Hostname: page-component-7bb8b95d7b-s9k8s Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-10-07T06:31:51.895Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Edmond Goblot’s (1858–1935) Selected Effects Theory of Function: A Reappraisal

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2022

Abstract

At the beginning of the twentieth century, the French philosopher of science Edmond Goblot wrote three prescient papers on function and teleology. He advanced the remarkable thesis that functions are, as a matter of conceptual analysis, selected effects. He also argued that “selection” must be understood broadly to include both evolutionary natural selection and intelligent design. Here, I do three things. First, I give an overview of Goblot’s thought. Second, I identify his core thesis about function. Third, I argue that, despite its ingenuity, Goblot’s expansive construal of function cannot be right. Still, Goblot deserves long-overdue credit for his work.

Type
Biological Sciences
Copyright
Copyright 2021 by the Philosophy of Science Association. All rights reserved.

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

I’d like to thank the participants of the workshop The Concept of Function in Biology: New Philosophical Perspectives held at Université du Québec à Montréal on October 4, 2019, including Brandon Conley, Antoine Dussault, Christophe Malaterre, and Parisa Moosavi. I particularly wish to thank the organizers, Antoine Dussault and Christophe Malaterre, for their valuable feedback. I’m also grateful to Sarah Arnaud and Dan Dennett for their comments on an earlier draft.

References

Bonsack, F. 1976. Fonction et Finalité: Symposium Ecrit. Bienne: Association F. Gonseth (Institut de la Méthode).Google Scholar
Dennett, D. 1969. Content and Consciousness. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Dennett, D.. 1995. Darwin’s Dangerous Idea. New York: Simon & Schuster.Google Scholar
Garson, J. 2011. “Selected Effects and Causal Role Functions in the Brain: The Case for an Etiological Approach to Neuroscience.” Biology and Philosophy 26:547–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Garson, J.. 2016. A Critical Overview of Biological Functions. Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Garson, J.. 2019. What Biological Functions Are and Why They Matter. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goblot, E. 1899. “Fonction et finalité.” Revue Philosophique de la France et de l’Étranger 47:495505, 632–45.Google Scholar
Goblot, E.. 1900. “La finalité sans intelligence.” Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 8:393406.Google Scholar
Goblot, E.. 1903. “La finalité en biologie.” Revue Philosophique de la France et de l’Étranger 56:366–79.Google Scholar
Godfrey-Smith, P. 1992. “Indication and Adaptation.” Synthese 92:283312.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Griffiths, P. E. 1993. “Functional Analysis and Proper Function.” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 44:409–22.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kitcher, P. 1993. “Function and Design.” Midwest Studies in Philosophy 18:379–97.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Millikan, R. G. 1984. Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Neander, K. 1983. “Abnormal Psychobiology.” PhD diss., La Trobe.Google Scholar
Neander, K.. 1991. “Functions as Selected Effects: The Conceptual Analyst’s Defense.” Philosophy of Science 58:168–84.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Papineau, D. 1984. “Representation and Explanation.” Philosophy of Science 51:550–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ruse, M. E. 1971. “Functional Statements in Biology.” Philosophy of Science 38:8795.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wimsatt, W. C. 1972. “Teleology and the Logical Structure of Function Statements.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 3:180.Google Scholar
Wright, L. 1973. “Functions.” Philosophical Review 82:139–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar