Hostname: page-component-7bb8b95d7b-5mhkq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-10-02T12:40:02.616Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

That All Shall be Saved: Heaven, Hell, and Universal Salvation by David Bentley Hart, Yale University Press, New Haven and London, 2019, pp. 222, £20.00, hbk

Review products

That All Shall be Saved: Heaven, Hell, and Universal Salvation by David Bentley Hart, Yale University Press, New Haven and London, 2019, pp. 222, £20.00, hbk

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2024

Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Type
Reviews
Copyright
Copyright © 2020 Provincial Council of the English Province of the Order of Preachers

In this short book David Bentley Hart, ‘an Eastern Orthodox scholar of religion and a philosopher, writer, and cultural commentator’, argues stridently in favour of universal salvation. He concludes not merely that this is one possibility among others, or that Christians may legitimately hope for this outcome, but that as a matter of fact, even of necessity, ‘all shall be saved’. Despite a pronounced tendency in modern theology towards some version of universalism, Hart presents himself as fighting a battle, even a hopeless battle, against a majority who support ‘infernalism’.  While infernalists conceive of hell as unceasing, Hart endorses a hell that will eventually come to an end, where punishment is always restorative. While infernalism is presumably in the majority in Eastern Orthodoxy, Hart focuses his assault firmly on the West: his chief adversaries are Calvinists, evangelicals who have become conservative Catholics, and Thomists. Hart refuses the moderation of academic caution: though in the minority, he is simply right, and his opponents are not to be treated lightly.

The core of Hart's book is found in four meditations, the first on the identity of God, the second on the nature of judgement, the third on personhood, and the fourth on freedom. These correspond to four arguments, each of which appears in various places throughout the book. The argument from freedom charges that no genuinely free intellectual creature can reject God. Hart rejects the modern view of freedom as negative liberty, and shares with his Thomist opponents an ‘intellectualist’, dynamic, patristic view of freedom, where the perfect freedom of heaven in the presence of divine goodness excludes the ability to sin. However, what is surely at issue is not perfect freedom, but sufficient freedom: do those on earth have sufficient freedom to reject God definitively? Hart seems to recognise the point but does not focus enough on what his opponents might consider as rendering freedom sufficient for such a choice. Without such an extended engagement, Hart cannot make the requisite critique of his opponents’ position. To that extent his assault is wide of the mark.

Another of Hart's argument is that no person can be in heaven while any other person is permanently excluded from it. It is an argument that surely touches all of us insofar as we wonder how we can be truly happy so long as someone we love is in hell eternally. Hart is especially disparaging of any response that watching the sufferings of those in hell can add to the happiness of the saints. However, if we suppose that God himself is our ultimate good and our beatitude, in the way that Hart's argument from freedom seems to suppose, then can the perfect knowledge of God's justice not exclude all sorrow from the souls of the saints? If God's perfect beatitude is undisturbed by the effect of his justice on those who have freely rejected him, and the saints are somehow enabled to see things from God's perspective, does this not point us to a solution? For Hart this will not do. For Hart not even God can have such a perspective, just because God is Good and completely in charge of his creation.

This brings us to Hart's argument from who God is. While he agrees with Brian Davies OP that God is not a moral agent among others, Hart contends that God is Moral Agency itself. Moreover, he is the First Cause of all. Rejecting the Thomist distinction between God's will as permitting and God's will as positively causing, Hart is nearer here to the Calvinists he so much despises. Although even sins are caused by God, Hart is not outraged that these and other evils such as their punishment are caused by Moral Agency itself, so long as they do not last for ever. However, it seems to many that, if Scripture supports even the possibility of an endless hell, then the latter must be compatible with the Goodness of God, and an endless punishment fitting for an offence against the infinite God. It is thus that the desire to be faithful to Scripture gives rise to the kind of theological speculation for which Hart has run out of respect. So Hart's view still has to negotiate Scripture: does Scripture teach that there is an end to hell or not?Hart reviews the Scriptural evidence for universalism and infernalism in his second meditation. What he does effectively is to treat universalism as clearly taught by the majority of relevant texts, although it seems to me that at least some of them can be interpreted as teaching a universal offer of salvation that only some might accept. The texts normally used to support an endless hell he treats as in a minority and more obscure, needing to be read in line with the universalist majority with the help of his own translation of The New Testament (2018). Much turns on Hart's translation of aiōnios, normally rendered ‘eternal’, as ‘of the Age’. Where all this leaves Hart's own theology of an endless heaven, in terms of a Scriptural basis, I am not sure. My own impression overall is that he is more successful in exposing the range of possible translations of the infernalists’ texts than in proving his own beyond reasonable doubt.

Many of Hart's adversaries doubtless appeal to Tradition as their guide for interpreting Scripture. It is thus a pity that Hart has little to say about Tradition. He himself follows, among others, St Gregory of Nyssa, drawn to them by his own personal instinct, but he knows that they are in the minority. Western theologians naturally have to deal with a wider range of authorities, which would have little significance for Hart, but it is disappointing that he has little to say about the condemnation of Origen, his continuing influence on the minority, and how this is to be negotiated. It seems to me that more needed to be said, but Hart is convinced he has said all that needs to be said.