sanctions.Footnote 30 Any work requirement ‘should be reasonable and achievable for the individual claimant and their circumstances’.Footnote 31 Work-related requirements are subject to specific legislative easements, but work coaches also have the discretion to ‘temporarily suspend conditionality requirements’ where it would be unreasonable to impose them because of the individual claimant's ‘complex needs’, which include homelessness, addiction and other mental health issues.Footnote 32 It should be noted, however, that ‘evidence suggests that they are not systematically applied’ and that ‘discretionary powers are routinely ineffective in addressing’ the power imbalance between claimants and those who administer the scheme.Footnote 33 Nevertheless, where claimants believe they are being asked to do something unreasonable given their personal circumstances then they are entitled to ‘ask for a review of the claimant commitment’.Footnote 34

It is worth noting here that the DWP considers zero-hours contracts to be reasonable employment.Footnote 35 In response to a Freedom of Information request, the DWP stated that ‘UC work coaches routinely use their discretion to decide if jobs including ZHC vacancies are suitable for a particular individual’. The DWP further stated that sanctions would be applied to claimants who fail to apply for zero-hours contracts barring those with an ‘exclusivity clause’.Footnote 36 This reliance on zero-hours contracts as reasonable employment, and the power to ‘mandate’ them for benefit claimants followed a change in policy with the shift to the UC scheme.Footnote 37 While there is no data on how many claimants have been required to accept zero-hours contract to avoid sanctions, the prevalence of zero-hours contracts has risen from 225,000 in December 2000 to over 1.1 million by the end of 2022.Footnote 38 Furthermore, empirical studies suggest that ‘the first contact with precarious jobs often starts at the Jobcentre where claimants are encouraged, directed or coerced to apply for … zero-hours work’.Footnote 39 Research suggests that it is not uncommon for work coaches to ‘insist’ that claimants accept zero-hours contracts.Footnote 40

Because the claimant commitment is a basic condition for receiving benefits, there is pressure on claimants to accept the assigned work-related requirements as soon as possible. Research indicates that the claimant commitment is ‘experienced … as coercive rather than contractual’.Footnote 41 Once agreed, the requirements become mandatory. The DWP guidance explains that a claimant fails to comply where they fail ‘to act in accordance with a specific requirement’. This includes refusing to do the specified activity but may also include other inappropriate behaviour such as being antagonistic, acting unreasonably or in a manner that is unacceptable in the workplace.Footnote 42 Claimants must be given an opportunity to explain and ‘show good reason’ for any failure to comply. In considering whether the claimant has shown good reason, the decision maker must take into account the claimant's ‘individual circumstances and reasonableness’.Footnote 43 Where a claimant fails to comply ‘for no good reason’, this may result in a sanction,Footnote 44 which reduces the benefit payment by 100% of the standard allowance.Footnote 45 There are four levels of sanction, with the higher-level sanctions lasting initially for 91 days, subject to extension up to 182 days for repeat failures.Footnote 46 Hardship payments are available to mitigate the impact of sanctions, provided claimants have complied with all work-related requirements for seven days prior to submitting the claim.Footnote 47

The scheme's underlying policy motivations were ‘to ensure that work always pays’Footnote 48 and the perceived need to tackle the ‘significant and growing problem’ of poverty and welfare dependency.Footnote 49 Based on the idea that ‘strong and clear sanctions are critical to incentivise benefit recipients to meet their responsibilities’,Footnote 50 this approach centres on individual responsibility, blame and coercive compliance, the ‘underlying assumption’ being that those who decline the opportunity to work are ‘benefit “scroungers” who do not want to work’ and thus do not deserve benefits.Footnote 51 In this age of ‘welfare austerity’, the government narrative emphasises the issue of welfare dependency at the expense of any concern for poverty.Footnote 52 This stigmatising narrativeFootnote 53 is reflected in the ‘creeping conditionality’ of welfare reforms that are particularly characterised by ‘the scale and nature of the cuts to public social spending and the elevated role of welfare withdrawal and sanctions’.Footnote 54

Wright and Dwyer describe UC as ‘the most all-encompassing manifestation of conditionality in any developed welfare system’.Footnote 55 The increased emphasis on welfare conditionality, and benefits as earned entitlements that must be deserved, has established ‘a framework of “state-mediated structural injustice”’.Footnote 56 Undermining the needs-based ‘rights and status of social citizenship’, UK welfare reforms have increased social inequalities, with the more frequent use of severe sanctions disproportionately impacting on the young, on single parents, the disabled and the homeless.Footnote 57 Against a backdrop of rising living costs, cuts to social security spending, and an increasingly precarious labour market, welfare conditionality has created a form of ‘structural violence’ that weaponises the humiliation of destitution to intimidate claimants into active engagement with the labour market.Footnote 58

For many claimants, life on benefits is a matter of survival, with destitution a reality or imminent threat.Footnote 59 The reliance on a coercive system of conditional welfare worsens the risk and reality of destitution, pushes claimants to adopt subversive or non-compliant survival strategies,Footnote 60 and negatively impacts the mental health of welfare recipients.Footnote 61 This may be exacerbated by the extensive use of sanctions,Footnote 62 particularly for relatively minor infractions.Footnote 63 Rather than being a relational device that enables the work adviser to support the claimant's search for employment, the claimant commitment becomes a surveillance device that facilitates the penal role of sanctions.Footnote 64 The coercive combination of the claimant commitment backed by punitive sanctions and the poorly paid, precarious employment at the lower end of the labour market upsets the ‘balance … between support and conditionality’,Footnote 65 so marginalising the ‘powerless’ unemployed.Footnote 66 As the Welfare Conditionality Project found, ‘stringent sanctions’ ensured compliance but did so in a counterproductive way that impacted negatively on wellbeing, failed to improve employment prospects and pressured claimants into applying for unsuitable employment, such as zero-hours contracts, to avoid the imposition of sanctions perceived as unfair and inappropriate.Footnote 67 The question then, is whether the approach under the UC scheme, which prioritises conditionality at the expense of the individual's needs,Footnote 68 violates the human rights of those trapped between destitution and in-work poverty?

From a legal human rights perspective, the effect that benefit sanctions may have on the lives of claimants and their families provides the basis for a claim under Article 3 of the ECHR, which prohibits inhuman or degrading treatment.Footnote 69 Arguably, the state is responsible for imposing sanctions that result in ‘[extreme] deprivation’,Footnote 70 and the UK's ‘punitive approach’ raises the spectre of ‘cruel, inhuman or degrading treatment’.Footnote 71 Significantly, however, Article 3 claims may only be successful in individual cases where a sanctioned person is ‘unable to access food or shelter to such an extent and for such a period as to cause significant suffering’.Footnote 72 The advantage of an Article 4 claim is that, insofar as the punitive use of sanctions coercively forces individuals into employment, it more readily allows for a principle-based challenge to the scheme itself. If it can be shown that sanctions are punitive measures that coerce people into employment, then their very existence undermines the principle that work should be voluntary and not exacted under the menace of a penalty.

2. Article 4 and the UK's conditional welfare scheme

Article 4 of the ECHR prohibits slavery and forced labour. In the context of work performed as part of a conditional welfare scheme, the Article 4(1) prohibition on slavery has no direct relevance.Footnote 73 Thus, the acceptability of the UK conditional welfare policy falls to be assessed under the Article 4(2) prohibition on forced labour. This is subject to the exception provided for under Article 4(3)(d), which allows work to be required as ‘part of normal civic obligations’.

It is notable that in all three cases to have reached Strasbourg, the claim that a state's conditional welfare policy violated Article 4(2) was summarily rejected as inadmissible.Footnote 74 This was followed by the Supreme Court in R (on the application of Reilly and Another) v Secretary of State for Work and Pensions, which concerned conditional welfare arrangements under the Jobseekers Act (JSA) 1995 and associated Regulations. Miss Reilly was required to participate in the unpaid Sector-based Work Academy scheme, which was intended to provide training and work-experience in a placement linked to a ‘genuine job vacancy’. Miss Reilly was wrongly told that her participation was mandatory. She claimed, inter alia, that her mandated participation, and/or the Regulations, were contrary to Article 4.Footnote 75 In rejecting Miss Reilly's cross-appeal on this issue, and upholding the Court of Appeal's decision, the Supreme Court held that Article 4 was aimed at preventing exploitative conduct and that, in the context of welfare benefits, ‘the imposition of the work condition’ failed to meet even ‘the starting point for a possible contravention of article 4’.Footnote 76

These cases suggest it would be difficult to satisfy the Court that conditional welfare schemes violate, or even engage, Article 4. Indeed, in Schuitemaker v the Netherlands the Court explained that ‘in general’ a state is ‘fully entitled’ to impose eligibility conditions on the payment of welfare benefits.Footnote 77 However, the case law has been criticised, and it is arguable that, by restricting its decision to the specific ‘condition at issue’, the Court in Schuitemaker did not rule out the possibility that a conditional welfare scheme could engage Article 4 and justify a full hearing of the merits.Footnote 78

This possibility is supported by the Court's evolutive approach to interpreting the ECHR as a ‘living instrument’ that adapts to changing social circumstances and attitudes.Footnote 79 Since the 1976 case of X v the Netherlands, the nature of the work obligations imposed on welfare claimants has changed.Footnote 80 Specifically, the obligation to accept precarious employment opportunities, such as zero-hours contracts, may distinguish the present UK scheme from those in previous cases and justify a full hearing. Furthermore, consider Faure v Australia, which concerned, inter alia, a claim that the requirement to attend the Australian Work for Dole program was a violation of Article 8(3) of the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights. While ultimately rejecting the claim, the UN Human Rights Committee observed that there was ‘undoubtedly’ an ‘arguable claim’,Footnote 81 and held that Faure's arguments were ‘sufficient[ly] weight[y] … for purposes of admissibility’.Footnote 82 Given that the Court may look to the UN Committee's communications as an aid to interpreting the ECHR,Footnote 83 its approach in Faure shows the potential for Article 4 if generously interpreted. It is, therefore, worth considering in more depth whether the current UK scheme is consistent with Article 4(2) of the ECHR.

An analysis of Article 4 jurisprudence identified four interrelated issues. The first two follow from the Court's reliance on the International Labour Organisation's (ILO) definition of forced labour as work ‘exacted from any person under the menace of any penalty and for which the said person has not offered himself voluntarily’.Footnote 84 Thus, the two issues are whether the scheme imposes ‘the menace of any penalty’, and whether the work is imposed as an involuntary obligation. The third issue is that the mischief targeted by Article 4(2) is ‘serious exploitation’.Footnote 85 The fourth issue is whether, under Article 4(3), the work is excluded from the definition of forced labour because it falls within the normal or ordinary obligations arising from living within a community.

(a) The menace of a penalty

The ‘menace of a penalty’ requirement targets the mischief of compelling performance by threating a punishment that would cause a loss or disadvantage.Footnote 86 The threat need not relate to a ‘sanction of a criminal character’, but must be ‘sufficiently daunting’.Footnote 87 Under the UK scheme, this may be satisfied by the threat of sanction where benefit claimants, without good reason, fail to comply with their work-related obligations.Footnote 88 While lacking the hostility of a criminal threat, the sanction mechanism serves the equivalent purpose of constraining choiceFootnote 89 and takes the same form as a threat or menace: ‘if you don't comply then you will be sanctioned’. Although mitigated by the good reason justification for noncompliance, the sanction mechanism remains a threat. Whether the UK scheme compels labour through ‘the menace of a penalty’ thus depends on whether the sanctions are penalties, a question that has been decided differently by the Danish (benefit sanctions are not penalties) and Dutch (benefit sanctions are penalties) courts.Footnote 90

It might be argued that the terminology of sanction used in the legislation is synonymous with a penalty: it is simply a different label for what is effectively the same concept. Consider the Supreme Court's discussion of when a parking charge would constitute a penalty.Footnote 91 For the Supreme Court, where the charge served no legitimate interest or was ‘out of all proportion’, being ‘extravagant’, ‘exorbitant’ or ‘unconscionable’, then it would constitute a penalty.Footnote 92

The UK scheme undoubtedly serves a legitimate interest, given the underlying policy goals of reducing unemployment, poverty, and the welfare budget. However, this may be undermined by the unjust, disproportionate, and punitive nature of the sanctions,Footnote 93 which ‘could have a profound and long-lasting financial impact’.Footnote 94 These sanctions threaten the risk of destitution, which is ‘unconscionable’ in a comparatively rich liberal democracy, such as the UK, and it is ‘out of all proportion’ to the legitimate aim of reducing unemployment. The availability of hardship payments mitigates the risk of destitution. However, claimants may not be informed of their availability and hardship payments must be repaid,Footnote 95 which limits their ability to stave off the longer-term risk of destitution that accompanies the prolonged periods of sanctions imposed for repeat failures to comply with the claimant commitments.Footnote 96

Whether state governments can be held responsible for individuals becoming destitute through a failure to provide welfare support has been considered in the context of the state's Article 3 obligation not to subject anyone to inhuman or degrading treatment.Footnote 97 While there is no general duty to prevent destitution,Footnote 98 the state may be held responsible, but the threshold is high.Footnote 99 Even 14 months of homelessness has been deemed insufficient to reach the severity required ‘to engage Article 3’, regardless of the impact on the claimant's health.Footnote 100 While the Court has held that unacceptable living conditions may be sufficient to cross the threshold, this was in the context of asylum seekers held in detention centres.Footnote 101 Similarly, the state may violate Article 3 if it fails to provide welfare support to destitute asylum seekers who are forbidden from working by law and cannot secure ‘assistance from friends or charity’.Footnote 102

Both benefit claimants and asylum seekers may be characterised as vulnerable and dependent on the state for support.Footnote 103 However, the key distinction between the two groups is the degree of control exerted over asylum seekers, the impact of that control on their agency and the level of their dependence on the state for the provision of basic necessities.Footnote 104 Furthermore, the claimant's responsibility for triggering a sanction may be sufficient for the Court to hold them, rather than the state, responsible for their predicament.Footnote 105 Nevertheless, it is the state that imposes sanctions, making it arguable that where such a ‘deliberate action of the state’ results in destitution then Article 3 has been violated.Footnote 106 If the Court can be so persuaded, then the argument that benefit sanctions amount to the menace of a penalty would be strengthened.

A core assumption of this argument is that the withdrawal of conditional welfare benefits is the kind of loss that may constitute a penalty. Dermine argues that the Commission's approach in X v the Netherlands was ‘outdated’ since it appeared to equate penalty with criminal sanction while the Court has since accepted that it includes ‘loss of a right, advantage, privilege or status’.Footnote 107 Derivative of the ILO's approach, this broad concept of a penalty includes financial loss.Footnote 108 Thus, insofar as it causes a loss, a sanction could amount to a penalty. However, as the Commission observed: ‘acceptance of a convenient employment is only a condition for granting unemployment benefits’.Footnote 109 This implies that sanctions do not cause a loss because the failure to satisfy the condition means that there is no initial entitlement to unemployment benefits. This lack of entitlement argument applies even if welfare benefits may be characterised as possessions and protected by Article 1 of Protocol No 1 of the ECHR.Footnote 110 Thus, conditional welfare schemes are an expression of responsibility and entitlement, rather than the ‘menace of a penalty’: ‘you must fulfil your work-based obligations if you are to be entitled to receive welfare benefits’.

It may be countered that the ‘punitive’ nature of the sanctions is revealed by their continued application, albeit at a reduced rate, even when the sanctioned individual's circumstances have changed, and they have been moved to a ‘no work-related requirements’ group. In such a case, the sanction no longer serves ‘to incentivise people into work’ since the obligation to seek work no longer applies.Footnote 111 The requisite nexus between the failure to fulfil the condition and the sanction is lost, disapplying the lack of entitlement argument.

Indeed, the fixed-term nature of the sanctions regime arguably implies a punitive rather than incentivising purpose. As such, the sanctions at least constitute ‘a risk comparable to the menace of a penalty’.Footnote 112 In Siliadin v France, the Court held that even though no actual penalty had been threatened, ‘she was in an equivalent situation in terms of the perceived seriousness of the threat’ that she might be arrested and deported.Footnote 113 For the Court it was sufficient that the fear was exploited to compel compliance. Arguably, then, the mischief is not the existence of a penalty per se, but the impact of a threat or menace on the voluntariness of any work obligation. However, the threat of sanctions is insufficient since: ‘not all work exacted from an individual under threat of a “penalty” is necessarily “forced or compulsory labour”’.Footnote 114 Beyond the menace of a penalty, forced labour requires that the work is involuntary.

(b) Voluntariness

It is arguable that, by applying for benefits and agreeing to comply with the claimant commitment, claimants voluntarily accept the work-related conditions to secure an entitlement to benefit payments. The Government does not force claimants to apply for benefits and is entitled to establish a conditional welfare scheme.Footnote 115 However, acts are involuntary when ‘compelled … by a sufficiently grave threat’ – voluntariness ‘is negated by compulsion’.Footnote 116 For example, the law allows contracts to be set aside where agreement has been secured through duress, even where the pressure to agree is not itself unlawful. For lawful act duress, an ‘unconscionable’ agreement may be sufficient to constitute ‘illegitimate pressure’, so vitiating consent to the contract.Footnote 117 While the claimant commitment is presented as an agreement, claimants had no real choice but to accept it given the alternative of complete ineligibility for welfare payments. The unconscionable compulsion that undermines choice and negates voluntariness comes from the risk of destitution in the absence of welfare support.

The relevance of choice was recognised in Siliadin. The fear of arrest and deportation, coupled with the vulnerability of the applicant as a minor living unlawfully in a foreign land, meant that ‘she was not given any choice’.Footnote 118 The applicant, however, did have a choice since she could have refused and accepted the risk of arrest. Threats ‘change the incentives … so that they influence but do not abolish choice’.Footnote 119 Nevertheless, the Court's point is that the choice was so unconscionable that the applicant could not have been expected to do anything but comply. As the Court stated: ‘it cannot be seriously maintained’ that the applicant ‘performed this work of her own free will’.Footnote 120 The lack of any ‘real’ choice rendered the performance involuntary.

For benefit claimants the choice is between agreeing to the claimant commitment and being ineligible for welfare payments. This is not a good choice, but arguably does not reach the level of unconscionability required to undermine its voluntariness. No one is compelled to apply for welfare benefits and individuals are free to find other means of support, even if this means relying on foodbanks and other forms of charity.Footnote 121 The choice may not be good, or fair, but remains sufficient for the claimant commitment to be considered voluntary. Furthermore, the need for benefits is economic, which does not equate to compulsion in the context of forced labour. As the ILO Director-General explained, forced labour ‘[does not] cover situations of pure economic necessity, as when a worker feels unable to leave a job because of the real or perceived absence of employment alternatives’.Footnote 122 If economic necessity is insufficient to negate the voluntariness of a work contract, then it should not be considered sufficient to negate the voluntariness of the claimant commitment. The Court has repeatedly rejected claims involving conditional welfare schemes and held that the obligation to seek employment as a condition of receiving welfare benefits is an insufficient compulsion to constitute forced labour.Footnote 123 The claimant commitment should, therefore, be seen as sufficiently voluntary in the context of Article 4(2).

While the claimant commitment may be voluntary, this does not mean that subsequent work-based obligations are automatically voluntary labour.Footnote 124 Following Van der Mussele, the claimant commitment represents a general ‘prior consent’, which might be vitiated by the particular circumstances of any consequential work-based obligation.Footnote 125 The Court in Van der Mussele relied on essentially three evaluative standards to assess the limits of a prior consent: the reasonableness of the work; its benefits; and the proportionality of its burdens. Footnote 126 The application of these standards depends on the particular circumstances, making it impossible to completely rule out a successful case. A distinction must be made between the scheme and its implementation. The possibility of inappropriate implementation in individual cases must leave open the possibility that the Court will find a violation of Article 4(2). The more pressing question is whether the scheme could amount to a violation as a matter of principle.Footnote 127

For Mantouvalou, the concern regarding the UK scheme is that it coerces people into precarious and exploitative work, such as zero-hours contract employment, that does little or nothing to alleviate poverty.Footnote 128 There is strong evidence that strict welfare conditionality reduces unemployment by transforming the unemployed poor into the working poor.Footnote 129 While not the sole concern with UK welfare policy, poverty arguably provides a bottom line measure of the (in)justice of that policy, particularly since poverty may be characterised as a human rights violation.Footnote 130 The human rights approach, which characterises poverty as a ‘moral catastrophe’, potentially provides ‘new mechanisms’ to tackle poverty and empowers the poor.Footnote 131

It may be asked whether the Court has a role in tackling poverty, particularly since the ECHR essentially focuses on civil and political rights. If, however, poverty is accepted as a human rights issue,Footnote 132 then as a human rights court, the Court should be concerned. The caveat is that the Court's concern must be constrained by its subject-matter jurisdiction. The ECHR, however, lacks any direct right to an adequate standard of living. Thus, if the Court is to legitimately address poverty as a human rights concern, recourse must be had to other provisions.

As discussed above, Article 3 provides only a very limited weapon against poverty and is best suited to addressing implementation issues, rather than the scheme itself.Footnote 133 By allowing the scheme itself to be challenged, Article 4 potentially provides an indirect mechanism for addressing the poverty trap of conditional benefits and precarious employment. For that potential to be realised, the Court must be persuaded that any requirement to accept zero-hours contract work would render the claimant commitment involuntary and constitute forced labour under the Van der Mussele standards. It is unlikely that the Court would be so persuaded.

Regarding the first standard, it should be noted that the work expectation under the UC scheme is limited to ‘reasonable employment’,Footnote 134 which includes zero-hours contract work.Footnote 135 As the DWP has clarified: ‘a Universal Credit claimant who is subject to all work related requirements can be expected to apply for a zero-hours contract job if it is considered suitable for their individual circumstances’.Footnote 136 Given the legality and prevalence of zero-hours contracts,Footnote 137 both in the UK and other European states parties to the ECHR,Footnote 138 the Court is also unlikely to consider such work to be unusual, or unreasonable. Personal circumstances may make such employment unreasonable, but claimants are entitled to refuse the employment if they have good reason.Footnote 139 Given the potentially negative impact of precarious employment on mental health and wellbeing, such work may not be suitable for everyone, particularly those who lack adequate social support or who have pre-existing mental health problems.Footnote 140 However, as the Taylor Report concluded, while working arrangements and protections could be improved, non-standard work is an important part of the UK labour market and can benefit both employers and employees.Footnote 141 Although the UK may be more permissive than many European countries,Footnote 142 the Taylor Report's findings support the proposition that the Court should not deem such work ‘unusual’ or unreasonable.

Regarding the second standard, claimants in low-paid jobs remain entitled to receive UC payments, which are reduced by 63 pence for every pound earned.Footnote 143 This should make the person financially better off. Even if Dwyer and Wright are correct that there may sometimes be a ‘perverse incentive to engage in limited hours of paid work’,Footnote 144 claimants should not be financially worse off given the benefit taper system. The availability of tapered UC payments suggests that claimants will benefit by working, even if they remain impoverished. Furthermore, even in zero-hours contract jobs, work provides the benefits of employment experience, the possibility of developing new skills and the opportunity to obtain references that may help to secure less precarious work. It is, therefore ‘plausible’ that ‘for certain groups of individuals facing a lacklustre labour market, the opportunity to work on a zero-hours contract represents a real benefit over the alternatives available’.Footnote 145 Furthermore, for the Supreme Court in Reilly, it was crucial that the purpose of the ‘work requirement’ was to improve the claimant's ‘employment prospects’. The likelihood of that ‘work requirement … achieving its purpose’ was irrelevant to the question of whether it constitutes forced labour.Footnote 146 Thus, evidence that the approach under the UK scheme ‘creates a new conditionality mismatch between strong sanctions (with associated ill-effects), unrealistic job expectations and unrealised employment outcomes’Footnote 147 warrants political challenge but does not impact on the compatibility of the scheme with Article 4.

Turning to the third standard. For work-related obligations to be disproportionate, they would need to impose excessive burdens that are ‘so considerable and unreasonable’ that the legitimacy of the underlying policy goals is undermined, so vitiating the consent embodied in the claimant commitment.Footnote 148 The UC scheme limits its work-based expectations to securing ‘reasonable employment’ within a 90-minute travel radius and a 35-hour week.Footnote 149 Welfare payments are also available to supplement low pay and help with the costs of working.Footnote 150 Furthermore, the availability of the ‘good reason’ excuse, if properly applied, should ensure that no one suffers a disproportionate burden under the UK scheme.

In CN and V v France, the Court interpreted the ‘notion of a “disproportionate burden”’ to include ‘the type and amount of work involved’. For the Court, ‘[t]hese factors help distinguish between “forced labour” and a helping hand which can reasonably be expected of other[s]’.Footnote 151 This approach is based on the finding in Van der Mussele, that the principles grounding the Article 4(3) exclusions form part of the definition of forced labour and create a context dependent de minimis gatekeeping condition. Footnote 152 For work to constitute forced labour, it must be something beyond what might ordinarily be expected as part of everyday life, whether as part of a family, part of a profession or part of the wider community. Thus, in Reilly, the Supreme Court applied this approach to argue that the ‘common features of life in democratic societies … do not represent the mischief at which the article is aimed’. Even where obligated ‘under menace of a penalty’,Footnote 153 work will not constitute forced labour under Article 4 unless it exceeds what might be considered ‘normal’ or ‘ordinary’ within the context of the obligations that arise as part of a social existence.Footnote 154

(c) Exploitation

Exploitation, as an essential, identifying characteristic,Footnote 155 lies at the ‘heart’ of forced labourFootnote 156 Exploitation, however, is a matter of degree, with no clear dividing line identifying the point at which it constitutes forced labour.Footnote 157 For the ILO, ‘there is a continuum’ between slavery and ‘freely chosen employment’.Footnote 158 Forced labour does not simply equate to ‘extremely poor’ or ‘sub-standard’ working conditions,Footnote 159 and requires more than an ‘infringement of labour legislation’. Since forced labour is a ‘severe violation of human rights’, the exploitation must sit towards the coercive ‘slavery and slavery-like’ end of the continuum.Footnote 160

In SM v Croatia, the Court held that ‘the notion of “forced or compulsory labour” … aims to protect against instances of serious exploitation, such as forced prostitution’.Footnote 161 By qualifying the degree of exploitation as ‘serious’, the judgment confirms that forced labour involves exploitation but that not all cases of labour exploitation amount to forced labour.Footnote 162 Thus, for a violation of Article 4(2), it must be shown, first, that the labour relationship is exploitative and, secondly, that the exploitation is ‘serious’.

Law is only concerned with wrongful exploitation, which is characterised by three core elements: a relationship with a power imbalance; the dominant party's abuse of the weaker party's vulnerability to exert control and secure an advantage;Footnote 163 and the conversion of the advantage into a gain that benefits the dominant party.Footnote 164 The wrong lies in the unfairness or injustice of the exploitative transaction,Footnote 165 which causes the weaker party to suffer an ‘undeserved’ loss.Footnote 166 Since an exploitative transaction may benefit both parties, the loss need only be relative insofar as any benefit provided to the weaker party is comparatively insufficient,Footnote 167 or inauthentic (a ‘false benefit’ that lacks the appropriate quality of a genuine gain – the exploiter owes the other party ‘something better’).Footnote 168

If the UK's conditional welfare scheme can be characterised as seriously exploitative, this is most likely to be where welfare claimants are pushed into accepting precarious employment involving zero-hours contracts or other non-standard work arrangements.Footnote 169 In such circumstances, there is a clear power imbalance between benefit claimants and the government. Claimants are made vulnerable through unemployment and a reliance on benefits to meet their basic needs. The government, backed by the legislative regime, has the legal power to insist on compliance with the claimant commitment and to withdraw benefits for unjustified non-compliance. Through this legal power, the government may use the claimant's vulnerability to exert sufficient control over them to secure their compliance with the claimant commitment.

In the absence of a good reason to refuse, benefit claimants may be required to accept zero-hours contract work even though they would not otherwise choose to work in such precarious employment. In pushing claimants to accept such work, the government gains a political benefit from any consequential reduction in the unemployment figures and welfare budget. Claimants may benefit from being employed, but the precarious nature of such employment that does little to relieve their financial insecurity, arguably means that any gain is insufficient, or of an inappropriate quality, to amount to a fair transaction. Thus, claimants at least suffer a relative loss from a transaction that may be characterised as unfairly exploitative. However, there are four reasons, other than politics and subsidiarity (see below), why it is unlikely that the Court would be persuaded that the exploitation is sufficiently serious to violate Article 4(2).

First, the poor quality of zero-hours contract work may support a claim of exploitation but is insufficient to amount to serious exploitation. More is required than that the work is precarious and leaves claimants in a position of financial insecurity.Footnote 170 This is illustrated by Chowdury, in which seasonal strawberry pickers ‘laboured under extreme physical conditions and for exhaustingly long working hours and were subjected to constant humiliation’.Footnote 171 However, this was insufficient to constitute serious exploitation without the additional threats posed by the armed supervision, the withholding of wages, the desperate living conditions and the vulnerability of the workers as ‘irregular migrants’ facing the constant threat of arrest and deportation.Footnote 172

Secondly, the degree of control exerted over claimants is insufficient to amount to serious exploitation, which requires that the dominant party of an ‘oppressive’ relationshipFootnote 173 treats the vulnerable party ‘as an object under his or her control’.Footnote 174 The UK scheme involves the negotiated agreement of the claimant commitment and allows claimants, who have good reason, to excuse themselves from a work-related responsibility. Both factors mitigate the coercive nature of the sanctions under the scheme. The threat of the sanction may function similarly to the threat of a penalty, but there is no legal compulsion to accept a job. While claimants lose any entitlement to the standard welfare allowance for the duration of the sanction, there is no legal offence associated with the failure to comply with the claimant commitment. Claimants are also free to stop claiming benefits and accept alternative offers of support or employment if available.Footnote 175 Thus, claimants are neither ‘under compulsion and manipulation at all times’,Footnote 176 nor ‘chained without physical chains’.Footnote 177 Claimants are not a ‘ruthlessly exploited … commodity’ lacking any ‘true freedom of choice’,Footnote 178 nor is their freedom ‘significantly curtailed’ through intimidation, mistreatment or physical violence.Footnote 179 To the contrary, claimants retain a sufficient degree of control to prevent the scheme amounting to a violation of Article 4(2).Footnote 180

Furthermore, since ‘pure economic necessity’ is not a relevant form of coercion,Footnote 181 the economic threat posed by the sanction is arguably exploitative, but not seriously exploitative. As the Supreme Court held: ‘The provision of a conditional benefit … comes nowhere close to the type of exploitative conduct at which article 4 is aimed’.Footnote 182 The sanctions are currently tougher than in Reilly, but it remains unlikely that they would support a claim that the scheme is seriously exploitative, particularly since higher-level sanctions were reduced from 1095 to 182 days.Footnote 183

Thirdly, by encouraging employment and reducing reliance on welfare, the scheme is intended to benefit both the unemployed and the wider community. In the zero-hours contract case, the benefit may be unequal and there may be better schemes available. However, the beneficial intention remains, which provides at least some justification for the schemeFootnote 184 and makes it unlikely that a court would consider that it constitutes serious exploitation. This argument is unaffected by any objection that the scheme may be ineffective in achieving the benefits since ‘the meaning of article 4 cannot depend on the degree of likelihood of the condition achieving its purpose’.Footnote 185

Fourthly, the nature of the conditional welfare scheme is such that any reasonable work requirement amounts to a normal civic obligation or is at least consistent with the general underlying principle of the Article 4(3) exclusions.Footnote 186 Work that falls directly under Article 4(3), or within its general underlying principles, lies outside the mischief targeted by Article 4 and would not be considered seriously exploitative by a court.

(d) Normal civic obligations

Under Article 4(3), normal civic obligations are excluded from the prohibition of forced labour. In Van der Mussele, the Court expanded the relevance of the exclusion by holding that the underlying principles of ‘general interest, social solidarity and what is in the normal course of affairs’ help to define the extent of the concept of forced labour.Footnote 187 Thus, there is no need to show that any required labour is a normal civic obligation provided it is consistent with those underlying principles and so forms part of the ‘normal’ or ‘common features of life in democratic societies’.Footnote 188 However, direct appeal to the Article 4(3)(d) exclusion is not precluded.

Normal civic obligations are those duties imposed by the government on citizens arising from the widely accepted ‘moral conviction’ that everyone should contribute to the community's common goals.Footnote 189 Based on what might be reasonably, properly or fairly expected of the good citizen (itself a politically contested notion),Footnote 190 the concept is vague and underdetermined by existing case law.Footnote 191 Beyond specific examples, such as the duty to serve on a jury,Footnote 192 the case law does, however, provide insights into the scope of the concept and the criteria that ‘restrict the competence of government to shape civic duties’.Footnote 193

For the Human Rights Committee in Faure, normal civic obligations must be ‘provided for by law in order to serve a legitimate purpose’ and neither ‘exceptional’ nor ‘punitive’ in nature.Footnote 194 In applying these conditions, it should be noted that the non-punitive condition applies to the nature of the work and not the use of sanctions.Footnote 195 The UK scheme is established under a legislative framework with the legitimate aims of encouraging employment and reducing the burden of unemployment on the state and its welfare budget.Footnote 196 Furthermore, the imposition of work obligations as a condition for receiving benefit payments is not exceptional. Such schemes are commonplace in contemporary democracies and have their roots in historical poor laws that implemented duty to work policies and preserved ‘the necessary motivation for employment’ by providing only limited relief.Footnote 197

The duty to work may be derived from the principles of general interest and social solidarity. Consistent with the UK Government's policy emphasis on social responsibility,Footnote 198 the idea is that working contributes to the economy and, through taxes, to public funds that provide welfare support. Working is, therefore, in the general interest of the state and its citizens. Since all citizens benefit from the support or security provided by a welfare system, they should do what they can to make a fair contribution to the state's economy and funds through working. Benefit claimants who could work but choose not to are free riders, exploiting the hard work of others. Free riders violate the norm of fairness because they take the benefit of other people's work without sharing the burden.Footnote 199

Social solidarity requires that all citizens fulfil their reciprocal obligations to justify the benefits that flow from being part of an organised community. Indeed, behavioural experiments suggest that ‘individuals are conditionally generous, willing to share with others if recipients are behaving in a fair manner’.Footnote 200 It is, therefore, not unreasonableFootnote 201 for a community to implement laws that secure the fulfilment of those obligations to ensure that the benefits and burdens of social existence are distributed fairly or proportionately.Footnote 202 To be consistent with normal civic obligations, or the underlying principle of social solidarity, any work requirement must be proportionate to the policy goals.Footnote 203

Consider, for example, Steindel v Germany, which concerned a private medical practitioner's obligation to provide public emergency services.Footnote 204 The Court held that this was a normal civic obligation since it was ‘founded on a concept of professional and civil solidarity’ and imposed a burden that was proportionate to the goal of managing medical emergencies. The burden of providing emergency services for six days every three months left ‘ample time’ for the applicant's private practice and was balanced by the benefits: the work was remunerated and ‘in principle’ meant that the applicant was not obliged to be available to his patients outside normal consultation hours.

Given that the UK scheme allows a person to be excused for ‘good reason’ and limits the hours and travel expectations of any work-related requirements, the burden should be characterised as proportionate. While the financial insecurity of zero-hours contract employment may factor into the calculation of proportionality, arguably it would be insufficient to make the obligation disproportionate given that claimants remain entitled to welfare payments to supplement low pay,Footnote 205 which mitigates that insecurity.Footnote 206 Thus, the UK scheme is arguably compliant with Article 4(2), although this does not preclude the possibility that Article 4(2) may be violated in specific cases where the scheme has been improperly implemented.

The strongest counterargument to the claim of proportionality begins with the premise that a cooperative social scheme can only generate a reciprocal duty to work where the outcome is a fair distribution of both benefits and burdens. For a distributively unjust scheme, the duty is undermined by the disjunction between burden and benefit.Footnote 207 Along with reducing unemployment, the UK scheme is also intended to ‘mak[e] sure work pays’ and to ‘reduce in-work poverty’.Footnote 208 While paid employment can provide the means to escape poverty, this is unlikely to be the case for ‘low paid, menial and insecure work’, exemplified by precarious zero-hours contract work, which may contrarily ‘harm family life and wellbeing’, ‘trapp[ing]’ individuals ‘in a cycle of “poor work” and worklessness’.Footnote 209 Such employment fails to provide the intended benefits of work as ‘the best form of welfare’.Footnote 210 Consequentially, the burden imposed by requiring claimants to accept such work exceeds the benefits and so may be characterised as disproportionate.

This counterargument relies on a point of comparison between employment and unemployment that takes welfare payments as the baseline. However, because welfare payments are part of the scheme and conditional on compliance with any reasonable work-related obligations imposed under the scheme, they should be excluded from the baseline position. If welfare payments are properly included in the benefit side of the benefit/burden proportionality argument, particularly since the scheme provides for in-work benefits, then even an obligation to accept zero-hours contract work is a proportionate burden. The proportionality of the UK programme is reinforced by the right to refuse employment where the claimant has ‘good reason’ as well as the right to hardship payments in the event of sanctions being applied.Footnote 211 As such, the work-related requirements of the UK's conditional welfare scheme may be characterised as normal civic obligations, or at least as consistent with the underlying principles of Article 4(3). Indeed, ‘work as a citizenship duty’ has become such a firmly embedded social norm that it has even been characterised as an ‘unquestionable’ obligation,Footnote 212

The preceding arguments are essentially contingent on competing views of what is distributively fair, pitting the UK Government's reliance on a desert-based policy approach against other, more needs-based, measures of justice. The question then is whether the courts should, or would, be willing to choose between these competing views. This will be addressed in the next section.

3. Politics, subsidiarity, and the UK's conditional welfare scheme

This paper has examined the claim that the UK scheme violates Article 4(2) by compelling claimants to accept precarious employment such as zero-hours contract work. For each of the four interrelated features that characterise forced labour, it was argued that the claim may be both plausibly defended and opposed. However, the weight of the arguments leans towards the conclusion that the UK scheme does not violate Article 4(2). This conclusion is supported by the politics of judicial decision-making, both at European and domestic levels.

Since all conditional welfare cases to reach Strasbourg have been rejected as inadmissible, the historical jurisprudence provides a strong initial barrier. This is supported domestically by the Supreme Court's approach in Reilly.Footnote 213 Furthermore, the admissibility decision can be used to strategically handle cases that might otherwise exacerbate the ongoing ‘tensions between the UK and Strasbourg’.Footnote 214 Such a politically tactical approach would enhance the barrier, making it more difficult to surmount. However, given that the ECHR is a ‘living instrument’,Footnote 215 that the sanctions are notably tough, and that zero-hours contract work is exploitatively precarious, it remains possible that the Court, like the Human Rights Committee in Faure, would accept as admissible the claim that the UK scheme violates Article 4(2).

Even if a case survives the admissibility decision, the principle of subsidiarityFootnote 216 should direct the Court towards the conclusion that the scheme does not violate Article 4(2). The principle of subsidiarity,Footnote 217 which has been enshrined in the Convention preamble by Protocol 15, guides the division of a shared responsibility for protecting the Convention rights between the Court and the member states.Footnote 218 Under the principle, member states have ‘primary responsibility’, with the Court having a supervisory role that requires due respect for the margin of appreciation afforded member states,Footnote 219 who ‘remain best placed’ to determine whether policies, laws and other measures adequately protect the Convention rights.Footnote 220 Where a claim essentially depends on contested political views of the way society should function, then the Court should defer to the ‘democratically more appropriate’ national policymakers by affording the state its due margin of appreciation, which serves to ‘[operationalise] normative subsidiarity’.Footnote 221

As a device for implementing subsidiarity, the margin of appreciation is particularly apposite to the question of proportionality. Since conditional welfare schemes are a matter of general socio-economic policy, the Court should afford the state a wide margin of appreciation. As observed in SAS v France, ‘in matters of general policy, on which opinions within a democratic society may reasonably differ widely, the role of the domestic policy-maker should be given special weight’.Footnote 222 Whether a conditional welfare scheme imposes a proportionate burden on the benefit claimants engages with the politically contested determination of what is fair in a distributive sense. Since opinions may reasonably differ widely on issues of distributive justice, the ‘special weight’ afforded domestic policymakers should tilt the balance in favour of the conclusion that the UK scheme does not violate Article 4(2). Given that exploitation is a continuum, the margin of appreciation should similarly be relevant to determining that the exploitative nature of the UK scheme does not reach the level of seriousness required to conclude that it amounts to forced labour.

At the procedural level of a ‘process-based review’,Footnote 223 the Court should accept that it is reasonable for domestic policymakers to rely on its previously settled jurisprudence when considering whether the scheme is likely to violate Article 4(2). While the Court might criticise UK policymakers for failing to explicitly consider the four elements relevant to the characterisation of work as ‘forced or compulsory’, it may deem as sufficient the Parliamentary debates and the legislative scrutiny of the Welfare Reform Bill. In this regard, the UK's Joint Committee on Human Rights believed that any human rights issues concerned Article 3 rather than Article 4.Footnote 224

The position of the UK scheme is strengthened by the recognition that similar, if less stringent, schemes have been implemented by successive UK governments and are prevalent in other European countries.Footnote 225 Furthermore, given the precedent of the Supreme Court decision in Reilly, it seems likely that domestic courts would accept that the UK scheme is compliant with Article 4(2). Given that the Court must have ‘strong reasons to substitute its own view for that of the domestic courts’,Footnote 226 and that the Human Rights Act 1998 makes the UK ‘a model in terms of subsidiarity’,Footnote 227 the Court should decide that the UK scheme does not violate Article 4(2).

The currently strained relationship between the UK and the Court is also a relevant factor. Given the backlash against the judicial activism that had ‘progressively expand[ed] the scope of the Convention’ since the 1980s,Footnote 228 there is little doubt that if the Strasbourg judges ‘push matters too far’ then they ‘risk challenges to their Court's authority’.Footnote 229 The UK backlash was particularly ‘striking’ and culminated in the ‘political uproar’ over what was characterised as the Court's antidemocratic interference in the ‘deeply polarized political arena’ of prisoners’ rights.Footnote 230 As a consequence, the Court now appears to be exercising more judicial restraint through ‘a notion of enhanced subsidiarity’ and a ‘stronger emphasis on the margin of appreciation doctrine’, making it more deferential to member states, particularly the UK.Footnote 231 Indeed, an empirical analysis of a dataset of rulings up to 2019 showed that the Court has been more deferential to consolidated democracies, with the greatest deference afforded to the UK, its strongest critic.Footnote 232 Therefore, given the Court's reliance on the ‘co-operation and good faith’ of its member states ‘to preserve its own future authority’,Footnote 233 the Court should, and most likely would, defer to the policymakers and hold that the UK scheme does not violate Article 4(2).

It has been argued that the Court would accept that conditional welfare is a political issue within the state's wide margin of appreciation. This raises the question of when it may be appropriate for judicial intervention in matters of social welfare policy. The Human Rights Act 1998 situates ‘the rights-based aspects of adjudication’ within the confines of a constitution characterised by the separation of powers and Parliamentary supremacy.Footnote 234 The implications of this political constitutionalism,Footnote 235 which limits the scope for judicial intervention, was apparent in the judgment of the Supreme Court in R (on the application of SC) v Secretary of State for Work and Pensions.Footnote 236

The case concerned the ‘two child limit’ on child tax credit introduced by the Welfare Reform and Work Act 2016, section 13. The issue was whether the limit amounted to discrimination against women as lone parents and against children living in larger households, contrary to Article 14 in conjunction with Article 8 of the ECHR, or Article 1 of the First Protocol. Giving the court's judgment, Lord Reed acknowledged that the judiciary should afford policymakers ‘a high level of respect … in the field of economic or social policy’, but that respect must be tempered by ‘the need for close scrutiny’ to ensure that differential treatment does not amount to ‘unjustifiable discrimination’ on a ‘suspect ground’.Footnote 237 This required a ‘nuanced approach’, which generally demanded a ‘low intensity of review’ based on the ‘manifestly without reasonable foundation’ test. However, where cases involved discrimination on ‘suspect’ grounds, the review should more stringently require that ‘weighty reasons’ have been shown to justify different treatment.Footnote 238 Despite this distinction, the courts’ role was to determine whether the legislated policy ‘pursues a legitimate aim’ and relies on reasonably proportionate means to achieve that aim.Footnote 239

In applying such an approach, Lord Reed noted that proportionality was ‘a question of intense political controversy’, which could not be resolved by legal reasoning based on legal standards. Rather it could ‘only be determined … through a political process which can take account of the values and views of all sections of society’. Given the strong ‘democratic credentials of the measure’, there was no basis for the courts to ‘properly overturn Parliament's judgment’ that the legislation was ‘fair and affordable’.Footnote 240 This deference to the democratic process limits judicial scrutiny to the procedural aspect of policymaking.Footnote 241 It reflects a reluctance to ‘interrogate or challenge’ more substantive issues, such as the prejudicial and stereotypical assumptions concerning ‘personal responsibility and welfare dependency’ that underpin current welfare policies and particularly disadvantage lone mothers.Footnote 242

The Supreme Court's highly restrictive approach represents an extreme form of political constitutionalism that arguably gives too much respect to the democratic process and ‘undermines the potential for judicial review and rights jurisprudence to stimulate a culture of good governance’.Footnote 243 Nevertheless, and regardless of the policy's impact on equality,Footnote 244 financial insecurity or public health,Footnote 245 the Supreme Court's unanimous judgment makes it clear that substantive issues of distributive justice, such as whether a policy is ‘fair, economically desirable and socially acceptable’, are matters of politics not law.Footnote 246 Although the courts have arguably become too deferential to the democratic process, the judgment appropriately recognises that it is not the court's place to resolve politically contentious issues of distributive justice, which should be determined in political rather than legal fora.

Conclusion

This paper considered whether the UK's conditional welfare scheme violates Article 4(2) of the ECHR. The scheme was analysed under each of the four interrelated elements that define the meaning and extent of the concept of forced labour. Plausible arguments were acknowledged both for and against the claim that the scheme violates Article 4(2). The arguments for the claim were most persuasive in relation to the ‘menace of a penalty’ element. For voluntariness, exploitation and normal civic obligations, the arguments on each side were more equivocal, but those against the claim were perhaps more persuasive. Particularly, while the UK scheme may be characterised as unfairly exploitative, the exploitation arguably fails to reach the requisite level of ‘serious exploitation’ to be characterised as forced labour.

If a case were brought before the Court today it may survive the admissibility hearing and proceed to a hearing on the merits. However, even if the Court was persuaded to move past its previous jurisprudence, which has seen all similar cases rejected as inadmissible, the current emphasis on the principle of subsidiarity means that the claim should, and most likely would, fail. The arguments on either side rely on different understandings of the demands of distributive justice, which is a matter for political debate rather than judicial determination. As such, the Court should defer to domestic policymakers and any challenges to the scheme itself should be political, rather than judicial. It remains possible that a successful claim might arise in cases where the scheme has been improperly implemented, but these should be dealt with by the national courts under the legislative framework of the scheme. There may be a greater likelihood of success for claims brought under Article 3 of the ECHR, but again this depends on a failure of implementation rather than the injustice of the scheme itself. When challenging conditional welfare schemes, the role for Article 4, and for legal human rights more generally, is very limited. The injustice of the UK scheme is essentially a matter of politics and should be challenged in the political arena rather than the judicial arena of human rights litigation.

References

1 L Medland et al The ‘Future of Work?’ A Call for the Recognition of Continuities in Challenges for Conceptualising Work and its Regulation (Bristol Law Research Paper Series No 001, 2019) p 1, available at http://www.bristol.ac.uk/law/research/legal-research-papers/.

2 Office for National Statistics ‘Unemployment rate (aged 16 and over, seasonally adjusted): %’ (19 July 2022), available at https://www.ons.gov.uk/employmentandlabourmarket/peoplenotinwork/unemployment/timeseries/mgsx/lms.

3 DNF Bell and DG Blanchflower What Should be Done about Rising Unemployment in the UK? (IZA-Institute of Labor Economics Discussion Papers No 4040, 2009) pp 14–17, available at https://www.iza.org/publications/dp/4040/what-should-be-done-about-rising-unemployment-in-the-uk.

4 Dean, HThe ethics of welfare-to-work’ (2007) 35 Policy & Politics 573CrossRefGoogle Scholar at 574.

5 Mantouvalou, VWelfare-to-work, structural injustice and human rights’ (2020) 83 Modern Law Review 929CrossRefGoogle Scholar at 930 and 954.

6 Ibid, at 946.

7 Ibid, at 948. See also Mantouvalou, VStructural injustice and the human rights of workers’ (2020) 73 Current Legal Problems 59Google Scholar at 77.

8 Dermine, EActivation policies for the unemployed and the international human rights case law on the prohibition of forced labour’ (2013) 5 European Journal of Human Rights 746Google Scholar at 775. See also E Dermine ‘Limitation of welfare to work: the prohibition of forced labour and the right to freely chosen work’ in A Eleveld et al (eds) Welfare to Work in Contemporary European Welfare States: Legal Social and Philosophical Perspectives on Justice and Domination (Bristol: Policy Press, ebook edn, 2020) loc 1501.

9 N Timmins et al Jobs and Benefits: The Covid-19 Challenge (Institute for Government and the Social Security Advisory Committee, March 2021) p 32; Smith, JCovid-19, Brexit and the United Kingdom – a year of uncertainty’ (2021) 110 The Round Table 62CrossRefGoogle Scholar at 73.

10 D Harari et al Rising Cost of Living in the UK (House of Commons Library Briefing Paper No 9428, 21 July 2022).

11 See A Eleveld et al ‘Welfare to work, social injustice and domination: an introduction to interdisciplinary normative perspectives on welfare policies’ and A Eleveld et al ‘The prohibition of forced labour and the right to freely chosen work: a comparison of Denmark, the Netherlands and the UK’ both in Eleveld et al (eds), above n 8, at loc 294 and loc 2536 respectively.

12 Mantouvalou, VWelfare-to-work, zero-hours contracts and human rights’ (2022) 13 European Labour Law Journal 431CrossRefGoogle Scholar at 431–432, 441.

13 Mantouvalou, above n 5, at 934, 937–940.

14 See eg H Dean ‘Social policy and human rights: re-thinking the engagement’ (2007) 7 Social Policy & Society 1; S Gloppen ‘Public interest litigation, social rights and social policy’ in A Dani and A de Haan (eds) Inclusive States: Social Policy and Structural Inequalities (Washington DC, The World Bank, 2008) p 343; M Langford ‘Critiques of human rights’ (2018) 14 Annual Review of Law and Social Science 69; M Goldmann Contesting Austerity: Genealogies of Human Rights Discourse (MPIL Research Paper Series No 2020-09, 2020), available at https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=3561660; Eleveld et al ‘Welfare to work…’, above n 11, at loc 320.

15 For the sake of clarity, and because the core elements of the UC scheme apply across the UK, the discussion is based on the scheme as applied in England and Wales. See further G McKeever ‘Legislative scrutiny, co-ordination and the Social Security Advisory Committee: from system coherence to Scottish devolution’ (2016) 23 Journal of Social Security Law 126; A Macklay ‘Social security powers in the UK’ (House of Commons Library Briefing Paper No 9048, 9 November 2020); T Mullen ‘Devolution of social security’ (2016) 16 Edinburgh Law Review 382.

16 Approximately 90% of single parents in the UK are women: DA and Others v Secretary of State for Work and Pensions [2019] UKSC 21, [22]. See also ONS Families and Households (9 March 2022), available at https://www.ons.gov.uk/peoplepopulationandcommunity/birthsdeathsandmarriages/families/datasets/familiesandhouseholdsfamiliesandhouseholds. The OMS data set estimates about 85% of single parents are women.

17 See R Cain ‘Responsibilising recovery: lone and low-paid parents, Universal Credit and the gendered contradictions of UK welfare reform’ (2016) 11 British Politics 488 at 500. See also M Carey and S Bell ‘Universal Credit, lone mothers and poverty: some ethical challenges for social work with children and families’ (2022) 16 Ethics and Social Welfare 3; M Campbell ‘The austerity of lone motherhood: discrimination law and benefit reform’ (2021) 41 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 1197.

18 Campbell, ibid.

19 See Zarb Adami v Malta [2006] ECHR 17209/02; Karlheinz Schmidt v Germany [1994] ECHR 13580/88 (ECHR 18 July 1994).

20 A Zaidi Welfare-to-Work Programmes in the UK and Lessons for Other Countries (European Centre for Social Welfare Policy and Research Policy Brief 10, October 2009) p 1, available at https://www.euro.centre.org/publications/detail/384.

21 M Quaid Workfare: Why Good Social Policy Ideas Go Bad (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2002) pp 9, 19–20.

22 M Ahluwalia and J Tomlinson ‘Benefit sanctions, illegality and administrative justice: after judicial review?’ (2018) 23 Judicial Review 225.

23 Welfare Reform Act 2012, ss 3(1)(a), 4(1)(e).

24 Ibid, s 14.

25 Ibid, ss 19–22.

26 Ibid, s 13.

27 Ibid, s 18(2).

28 R (on the application of Reilly and Another) v Secretary of State for Work and Pensions [2013] UKSC 68, [65].

29 DWP ‘Advice for decision making: staff guide’ (2013 as updated to 24 November 2022) para J3001, available at https://www.gov.uk/government/publications/advice-for-decision-making-staff-guide.

30 Ibid, at J3005.

31 Ibid, at J3007.

32 Ibid, at J3253.

33 P Dwyer ‘Questions of conduct and social justice: the ethics of welfare conditionality within UK social security’ in Eleveld et al (eds), above n 8, at loc 4076, 4340. See also loc 4320.

34 DWP, above n 29, at K2053.

35 Zero-hours contracts refer to a range of varied contractual arrangements ‘in which workers are not guaranteed any hours of work in a particular period’: A Adams and J Prassl Zero-Hours Work in the United Kingdom (International Labour Office Conditions of Work and Employment Series No 101, 2018) at 1, available at https://www.ilo.org/wcmsp5/groups/public/---ed_protect/---protrav/---travail/documents/publication/wcms_624965.pdf.

36 DWP response to Freedom of Information request from Adam Wilson (20 January 2015), available at https://www.whatdotheyknow.com/request/243744/response/607340/attach/html/2/FOI%205325%20reply.pdf.html. See further, text at n 121.

37 R Mason ‘Jobseekers being forced into zero-hours roles’ (The Guardian, 5 May 2014), available at https://www.theguardian.com/uk-news/2014/may/05/jobseekers-zero-hours-contracts.

38 ONS ‘EMP17: People in employment on zero-hours contracts’ (14 February 2023), available at https://www.ons.gov.uk/employmentandlabourmarket/peopleinwork/employmentandemployeetypes/datasets/emp17peopleinemploymentonzerohourscontracts.

39 D Kamerāde and L Scullion ‘Welcome to Britain: a land where jobs may be plentiful but are more and more precarious’ (The Conversation, 21 November 2017), available at https://theconversation.com/welcome-to-britain-a-land-where-jobs-may-be-plentiful-but-are-more-and-more-precarious-87423.

40 S Wright and P Dwyer ‘In-work Universal Credit: claimant experiences of conditionality mismatches and counterproductive benefit sanctions’ (2022) 51 Journal of Social Policy 20 at 28. See also Welfare Conditionality Project Final Findings: Universal Credit (2018) p 8 available at www.welfareconditionality.ac.uk.

41 Wright and Dwyer, ibid, at 27. See also Dwyer, above n 33, at loc 4320.

42 DWP, above n 29 at K1013–1016.

43 Ibid, at K2004-2009. Reasonableness refers to the standard of the objective reasonable person in the claimant's ‘particular circumstances’ (K2021–2022). Individual circumstances refer to the claimants ‘complex needs’ such as issues with literacy, numeracy, language, domestic circumstances, emergencies, and mental health (K2053).

44 Ibid, at J3002; Welfare Reform Act 2012, ss 26, 27.

45 Universal Credit Regulations 2013, SI 2013/376, reg 111(1).

46 Ibid, reg 102. The original duration of 1095 days for repeat failures was reduced to 182 days by the Jobseeker's Allowance and Universal Credit (Higher-Level Sanctions) (Amendment) Regulations 2019, SI 2019/1357, reg 3.

47 Welfare Reform Act 2012, s 29. Universal Credit Regulations 2013, SI 2013/376, regs 116, 119.

48 Department for Work and Pensions 21st Century Welfare Cm 7913, July 2010, p 2.

49 Department for Work and Pensions Universal Credit: Welfare that Works Cm7957, Nov 2010, pp 6, 11.

50 Ibid, pp 6, 28.

51 I Newman ‘Work as a route out of poverty: a critical evaluation of the UK welfare to work policy’ (2011) 32 Policy Studies 91 at 94.

52 C Grover ‘Violent proletarianization: social murder, the reserve army of labour and social security ‘austerity’ in Britain’ (2019) 39 Critical Social Policy 335 at 336.

53 Eleveld et al ‘Welfare to work…’, above n 11, at loc 294.

54 P Dwyer ‘Creeping conditionality in the UK: from welfare rights to conditional entitlements?’ (2004) 29(2) Canadian Journal of Sociology 265; D Edmiston ‘Welfare, austerity and social citizenship in the UK’ (2017) 16 Social Policy & Society 261 at 262.

55 Wright and Dwyer, above n 40, at 22.

56 Mantouvalou, above n 5, at 929.

57 Edmiston, above n 54, at 263, 265–266. See also Cain, above n 17; K Reeve ‘Welfare conditionality, benefit sanctions and homelessness in the UK: ending the “something for nothing culture” or punishing the poor?’ (2017) 25 Social Justice 65; B Watts et al Welfare Sanctions and Conditionality in the UK (Joseph Rowntree Foundation, 2014), available at https://www.jrf.org.uk/report/welfare-sanctions-and-conditionality-uk.

58 Grover, above n 52, at 338–339.

59 Destitution may be defined as the inability to secure ‘adequate accommodation’ or the inability to meet ‘essential living needs’: Immigration and Asylum Act 1999, s 95(3). A wider conception suggests that individuals are destitute if they ‘can only access essential needs through charitable or family support’: G McKeever and T Walsh ‘The moral hazard of conditionality: restoring the integrity of social security law’ (2020) 5 Australian Journal of Social Issues 73 at 75.

60 J Redman, ‘“Chatting shit” in the jobcentre: navigating workfare policy at the street-level’ (2021) Work, Employment and Society 1 at 14–16. See also Grover, above n 52, at 348.

61 See E Williams ‘Punitive welfare reform and claimant mental health: the impact of benefit sanctions on anxiety and depression’ (2021) 55 Social Policy & Administration 157. See also National Audit Office Benefit Sanctions HC 628, 30 November 2016, para 3.17.

62 Decisions to apply a sanction rose from 438 in May 2016 to a pre-Covid peak of 22,567 in July 2019. Post-Covid, rates have exceeded pre-Covid levels with 37,701 decisions in December 2021 and 38, 244 in January 2022. In January 2022, of approximately 2 million claimants who could be sanctioned, there were 75,059 (3.74%) affected by sanctions. In February 2022, the figure was similar with 78,762 (3.90%) affected by sanctions: Department of Work & Pensions Benefit Sanctions Statistics to January 2022 (experimental) (17 May 2022), tables 1.1, and 2.1, available at https://www.gov.uk/government/collections/jobseekers-allowance-sanctions.

63 Welfare Conditionality Project Final Findings Report (2018) pp 23–24, available at www.welfareconditionality.ac.uk.

64 See S Wright et al ‘Punitive benefit sanctions, welfare conditionality, and the social abuse of unemployed people in Britain: transforming claimants into offenders?’ (2020) 54 Social Policy & Administration 278 at 284–292.

65 Department for Work and Pensions 21st Century Welfare Cm 7913, July 2010, p 5.

66 Newman, above n 51, at 103–104; Dean, above n 4, at 585.

67 Welfare Conditionality Project, above n 40, pp 6, 8–10.

68 McKeever and Walsh, above n 59, at 83.

69 Arts 2 (right to life) and 8 (right to private and family life) may also be relevant: C O'Cinneide ‘A modest proposal: destitution, state responsibility and the European Convention on Human Rights’ (2008) European Human Rights Law Review 583 at 584.

70 Mantouvalou, above n 5, at 950–951. See also O'Cinneide, ibid, at 587–590; L Lavrysen ‘Poverty and human rights: a European perspective’ in E Brems et al (eds) Human Rights and Development: Legal Perspectives from and for Ethiopia (Leiden: Brill, 2015) p 303 at pp 308–309.

71 M Adler Cruel, Inhuman or Degrading Treatment? Benefit Sanctions in the UK (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2018); McKeever and Walsh, above n 59, at 82.

72 M Simpson ‘“Designed to reduce people to complete destitution”: human dignity in the active welfare state’ (2015) European Human Rights Law Review 66 at 76–77; Mantouvalou, above n 5, at 951. The difficulty of showing a violation of Art 3 is discussed further at n 99.

73 See Reilly, above n 28, at [79]. See also Determinations by Social Security Commissioner ‘Application for leave to appeal on a question of law from the decision of an appeal tribunal’, CSJSA/495/2007, May QC, Commissioner.

74 X v the Netherlands [1976] European Commission 7602/02; Talmon v the Netherlands [1997] European Commission 30300/96; Schuitemaker v the Netherlands [2010] ECHR 15906/08.

75 Reilly, above n 28, at [18], [21], [27].

76 Reilly, above n 28, at [89]–[90], per Lords Neuberger and Toulson. See also Determinations by Social Security Commissioner, above n 73.

77 Schuitemaker, above n 74.

78 Dermine, above n 8, at 772.

79 Tyrer v the United Kingdom [1978] ECHR 5856/72 at [31]; F Dorssemont ‘The European Convention on Human Rights as a fountain of labour rights’ in JR Bellace and B ter Haar (eds) Research Handbook on Labour, Business and Human Rights Law (Cheltenham: Edward Elgar, 2019) p 314 at p 317.

80 Dermine, above n 8, at 771.

81 UN Human Rights Committee, Communication No 1036/2001 (UN Doc CCPR/C/85/D/1036/2001, 2005) at [7.3].

82 Ibid, at [6.3].

83 See Svinarenko and Slyadnev v Russia [2014] ECHR 32541/08; 43441/08 at [70], [132].

84 ILO Forced Labour Convention, 1930 (No 29), Art 2; Van der Mussele v Belgium [19830 ECHR 8919/80 at [32]; Siliadin v France [2005] ECHR 73316/01 at [115]–[117]; CN and V v France [2012] ECHR 67724/09 at [71].

85 SM v Croatia [2020] ECHR 60561/14 at [300]. See also Reilly, above n 28, at [81], [89].

86 Oxford English Dictionary Online (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2021), available at http://www.oed.com/viewdictionaryentry/Entry/139990.

87 Van der Mussele, above n 84, at [35].

88 Welfare Reform Act 2012, ss 26, 27.

89 J Hyman ‘Voluntariness and intention’ (2016) 7 Jurisprudence 692 at 695.

90 See Eleveld et al ‘The prohibition of forced labour…’, above n 11, at loc 2636–2643. The cases relied on are the Danish Supreme Court Judgment U 2006.77H and a 2010 Dutch Central Appeals Tribunal (no citation provided).

91 Cavendish Square Holding BV v Talal El Makdessi; ParkingEye Ltd v Beavis [2015] UKSC 67.

92 Ibid, at [99]–[100] per Lords Neuberger and Sumption (Lord Carnwath agreeing), [152] per Lord Mance, and [255] per Lord Hodge.

93 DR Fletcher and S Wright ‘A hand up or a slap down? Criminalising benefit claimants in Britain via strategies of surveillance, sanctions and deterrence’ (2018) 38 Critical Social Policy 323 at 333–334. See also Wright and Dwyer, above n 40, at 25–26.

94 House of Commons Work and Pensions Committee Benefit Sanctions Nineteenth Report of Session 2017–19, HC 955, 31 October 2018, p 19, available at https://publications.parliament.uk/pa/cm201719/cmselect/cmworpen/955/955.pdf.

95 See Department of Work and Pensions The Jobcentre Plus Offer: Final Evaluation Report (2013) p 162.

96 Fletcher and Wright, above n 93, at 334.

97 S Clarke ‘Do benefit sanctions breach Article 3 ECHR?’ Public Law Project Blog (29 May 2019), available at https://publiclawproject.org.uk/uncategorized/do-benefit-sanctions-breach-article-3-echr/.

98 R v Secretary of State for the Home Department, ex p Adam, Limbuela, and Tesema [2005] UKHL 66 at [7].

99 Budina v Russia [2009] ECHR 45603/05.

100 O'Rourke v UK [2001] ECHR 39022/97.

101 MSS v Belgium and Greece [2011] ECHR 30696/09 at [230]–[234].

102 R (on the application of Q and Others) v Secretary of State for the Home Department [2003] EWCA Civ 364 at [45]–[63]. See also ex p Adam, Limbuela, and Tesema, above n 98.

103 Foreign workers may also constitute a vulnerable group where the state restricts their agency through restrictive employment regulations such as the Kafala system, which leaves workers open to abuse by unscrupulous employers: A Almutawa and KM Aldweri ‘Bahrain's pioneering role in the protection of the rights of temporary workers in the Gulf region’ (2020) 4 The Asian Yearbook of Human Rights and Humanitarian Law 349.

104 See C Heri Responsive Human Rights: Vulnerability, Ill-treatment and the ECtHR (Oxford, Hart Publishing, 2021) pp 204–230, particularly p 213.

105 O'Rourke v UK, above n 100.

106 Ex p Adam, Limbuela, and Tesema, above n 98, at [7] per Lord Bingham. See Clarke, above n 97.

107 Dermine, above n 8, at 770.

108 CN and V v France, above n 84, at [77]; Report of the Director-General The Cost of Coercion: Global Report under the Follow up to the ILO Declaration on Fundamental Principles and Rights at Work (Report 1B, International Labour Conference 98th Session, 2009) at para 24.

109 X v the Netherlands, above n 74.

110 Stec and Others v the United Kingdom [2006] ECHR 65731/01; 65900/01 at [53].

111 House of Commons Work and Pensions Committee, above n 94, pp 40–41.

112 Reilly, above n 28, at [82].

113 Siliadin, above n 84, at [118].

114 CN and V v France, above n 84, at [74]. See also Chowdury and Others v Greece [2017] ECHR 21884/15 at [90]–[91].

115 Schuitemaker, above n 74.

116 J Hyman ‘Voluntariness and choice’ (2013) 63 The Philosophical Quarterly 683 at 684, 695.

117 Pakistan International Airline Corporation v Times Travel (UK) Ltd [2021] UKSC 40 at [2] per Lord Hodge (Lords Reed, Lloyd-Jones and Kitchin agreeing).

118 Siliadin, above n 84, at [119].

119 Hyman, above n 116, at 691.

120 Siliadin, above n 84, at [119].

121 See H Lambie-Mumford ‘“Every town should have one”: emergency food banking in the UK’ (2013) 42 Journal of Social Policy 73; Special Rapporteur on extreme poverty and human rights Visit to the United Kingdom of Great Britain and Northern Ireland (A/HRC/41/39/Add.1, 23 April 2019) at para 47. This point depends on the availability of charitable support. Indeed, where it is accessible, charitable support may be sufficient to prevent a violation of Art 3 in the context of asylum seekers who are not lawfully allowed to work and have been denied support by the Secretary of State: R (on the application of Q and Others), above n 102, at [63]. See also rx p Adam, Limbuela, and Tesema, above n 98, at [61].

122 Report of the Director-General, above n 108, at para 23.

123 X v the Netherlands, above n 74; Talmon v the Netherlands, above n 74; Schuitemaker v the Netherlands, above n 74.

124 This is acknowledged in DWP guidance, which notes that the claimant commitment is too generic to constitute a ‘personal commitment’ to carry out a specific work-related activity, which requires additional information: DWP, above n 29, at J1004.

125 Van der Mussele, above n 84, at [36]–[37].

126 Ibid, at [39].

127 See the discussion in section 1, text at n 69.

128 Mantouvalou, above n 5, at 936–937; Mantouvalou, above n 12, at 436.

129 See D Seikel and D Spannagel ‘Activation and in-work poverty’ in H Lohmann and I Marx (eds) Handbook on In-Work Poverty (Cheltenham: Edward Elgar, 2018) p 245.

130 See T Campbell ‘Poverty as a violation of human rights: inhumanity or injustice?’ in T Pogge (ed) Freedom from Poverty as a Human Right: Who Owes What to the Very Poor? (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007) p 55.

131 Ibid, p 56.

132 Ibid. See also Md Arifuzzman et al ‘Exploration of poverty and human rights violation: a legal analysis’ (2021) 3 Asian Journal of Social Sciences and Legal Studies 10; F Doz Costa ‘Poverty and human rights from rhetoric to legal obligations: a critical account of conceptual frameworks’ (2008) 5 SUR International Journal on Human Rights 81; T Pogge ‘Severe poverty as a human rights violation’ in MT Kamminga (ed) Challenges in International Human Rights Law, Volume III (London: Routledge, 2017) p 721.

133 See text at n 69 and at n 98.

134 Welfare Reform Act 2012, s 17(1) and Explanatory Notes.

135 See also above, text at nn 35–40.

136 C Stevens MP and A Sharma MP ‘Universal Credit: zero-hours contracts’ (UIN197460, 29 November 2018), available at https://www.parliament.uk/business/publications/written-questions-answers-statements/written-question/Commons/2018-11-29/197460/.

137 N Datta et al ‘Zero-hours contracts and labour market policy’ (2019) 34 Economic Policy 369 at 373; E Farina et al ‘Zero-hours contracts and their growth’ (2020) 58 British Journal of Industrial Relations 507 at 514.

138 Including Cyprus, Finland, Ireland, Malta, Norway and Sweden: Adams and Prassl, above n 35, at 6.

139 See Stevens and Sharma, above n 136.

140 DL Blustein et al ‘Decent work: a psychological perspective’ (2016) 7 Frontiers in Psychology 1 at 5.

141 M Taylor et al Good Work: The Taylor Review of Modern Working Practices (July 2017) pp 9, 14, available at https://www.gov.uk/government/publications/good-work-the-taylor-review-of-modern-working-practices.

142 Farina at al, above n 137, at 507, 514.

143 DWP ‘Guidance: Universal Credit work allowances’ (12 April 2021), available at https://www.gov.uk/government/publications/universal-credit-work-allowances/universal-credit-work-allowances#.

144 P Dwyer and S Wright ‘Universal Credit, ubiquitous conditionality and its implications for social citizenship’ (2014) 22 Journal of Poverty and Social Justice 27 at 31.

145 Adams and Prassl, above n 35, at 21.

146 Reilly, above n 28, at [83].

147 Wright and Dwyer, above n 40, at 26–27.

148 Van der Mussele, above n 84, at [40].

149 Welfare Reform Act 2012, s 17(1) and Explanatory Notes; Universal Credit Regulations 2013, SI 2013/376, regs 88(1), 97(3).

150 Although capped at £1108.04 per month for two or more children, UC provides up to 85% of childcare costs for working parents. See UK Government ‘Universal Credit: childcare guide’ (17 October 2022), available at https://www.gov.uk/government/publications/universal-credit-and-childcare/universal-credit-childcare-guide#hours-free-childcare.

151 CN and V v France, above n 84, at [74]. See also Chowdury, above n 114, at [90]–[91].

152 Van der Mussele, above n 84, at [37]–[39].

153 Reilly, above n 28, at [81]–[90].

154 See section 2(d) for further discussion.

155 Report of the Director-General, above n 108, at para 43.

156 Reilly, above n 28, at [81].

157 Report of the Director-General A Global Alliance against Forced Labour: Global Report under the Follow Up to the ILO Declaration on Fundamental Principles and Rights at Work (Report 1B, International Labour Conference 93rd Session, 2005) at para 31.

158 Report of the Director-General, above n 108, at para 43.

159 Report of the Director-General, above n 157, at para 31; ILO Forced Labour and Human Trafficking: A Handbook for Labour Inspectors (2008) p 5, available at https://www.ilo.org/wcmsp5/groups/public/---ed_norm/---declaration/documents/publication/wcms_097835.pdf.

160 Report of the Director-General, above n 108, at para 44.

161 SM v Croatia, above n 85, at [300].

162 J Morgan and W Olsen ‘Forced and unfree labour: an analysis’ (2014) 4 International Critical Thought 21 at 22.

163 SM v Croatia, above n 85, at [329].

164 H Steiner ‘A liberal theory of exploitation’ (1984) 94 Ethics 225; AW Wood ‘Exploitation’ (1995) 12 Social Philosophy and Policy 136; R Mayer ‘What's wrong with exploitation?’ (2007) 24 Journal of Applied Philosophy 137.

165 A Wertheimer Exploitation (Princeton, Princeton University Press, 1999) p 16; R Arneson ‘Exploitation and outcome’ (2013) 12 Politics, Philosophy & Economics 392; MR Reiff Exploitation and Economic Justice in the Liberal Capitalist State (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013) p 27; J Collins ‘Exploitation of persons and the limits of the criminal law’ (2017) 3 Criminal Law Review 169 at 171.

166 Mayer, above n 164, at 140; AW Wood ‘Unjust exploitation’ (2016) 54 Southern Journal of Philosophy 92, 96.

167 Arneson, above n 165, at 394.

168 Mayer, above n 164, at 142, 144.

169 Mantouvalou, above n 5, at 936–937; Mantouvalou above n 12, at 436–438.

170 See R v SK [2011] EWCA Crim 1691 at [44].

171 Chowdury, above n 114, at [98]. See also Balogh v Hick Lane Bedding Ltd [2021] EWHC 1140 (QB).

172 Chowdury, above n 114, at [97]–[98].

173 Reilly, above n 28, at [89].

174 R v SK, above n 170, at [49].

175 X v the Netherlands, above n 74.

176 MS (Trafficking – Tribunal Powers – Art 4 ECHR) [2016] UKUT 00226 (IAC) at [51]. See also MS (Pakistan) v Secretary of State for the Home Department [2020] UKSC 9.

177 A v Abu [2017] EWHC 3098 (QB) at [93].

178 MS (Trafficking), above n 176, at [50]–[52].

179 Attorney General's Reference (Nos 2, 3, 4, and 5 of 2013) [2013] EWCA Crim 324 at [12], [20].

180 See Schuitemaker, above 74.

181 Report of the Director-General, above n 108, at para 23.

182 Reilly, above n 28, at [83].

183 Jobseeker's Allowance and Universal Credit (Higher-Level Sanctions) (Amendment) Regulations 2019, SI 2019/1357, reg 3.

184 Arneson, above n 165, at 399.

185 Reilly, above n 28, at [83].

186 See below, text at n 187.

187 Van der Mussele, above n 84, at [38].

188 Reilly, above n 28, at [81].

189 G ten Berge ‘Towards an equilibrium between citizens’ rights and civic duties in relation to government’ (2007) 3 Utrecht Law Review 219 at 220, 221.

190 See J Pykett et al ‘Framing the good citizen’ (2010) 12 British Journal of Politics and International Relations 523; A de Koning et al ‘Citizenship agendas in and beyond the nation state: (en)countering framings of the good citizen’ (2015) 19 Citizenship Studies 121.

191 See Dermine , above n 8, at 752–764.

192 Zarb Adami v Malta, above n 19, at [47]. Other examples include compulsory participation in the provision of a fire service (Karlheinz Schmidt v Germany, above n 19, at [23]), the unremunerated performance of medical examinations (Reitmayr v Austria [1995] European Commission 23866/94), and the provision of free legal representation for indigent persons (Van der Mussele, above n 84).

193 ten Berge, above n 189, at 220.

194 Faure, above n 81, at [7.5].

195 Reilly, above n 28, at [82].

196 Mantouvalou, above n 5, at 931, 943, 946.

197 S Deakin and F Wilkinson The Law of the Labour Market (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005) pp 134, 198–199.

198 D Freud Reducing Dependency, Increasing Opportunity: Options for the Future of Welfare to Work (Independent Report to the Department for Work and Pensions, 2007) p 77; ID Smith ‘Foreword by the Secretary of State’ in Department for Work and Pensions, 21st Century Welfare Cm 7913, July 2010, p 1.

199 Mayer, above n 164, at 141.

200 A Molander and G Torsvik ‘Getting people into work: what (if anything) can justify mandatory activation of welfare recipients?’ (2015) 32 Journal of Applied Philosophy 373 at 381.

201 Schuitemaker, above n 74.

202 Van der Mussele, above n 84, at [40].

203 Ibid, at [37]–[38]; Z Leventhal ‘Focus on Article 4 of the ECHR’ (2005) Juridical Review 237 at 239.

204 Steindel v Germany [2010] ECHR 29878/07.

205 Albeit that the in-work benefits scheme is not without its problems. For a valuable critique see K Puttick ‘From mini to maxi jobs? Low pay, “progression”, and the duty to work (harder)’ (2019) 48 Industrial Law Journal 143.

206 M Koumenta and M Williams ‘An anatomy of zero-hours contracts in the UK’ (2019) 50 Industrial Relations Journal 20 at 36.

207 M Chobli ‘The duty to work’ (2018) 21 Ethical Theory and Practice 1119 at 1124.

208 Department for Work and Pensions ‘2010 to 2015 government policy: welfare reform’ (2013, as updated to 8 May 2015), available at https://www.gov.uk/government/publications/2010-to-2015-government-policy-welfare-reform.

209 R Patrick ‘Work as the primary “duty” of the responsible citizen: a critique of this work-centric approach’ (2012) 6 People, Place and Policy Online 5 at 7.

210 Department for Work and Pensions Raising Expectations and Increasing Support: Reforming Welfare for the Future, Cmnd 7506, December 2008, p 38.

211 Dermine, above n 8, at loc 1690. For Dermine, proportionality should be determined by four criteria: quality of work; exit options (the severity of sanctions and the availability of subsistence); the ability of claimants to be heard or have a ‘voice’ (options to refuse, power influence work assignments, right of appeal); the scheme's goals and effects.

212 M Wilińska et al ‘“When I'm 65”: on the age-negotiated duty to work’ (2021) 35 Work, Employment and Society 21 at 22.

213 Reilly, above n 28.

214 L Graham ‘Strategic admissibility decisions in the European Court of Human Rights’ (2020) 69 International and Comparative Law Quarterly 79 at 101–102.

215 Tyrer v the UK, above n 79, at [31]. See S Theil ‘Is the “living instrument” approach of the European Court of Human Rights compatible with the ECHR and international law?’ (2017) 23 European Public Law 587.

216 Z and Others v the UK [2001] ECHR 29392/95 at [103].

217 For a critical overview see A Mowbray ‘Subsidiarity and the European Convention on Human Rights’ (2015) 15 Human Rights Law Review 313.

218 J-M Sauvé ‘Subsidiarity: a two-sided coin?’ (Speech delivered to the European Court of Human Rights Seminar on the role of the national authorities, Strasbourg, 30 January 2015), available at https://www.echr.coe.int/Documents/Speech_20150130_Seminar_JMSauv%C3%A9_ENG.pdf.

219 Protocol No 15 amending the Convention on the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Principles (2013), Art 1. The Protocol entered into force on 1 August 2021: Council of Europe ‘Chart of signatures and ratifications of Treaty 213’, available at https://www.coe.int/en/web/conventions/full-list/-/conventions/treaty/213/signatures?module=treaty-detail&treatynum=213. See also D Spielmann ‘Whither the margin of appreciation?’ (2014) 67 Current Legal Problems 49 at 65.

220 Sauvé, above n 218.

221 A von Staden ‘The democratic legitimacy of judicial review beyond the state: normative subsidiarity and judicial standards of review’ (2012) 10 International Journal of Constitutional Law 1023 at 1026, 1037.

222 SAS v France [2014] ECHR 43835/11 at [154].

223 R Spano ‘The future of the European Court of Human Rights – subsidiarity, process-based review and the rule of law’ (2018) 18 Human Rights Law Review 473.

224 Joint Committee on Human Rights Legislative Scrutiny: Welfare Reform Bill Twenty-first Report of Session 2010–2012, HL 233, HC 1704, 23 December 2011 (TSO, 2011) para 1.37.

225 A Simola and S Wrede ‘Young EU migrant citizens’ access to financial independence in conditions of precarious work: a tripartite approach to welfare conditionality’ (2020) Journal of European Social Policy 1 at 4.

226 Von Hannover v Germany (No 2) [2012] ECHR 40660/08; 60641/08 at [107].

227 D Spielmann ‘Whither the margin of appreciation?’ UCL Current Legal Problems Lecture (London, 20 March 2014) p 12, available at https://www.echr.coe.int/Documents/Speech_20140320_London_ENG.pdf.

228 Madsen, MRThe challenging authority of the European Court of Human Rights: from cold war legal diplomacy to the Brighton Declaration and backlash’ (2016) 79 Law and Contemporary Problems 141Google Scholar at 144, 151.

229 Bates, EBritish sovereignty and the European Court of Human Rights’ (2012) 128 Law Quarterly Review 382Google Scholar at 410–411.

230 Madsen, above n 228, at 170, 174; Vinters v the UK [2013] ECHR 66069/09; 130/10; 3896/10; Hirst (No 2) v UK [2005] ECHR 74025/01.

231 H Fenwick and R Masterman ‘The conservative project to “break the link between British courts and Strasbourg’: rhetoric or reality?’ (2017) 80 Modern Law Review 1111 at 1129–1130; Madsen, above n 228, at 171. See also Bratza, NThe relationship between the UK courts and Strasbourg’ (2011) 5 European Human Rights Law Review 505Google Scholar.

232 Ø Stiansen and E Voeten ‘Backlash and judicial restraint: evidence from the European Court of Human Rights’ (2020) 64 International Studies Quarterly 770.

233 Bates, above n 229, at 409.

234 Bellamy, RPolitical constitutionalism and the Human Rights Act’ (2011) 9 International Journal of Constitutional Law 86CrossRefGoogle Scholar at 110–111.

235 Tan, GChildren's rights and the influence of Lord Sales in the UKSC's political constitutionalist turn’ (2022) 26 Edinburgh Law Review 93CrossRefGoogle Scholar at 94.

236 R (on the application of SC) v Secretary of State for Work and Pensions [2021] UKSC 26.

237 Ibid, at [146]. “Suspect” grounds include sex or gender, birth status, nationality, sexual orientation, race or ethnic origin, religious belief, disabilities and HIV status (at [101]–[113]).

238 Ibid, at [158].

239 Ibid, at [187].

240 Ibid, at [208]–[209].

241 Including the scope, intensity and ‘rights-centred perspective’ of any parliamentary debate. See Sales, PPartnership and challenge: the courts’ role in managing integration of rights and democracy’ [2016] Public Law 456Google Scholar at 458–464.

242 Clarke, CNow you see them, now you don't: the role of children's interests in social security law’ (2022) 29 Journal of Social Security Law 12Google Scholar at 26; Campbell, above n 17, at 1222.

243 Sayer, TManifest unreasonableness in the UK Supreme Court: a doctrine working itself pure’ (2022) 33 King's Law Journal 122CrossRefGoogle Scholar at 145.

244 Although written before the Supreme Court's hearing of the case, for a powerful critique of the domestic courts’ failure to interrogate the substantive inequalities of the present welfare policies, see Campbell, above n 17.

245 Clarke, above n 242, at 26; Machin, RThe two-child limit for benefits in the Supreme Court: implications for public health’ (2022) 142 Perspectives in Public Health 137CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

246 R (on the application of SC), above n 236, at [207].