Hostname: page-component-7bb8b95d7b-cx56b Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-09-29T19:14:18.051Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

DIVERGENT MODELS WITH THE FAILURE OF THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS

Part of: Set theory

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 December 2023

NAM TRANG*
Affiliation:
DEPARTMENT OF MATHEMATICS UNIVERSITY OF NORTH TEXAS DENTON, TX 76205, USA
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

We construct divergent models of $\mathsf {AD}^+$ along with the failure of the Continuum Hypothesis ($\mathsf {CH}$) under various assumptions. Divergent models of $\mathsf {AD}^+$ play an important role in descriptive inner model theory; all known analyses of HOD in $\mathsf {AD}^+$ models (without extra iterability assumptions) are carried out in the region below the existence of divergent models of $\mathsf {AD}^+$. Our results are the first step toward resolving various open questions concerning the length of definable prewellorderings of the reals and principles implying $\neg \mathsf {CH}$, like $\mathsf {MM}$, that divergent models shed light on, see Question 5.1.

Type
Article
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Association for Symbolic Logic

1 Introduction

In this paper, we identify the reals $\mathbb {R}$ with $\mathbb {N}^{\mathbb {N}}$ , the set of all infinite sequences of natural numbers equipped with the Baire topology.

Definition 1.1. Suppose M and N are transitive models of $\mathsf {AD}^+$ . We say that M and N are divergent models of $\mathsf {AD}^+$ if there are sets of reals $A\in M$ and $B\in N$ such that $A\notin N$ and $B\notin M$ .

If $M,N$ are divergent models of $\mathsf {AD}^+$ , then the Wadge hierarchies of $M, N$ “diverge,” or equivalently ${\wp }(\mathbb {R})\cap M\nsubseteq N$ and ${\wp }(\mathbb {R})\cap N \nsubseteq M$ . Woodin has shown that letting $\Gamma = {\wp }(\mathbb {R})\cap M \cap N$ , then $\Gamma = {\wp }(\mathbb {R})\cap L(\Gamma ,\mathbb {R})$ and furthermore, $L(\Gamma ,\mathbb {R})\models \mathsf {AD}_{\mathbb {R}} + \mathsf {DC}$ . The upper-bound consistency strength of divergent models of $\mathsf {AD}^+$ , as shown by Woodin, is the existence of a Woodin cardinal which is a limit of Woodin cardinals. This bound is conjectured to be exact.Footnote 1 Divergent models of $\mathsf {AD}^+$ play a very important role in descriptive inner model theory; virtually, all known analyses of HOD in strong $\mathsf {AD}^+$ models are carried out below this bound (see cf. [Reference Sargsyan3, Reference Sargsyan and Trang5]).

Working in a universe satisfying $\mathsf {CH}$ , Woodin constructed divergent models of $\mathsf {AD}^+$ [Reference Farah1]. We prove that it is consistent that there are divergent models of $\mathsf {AD}^+$ while $\mathsf {CH}$ fails.

Theorem 1.2. Suppose $\mathsf {CH}$ holds and there are two sets of reals $A,B$ such that $:$

  • $(\mathbb {R},A)^\sharp , (\mathbb {R},B)^\sharp $ exist and are $\aleph _1$ -universally Baire,

  • $L(A,\mathbb {R}), L(B,\mathbb {R})$ are models of $\mathsf {AD}^+$ such that letting $H_A = HOD^{L(A,\mathbb {R})}$ and $H_B = HOD^{L(B,\mathbb {R})}$ , there is some $\alpha < \textrm {min}\{\omega _1^{H_A}, \omega _1^{H_B}\}$ such that the $\alpha $ -th real in the canonical well-order of $H_A$ is different from the $\alpha $ -th real in the canonical well-order of $H_B$ .

Let $\mathbb {P}$ be the standard ccc forcing that adds $\omega _2$ many Cohen reals and $g\subseteq \mathbb {P}$ be V-generic. Then in $V[g]$ , there are $A^*,B^*$ and embeddings $j_A, j_B$ such that $:$

  1. 1. $j_A: L(A,\mathbb {R}^V) \rightarrow L(A^*,\mathbb {R}^{V[g]})$ , $j_B: L(B,\mathbb {R}^V) \rightarrow L(B^*,\mathbb {R}^{V[g]})$ fix all ordinals, and

  2. 2. $L(A^*,\mathbb {R}^{V[g]}), L(B^*,\mathbb {R}^{V[g]})$ are divergent models of $\mathsf {AD}^+$ .

Corollary 1.3. Con( $\mathsf {ZFC} + $ there is a Woodin limit of Woodin cardinals) implies Con( $\mathsf {CH}$ fails and there are divergent models of $\mathsf {AD}^+)$ .

Proof By results of Woodin’s (see [Reference Farah1]), the hypothesis of Theorem 1.2 is consistent relative to the existence of a Woodin limit of Woodin cardinals. The corollary follows from Theorem 1.2.

The following theorem is folklore. We include the proof here for self-containment. It is used in the proof of Corollary 1.5. A forcing $\mathbb {P}$ is said to be weakly proper if whenever $g\subset \mathbb {P}$ is V-generic, for any ordinal $\alpha $ , ${\wp }_{\omega _1}^{V[g]}(\alpha )\subset {\wp }^V_{\omega _1}(\alpha )$ . $\Gamma _\infty $ denotes the collection of universally Baire sets.

Theorem 1.4. Assume there is a proper class of Woodin cardinals and $A\subseteq \mathbb {R}$ is universally Baire. Suppose $\mathbb {P}$ is weakly proper. Then for any V-generic $g\subseteq \mathbb {P}$ , there is some universally Baire set $B\in V$ such that letting $B^*$ be the canonical interpretation of B in $V[g]$ , A is Wadge reducible to $B^*$ .

Corollary 1.5. Assume there is a proper class of Woodin cardinals. Suppose $A,B$ are as in the hypothesis of Theorem 1.2. Furthermore, assume that $\Gamma _\infty \subset L(A,\mathbb {R})\cap L(B,\mathbb {R})$ . Let $\mathbb {P}$ be the forcing that adds $\omega _2$ Cohen reals and $g\subseteq \mathbb {P}$ be V-generic. Then in $V[g]$ , $\Gamma _\infty \subset L(A^*,\mathbb {R}^{V[g]})\cap L(B^*,\mathbb {R}^{V[g]})$ .

Now we address the question of whether the hypothesis of Corollary 1.5 is consistent. We construct divergent models of $\mathsf {AD}^+$ that contain the collection of universally Baire sets from a strong hypothesis. We are hopeful that with recent advancement in descriptive inner model theory, this hypothesis can be shown to be consistent.

Definition 1.6. Let ${\mathcal {M}}$ be a hybrid premouse. We say that ${\mathcal {M}}$ is appropriate premouse if ${\mathcal {M}} = (|{\mathcal {M}}|,\in , \mathbb {E}, \mathbb {S})$ is an amenable J-structure that satisfies $:$

  1. 1. the predicate $\mathbb {S}$ codes $({\mathcal {P}}_0, \Sigma )$ , where ${\mathcal {P}}_0 = ({\mathcal {M}}|{\delta _0})^\sharp $ Footnote 2 for some Woodin cardinal $\delta _0$ such that ${\mathcal {P}}_0$ is an lsa hod premouse and $\Sigma $ is the short-tree strategy of ${\mathcal {P}}_0;$ Footnote 3

  2. 2. there is a proper class of Woodin cardinals and a Woodin limit of Woodin cardinals $> \delta _0$ as witnessed by a fine-extender sequence $($ in the sense of [Reference Steel7] $)$ coded by $\mathbb {E};$

  3. 3. for any set generic h, $\Sigma $ has a canonical interpretation $\Sigma ^h$ in $V[h];$ more precisely, there is a term-relation $\tau $ such that for all generic h, $\tau ^h = \Sigma ^h;$

  4. 4. in all generic extensions $V[g]$ of V for which ${\mathcal {P}}_0$ is countable, $\Sigma ^g\notin (\Gamma _\infty )^{V[g]}$ but letting $\Gamma ({\mathcal {P}}_0,\Sigma ^g)$ be the set of A such that there is a countable ${\mathcal {T}}$ according to $\Sigma ^g$ such that $A \leq _w \Sigma ^g_{{\mathcal {T}}, {\mathcal {M}}({\mathcal {T}})}$ , then $\Gamma ({\mathcal {P}}_0,\Sigma ^g) = (\Gamma _\infty )^{V[g]}$ . This essentially says that all lower-level strategies of $\Sigma ^g$ or its iterates are in $(\Gamma _\infty )^{V[g]}$ .

$({\mathcal {M}},\Psi )$ is an appropriate mouse if ${\mathcal {M}}$ is an appropriate premouse and $\Psi $ is an iteration strategy for ${\mathcal {M}}$ such that if $i: {\mathcal {M}}\rightarrow {\mathcal {N}}$ be an iteration according to $\Psi $ , then for any ${\mathcal {N}}$ -generic g, $i(\tau )^g = (\Psi _N)^{sh}_{{\mathcal {P}}_0}{\mathop{\restriction} } {\mathcal {N}}[g]$ , here $(\Psi _N)_{{\mathcal {P}}_0}^{sh}$ is the restriction of the tail strategy $\Psi _N$ on N to short trees on ${\mathcal {P}}_0$ .

It is not known if the existence of an appropriate mouse is consistent; a weaker version of this is shown to be consistent in [Reference Sargsyan and Trang4] and plays a key role in determining the exact consistency strength of Woodin’s Sealing of the Universally Baire sets. Property 4, namely the assumption on $\Sigma $ , is an abstraction of properties of excellent mice defined in [Reference Sargsyan and Trang4] and is the key property that allows us to prove Theorem 1.7. The intuition giving rise to 4 comes from the construction of models of $\mathsf {LSA - over - UB}$ in [Reference Sargsyan and Trang4], where the $\mathsf {LSA}$ model is generated by a pair $({\mathcal {P}},\Sigma )$ such that $\Sigma $ is a short-tree strategy for an lsa-type hod premouse ${\mathcal {P}}$ and $\Gamma ({\mathcal {P}},\Sigma )=\Gamma _\infty $ . In the proof of Theorem 1.7, we use this property to show that $\Gamma _\infty $ (in a generic extension of the appropriate mouse) is in both divergent models, by showing the interpretation of $\tau $ by the generic is in both models. The main difference between an appropriate mouse and an excellent mouse lies in property 2. We do not yet have a theory of layered-hod mice that reaches the level of “ $\mathsf {ZFC} + $ there is a Woodin cardinal which is a limit of Woodin cardinals” $(\mathsf {WLW})$ , but such a theory exists for least-branch hod mice [Reference Steel8], so it seems very plausible that the existence of appropriate mice is consistent.Footnote 4

The following property abstracts out some of the features of countable substructures of models obtained by fully backgrounded constructions (see cf. [Reference Neeman2, Reference Steel7]). We say that V satisfies countable self-iterability if for any cardinal $\delta $ and any countable $X\prec V_{\delta +1}$ , the transitive collapse M of X is fully iterable with $\delta $ -universally Baire strategy $\Lambda $ ; furthermore, letting $\tau : M\rightarrow X$ be the uncollapse map, $\Lambda $ is $\tau $ -realizable, i.e., whenever $\pi : M \rightarrow N$ is an iteration map according to $\Lambda $ with $|N| < \omega _1$ , there is some $\sigma : N\rightarrow V_{\delta +1}$ such that $\tau = \sigma \circ \pi $ .

Theorem 1.7. Suppose $V = L[\vec {E}]$ is an extender model such that in V, there is a proper class of Woodin cardinals and countable self-iterability holds. Suppose there is an appropriate mouse $({\mathcal {M}},\Psi )$ such that $\Psi \in \Gamma _\infty $ . Then in some generic extension of ${\mathcal {M}}$ , there are divergent models of $\mathsf {AD}^+ N_1, N_2$ such that $\Gamma _\infty \subset N_1\cap N_2$ .

Remark 1.8. Theorem 1.7 relates to Question 5.1 $(i)$ in light of recent development in the core model induction $;$ in particular, one can show under $\mathsf {MM}$ that $\Gamma _\infty $ contains very complicated mice, e.g., there are Wadge initial segments $\Gamma $ such that $L(\Gamma )\models \mathsf {AD}_{\mathbb {R}} + "\Theta $ is regular” and much more. One can hope that $\mathsf {MM}$ implies the existence of mice that satisfies $\mathsf {WLW}$ with universally Baire iteration strategies. Question 5.1 $(ii)$ is a weakening of Question 5.1 $(i)$ as $\mathsf {MM}$ implies . If Question 5.1 $(ii)$ was true, then $\Gamma _\infty $ is “large” in that $o(\Gamma _\infty )> \omega _2$ . It is open whether $o(\Gamma _\infty )$ could be $>\omega _3$ .

2 Preliminaries

Let $\Theta $ be the supremum of ordinals $\gamma $ such that there is a surjection from $\mathbb {R}$ onto $\gamma $ . A very useful extension of the Axiom of Determinacy, $\mathsf {AD}$ , is a theory called $\mathsf {AD}^+$ isolated by Woodin. $\mathsf {AD}^+$ consists of the following statements.

  • $\mathsf {DC}_{\mathbb {R}}$ .

  • Every set of reals has an $\infty $ -Borel code. (An $\infty $ -Borel code is a pair $(S,\varphi )$ where S is a set of ordinals and $\varphi $ is a formula of set theory. Let $\mathfrak {B}_{(S,\varphi )} = \{r \in \mathbb {R} : L[S,r] \models \varphi (S,r)\}$ . $(S,\varphi )$ is an $\infty $ -Borel code for a set $A \subseteq \mathbb {R}$ if and only if $A = \mathfrak {B}_{(S,\varphi )}$ .)

  • $\mathsf {Ordinal\ Determinacy}$ , which is the statements that for every $\lambda < \Theta $ , $X \subseteq \mathbb {R}$ , and continuous function $\pi : {}^\omega \lambda \rightarrow \mathbb {R}$ , the two player game on $\lambda $ with payoff set $\pi ^{-1}(X)$ is determined.

It is conjectured that under $\mathsf {ZF + DC}_{\mathbb {R}}$ , $\mathsf {AD}$ implies $\mathsf {AD}^+$ . All known models of $\mathsf {AD}$ satisfy $\mathsf {AD}^+$ .

For any model M of $\mathsf {AD}^+$ , the ordinal $\Theta ^M$ is defined to be the supremum of ordinals $\gamma $ such that there is a surjection from $\mathbb {R}$ onto $\gamma $ in M. For any set of reals A in M, let $w(A)$ denote the Wadge rank of A in M. A basic result due to R. Solovay, is that $\Theta ^M$ is supremum of the Wadge ranks of sets of reals A in M.

We summarize basic facts about (weakly) homogeneously Suslin and universally Baire sets we need. For a more detailed discussion, the reader should consult for example [Reference Steel6].

Given an uncountable cardinal $\kappa $ , and a set Z, $meas_\kappa (Z)$ denotes the set of all $\kappa $ -additive measures on $Z^{<\omega }$ . If $\mu \in meas_\kappa (Z)$ , then there is a unique $n<\omega $ such that $Z^n\in \mu $ by $\kappa $ -additivity; we let this $n = dim(\mu )$ . If $\mu ,\nu \in meas_\kappa (Z)$ , we say that $\mu $ projects to $\nu $ if $dim(\nu ) = m \leq dim(\mu ) = n$ and for all $A\subseteq Z^m$ ,

$$ \begin{align*} A\in \nu \Leftrightarrow \{u : u{\mathop{\restriction}} m\in A\} \in \mu. \end{align*} $$

In this case, there is a natural embedding from the ultrapower of V by $\nu $ into the ultrapower of V by $\mu $ :

$$ \begin{align*} \pi_{\nu,\mu} : Ult(V,\nu) \rightarrow Ult(V,\mu) \end{align*} $$

defined by $\pi _{\nu ,\mu }([f]_\nu ) = [f^*]_\mu $ where $f^*(u) = f(u\mathop{\restriction} m)$ for all $u\in Z^n$ . A tower of measures on Z is a sequence $\langle \mu _n : n<k \rangle $ for some $k\leq \omega $ such that for all $m\leq n < k$ , $dim(\mu _n) = n$ and $\mu _n$ projects to $\mu _m$ . A tower $\langle \mu _n : n<\omega \rangle $ is countably complete if the direct limit of $\{Ult(V,\mu _n), \pi _{\mu _m,\mu _n}: m\leq n < \omega \}$ is well-founded. We will also say that the tower $\langle \mu _n : n<\omega \rangle $ is well-founded.

Recall we identify the set of reals $\mathbb {R}$ with the Baire space ${}^\omega \omega $ .

Definition 2.1. Fix an uncountable cardinal $\kappa $ . A function $\bar {\mu }: \omega ^{<\omega } \rightarrow meas_\kappa (Z)$ is a $\kappa $ -complete homogeneity system with support Z if for all $s,t\in \omega ^{<\omega }$ , writing $\mu _t$ for $\bar {\mu }(t):$

  1. 1. $dom(\mu _t) = dom(t)$ ,

  2. 2. $s\subseteq t \Rightarrow \mu _t$ projects to $\mu _s$ .

Often times, we will not specify the support $Z;$ instead, we just say $\bar {\mu }$ is a $\kappa $ -complete homogeneity system.

A set $A\subseteq \mathbb {R}$ is $\kappa $ -homogeneous iff there is a $\kappa $ -complete homogeneity system $\bar {\mu }$ such that

$$ \begin{align*} A = S_{\mu} =_{def} \{ x : \bar{\mu}_x \textrm{ is countably complete} \}. \end{align*} $$

A is homogeneous if it is $\kappa $ -homogeneous for all $\kappa $ . Let $\textrm {Hom}_\infty $ be the collection of all homogeneous sets.

Definition 2.2. Fix an uncountable cardinal $\kappa $ . A function $\bar {\mu }: \omega ^{<\omega } \rightarrow meas_\kappa (Z)$ is a $\kappa $ -complete weak homogeneity system with support Z if it is injective and for all $t\in \omega ^{<\omega }:$

  1. 1. $dom(\mu _t) \leq dom(t)$ ,

  2. 2. if $\mu _t$ projects to $\nu $ , then there is some $i<dom(\mu _t)$ such that $\nu = \mu _{t{\mathop{\restriction} } i}$ .

A set $A\subseteq \mathbb {R}$ is $\kappa $ -weakly homogeneous iff there is a $\kappa $ -complete weak homogeneity system $\bar {\mu }$ such that

$$ \begin{align*} A = W_{\bar{\mu}} =_{def} \{ x : \exists (i_k : k<\omega) \in \omega^\omega \langle \mu_{x|i_k} : k<\omega\rangle {is~well\text{-}founded}\}. \end{align*} $$

A is weakly homogeneous if it is $\kappa $ -weakly homogeneous for all $\kappa $ . Let $\textrm {wHom}_\infty $ be the collection of all weakly homogeneous sets.

Definition 2.3. $A\subseteq \mathbb {R}$ is $\kappa $ -universally Baire if there are trees $T,U \subseteq (\omega \times ON)^{<\omega }$ that are $\kappa $ -absolutely complemented, i.e., $A = p[T] = \mathbb {R}\backslash p[U]$ and whenever $\mathbb {P}$ is a forcing such that $|\mathbb {P}|<\kappa $ and $g\subseteq \mathbb {P}$ is V-generic, in $V[g]$ , $p[T] = \mathbb {R}\backslash p[U]$ . In this case, we let $A_g = p[T]$ be the canonical interpretation of A in $V[g]$ .

A is universally Baire if A is $\kappa $ -universally Baire for all $\kappa $ . Let $\Gamma _\infty $ be the collection of all universally Baire sets.

We remark that if A is $\kappa $ -universally Baire as witnessed by pairs $(T_1, U_1)$ and $(T_2, U_2)$ and $\mathbb {P}\in V_\kappa $ and $g\subset \mathbb {P}$ is V-generic, then $A_g = p[T_1] = p[T_2]$ , i.e., $A_g$ does not depend on the choice of absolutely complemented trees that witness A is $\kappa $ -universally Baire. A similar remark applies to $\kappa $ -(weakly) homogeneously Suslin sets.

Suppose there is a proper class of Woodin cardinals. The following are some standard results about universally Baire sets we will use throughout our paper. The proof of these results can be found in [Reference Steel6].

  1. 1. Hom $_\infty = \textrm {wHom}_\infty = \Gamma _\infty $ .

  2. 2. For any $A\in \Gamma _\infty $ , $L(A,\mathbb {R})\models \mathsf {AD}^+$ ; furthermore, given such an A, there is a $B\in \Gamma _\infty $ such that $B\notin L(A,\mathbb {R})$ and $A\in L(B,\mathbb {R})$ . In fact, $A^\sharp $ is an example of such a B.

  3. 3. Suppose $A\in \Gamma _\infty $ . Let B be the code for the first order theory with real parameters of the structure $(HC,\in , A)$ (under some reasonable coding of $HC$ by reals). Then $B\in \Gamma _\infty $ and if g is V-generic for some forcing, then in $V[g]$ , $B_g\in \Gamma _\infty $ is the code for the first order theory with real parameters of $(HC^{V[g]},\in , A_g)$ .

Under the same hypothesis, the results above also imply that:

  • $\Gamma _\infty $ is closed under Wadge reducibility,

  • if $A\in \Gamma _\infty $ , then $\neg A\in \Gamma _\infty $ ,

  • if $A\in \Gamma _\infty $ and g is V-generic for some forcing, then there is an elementary embedding $j: L(A,\mathbb {R})\rightarrow L(A_g, \mathbb {R}_g)$ , where $\mathbb {R}_g = \mathbb {R}^{V[g]}$ .

Finally, the reader should consult [Reference Steel7] for the basics of inner model theory. This is the background needed to follow the proof of Theorem 1.7. Consult [Reference Sargsyan and Trang4, Reference Sargsyan and Trang5] for more information on the theory of short-tree strategy mice related to lsa hod mice and appropriate mice; we will not need this material in this paper, however. In the following, we fix a natural coding of $(\omega _1,\omega _1)$ -iteration strategies for countable mice by sets of reals, e.g., we fix a function $\tau : HC\rightarrow \mathbb {R}$ that codes elements of $HC$ by reals as in [Reference Woodin9, Chapter 2] and $Code: {\wp }(HC)\rightarrow {\wp }(\mathbb {R})$ is the induced function given by: $Code(A) = \tau [A]$ .

3 Divergent models of $\mathsf {AD}^+$ and the failure of $\mathsf {CH}$

Proof of Theorem 1.2

Fix $A,B, \mathbb {P}, g$ as in the statement of the theorem. Let $\mathbb {R}_g = \mathbb {R}^{V[g]}$ . Let $\alpha $ be the least such that letting $x_A$ be the $\alpha $ -th real in the canonical well-order of $H_A$ and $x_B$ be the $\alpha $ -th real in the canonical well-order of $H_B$ , then $x_A\neq x_B$ .

Let $(U,\varphi )$ and $(W,\psi )$ be $\infty $ -Borel codes for $A, B$ , respectively. Let $s\in ({\wp }_{\omega _1}(\omega _2))^{V[g]}$ . Note that s is added by a countable suborder of $\mathbb {P}$ by the countable chain condition of $\mathbb {P}$ . Let $\mathbb {R}_s = \mathbb {R}^{V[s]}$ and define $A_s$ by: for all $x\in \mathbb {R}_s$ ,

$$ \begin{align*} x\in A_s \Leftrightarrow L[U, x] \models \varphi[x, U]. \end{align*} $$

We define $B_s$ using $(W,\psi )$ in a similar fashion. Let

$$ \begin{align*} M_s = L(A_s, \mathbb{R}_s) \end{align*} $$

and

$$ \begin{align*} N_s = L(B_s, \mathbb{R}_s), \end{align*} $$

Claim 1: Suppose $t\in ({\wp }_{\omega _1}(\omega _2))^{V[g]}$ and $s\subseteq t$ . Then the map $\pi ^A_{s,t}: M_s \rightarrow M_t$ defined by: $\pi ^A_{s,t}{\mathop{\restriction} } \mathbb {R}_s\cup ON = id$ and $\pi ^A_{s,t}(A_s) = A_t$ is an elementary embedding. Similarly, $\pi ^B_{s,t}$ is an elementary embedding.

Proof We prove the statement for A. This follows from [Reference Woodin9, Theorems 10.63 and 2.27–2.29] and [Reference Farah1, Theorems 6.3 and 6.4]. The key points are:

  • All sets of reals in $L(A,\mathbb {R})$ are $\aleph _1$ -universally Baire, as $(\mathbb {R},A)^\sharp $ is $\aleph _1$ -universally Baire.

  • The suborder of $\mathbb {P}$ adding s is weakly proper and countable, so $\pi ^A_{\emptyset ,s}{\mathop{\restriction} } ON = id$ and $\pi ^A_{\emptyset ,s}(A) = A_s$ is the canonical interpretation of A in $V[s]$ .

Let $M_\infty $ be the direct limit of $\mathcal {F}_A = \{M_s, \pi ^A_{s,t}: s\subseteq t \in ({\wp }_{\omega _1}(\omega _2))^{V[g]}\}$ and $N_\infty $ be the direct limit of $\mathcal {F}_B = \{N_s, \pi ^B_{s,t}: s\subseteq t \in ({\wp }_{\omega _1}(\omega _2))^{V[g]}\}$ .

Claim 2: $M_\infty , N_\infty $ are well-founded.

Proof The directed systems $\mathcal {F}_A, \mathcal {F}_B$ consist of well-founded models and the directed relation ( $\subseteq $ ) is in fact countably directed, i.e., if $(s_n : n < \omega )$ is such that for all n, $s_n\in ({\wp }_{\omega _1}(\omega _2))^{V[g]}$ , then there is some $s\in ({\wp }_{\omega _1}(\omega _2))^{V[g]}$ such that $s_n \subseteq s$ for all n. Therefore, $M_\infty , N_\infty $ are well-founded as any witness that $M_\infty $ ( $N_\infty $ ) is ill-founded has preimage in some $M_s$ ( $N_s$ ).

Let

$$ \begin{align*} \pi^A: L(A,\mathbb{R}) \rightarrow M_\infty = L(A_\infty, \mathbb{R}_g) \end{align*} $$

and

$$ \begin{align*} \pi^B: L(B,\mathbb{R}) \rightarrow M_\infty = L(B_\infty, \mathbb{R}_g) \end{align*} $$

be the directFootnote 5 limit maps. Note that $\pi ^A{\mathop{\restriction} } ON = \pi ^B{\mathop{\restriction} } ON = id$ . Now we claim that $M_\infty , N_\infty $ are divergent models of $\mathsf {AD}^+$ in $V[g]$ . This finishes the proof of the theorem.

We note that $\pi ^A(x_A) = x_A$ is the $\alpha $ -th real in the canonical well order of $HOD^{M_\infty }$ . This follows from the fact that $\pi ^A$ is elementary and fixes all ordinals. Similarly, $\pi ^B(x_B) = x_B$ is the $\alpha $ -th real in the canonical well order of $HOD^{M_\infty }$ . If $M_\infty , N_\infty $ are compatible, then the $\alpha $ -th real in $HOD^{M_\infty }$ must be equal to the $\alpha $ -th real in $HOD^{N_\infty }$ . To see this, suppose without loss of generality ${\wp }(\mathbb {R})^{M_\infty }\subseteq {\wp }(\mathbb {R})^{N_\infty }$ . Suppose $\beta \leq \Theta ^{N_\infty }$ is such that ${\wp }(\mathbb {R})^{M_\infty } = \{A\in N_\infty : w(A) < \beta \}$ . This easily gives $HOD^{M_\infty }$ is $OD$ in $N_\infty $ and that the canonical well-order of $OD$ -reals in $M_\infty $ is compatible with the canonical well-order of $OD$ -reals in $N_\infty $ . So $x_A= x_B$ . Contradiction.⊣

Proof of Theorem 1.4

Fix $A, \mathbb {P}, g$ as in the statement of the theorem. Let $\kappa $ be a measurable cardinal such that:

  • $\mathbb {P}\in V_\kappa $ .

  • A is $\kappa $ -homogeneous.

  • Every $\kappa $ -homogeneously Suslin set in $V[g]$ is universally Baire in $V[g]$ .

Let $\bar {\mu } = (\mu _s : s \in \omega ^{<\omega })$ be a homogeneous system witnessing A is $\kappa $ -homogeneously Suslin, i.e.,

$$ \begin{align*} x\in A \Leftrightarrow (\mu_{x|i} : i < \omega)\ \mathrm{is\ countably\ complete}. \end{align*} $$

Since $\mathbb {P}\in V_\kappa $ , for each $s\in \omega ^{<\omega }$ , there is $\nu \in meas_\kappa (\kappa ^{|s|})$ in V such that $\nu ^* = \mu _s$ , where $\nu ^* = \{A\in V[g] : \exists B\in \nu (B\subseteq A)\}$ is the canonical extension of $\nu $ in $V[g]$ . By the weak properness of $\mathbb {P}$ , there is a countable set of measures $\sigma \subset meas_\kappa (\bigcup _n \kappa ^n)$ in V such that

$$ \begin{align*} \bar{\mu}\subseteq \sigma^* = \{\nu^* : \nu\in\sigma\}. \end{align*} $$

In V, let $\bar {\nu } = (\nu _s : s\in \omega ^{<\omega })$ be an enumeration of $\sigma $ such that:

  1. (i) for each $s\in \omega ^{<\omega }$ , $\nu _s$ concentrates on $\kappa ^{|s|}$ ;

  2. (ii) if $\nu _t$ projects to $\nu $ , then there is some $i < dom(\nu _t)$ such that $\nu _{t|i} = \nu $ .

Now define the following set B, which is just the $\kappa $ -homogeneously Suslin set given by $\bar {\nu }$ : for $x\in \mathbb {R}$ ,

$$ \begin{align*} x\in B \Leftrightarrow (\nu_{x|k} : k<\omega)\ \mathrm{is\ countably\ complete}. \end{align*} $$

Let $B^*$ be the canonical extension of B induced by $\bar {\nu ^*} = (\nu ^*_s : s\in \omega ^{<\omega })$ in $V[g]$ . Thus, $B^*$ is $\kappa $ -homogeneously Suslin and hence is universally Baire in $V[g]$ . Let $f: \omega ^{<\omega } \rightarrow \omega ^{<\omega }$ be

$$ \begin{align*} f(s) = t\ \text{where}\ t \text{ is such that } \mu_s = \nu_t^*. \end{align*} $$

By the properties of $\bar {\nu }$ and $\bar {\mu }$ , we have:

  1. (a) $f(s)$ has the same length as s for every $s\in \omega ^{<\omega }$ .

  2. (b) f is order preserving, i.e., if $s_0$ is an initial segment of $s_1$ , then $f(s_0)$ is an initial segment of $f(s_1)$ .

Let $\hat {f}:\mathbb {R}^{V[g]}\rightarrow \mathbb {R}^{V[g]}$ be the continuous map induced by f:

$$ \begin{align*} \hat{f}(x) = \bigcup_{i<\omega} f(x|i). \end{align*} $$

We have, for any $x\in \mathbb {R}^{V[g]}$ ,

$$ \begin{align*} \begin{split} x\in A & \Leftrightarrow (\mu_{x|i} : i<\omega) \textrm{ is countably complete}\\ & \Leftrightarrow (\nu^*_{f(x|i)} : i<\omega) \textrm{ is countably complete}\\ & \Leftrightarrow \hat{f}(x) \in B^*. \end{split} \end{align*} $$

Thus $\hat {f}$ witnesses A is Wadge reducible to $B^*$ .

Proof of Corollary 1.5

First note that $\mathbb {P}$ is weakly proper, so we can apply Theorem 1.4. Now note that

(1) $$ \begin{align} o(\Gamma_\infty)^{V[g]} = \textrm{sup}[j_A{\mathop{\restriction}} o(\Gamma_\infty^V)] = \textrm{sup}[j_B{\mathop{\restriction}} o(\Gamma_\infty^V)]. \end{align} $$

Here, $o(\Gamma _\infty )$ is the length of the Wadge prewellorder on $\Gamma _\infty $ . To see (1), note that for each $X\in \Gamma _\infty $ , $j_A(X), j_B(X) \in \Gamma _\infty ^{V[g]}$ Footnote 6 and is the canonical interpretation of X, so $j_A(X) = j_B(X)$ . Now apply Theorem 1.4 to see that $j_A{\mathop{\restriction} } \Gamma ^V_\infty = j_B{\mathop{\restriction} }\Gamma ^V_\infty $ is cofinal in $\Gamma _\infty ^{V[g]}$ .

Finally, for each $X\in \Gamma _\infty $ , X is Wadge reducible to A ( $X \leq _w A$ ) in $L(A,\mathbb {R})$ . To see this, note that $A\notin \Gamma _\infty $ . Otherwise, by the facts mentioned at the end of Section 2, there is some $C\in \Gamma _\infty $ such that $A \in L(C,\mathbb {R})$ ; furthermore, $C^\sharp \in \Gamma _\infty $ , so $C^\sharp \notin L(A,\mathbb {R})$ . This contradicts $\Gamma _\infty \subset L(A,\mathbb {R})$ . Since $A\notin \Gamma _\infty , \Gamma _\infty \subset L(A,\mathbb {R})$ , and $L(A,\mathbb {R})\models \mathsf {AD}^+$ , the claim is established.

By elementarity $j_A(X) \leq _w A^*$ . By (1), $\Gamma ^{V[g]}_\infty \subset L(A^*,\mathbb {R}^{V[g]})$ . Similarly, $\Gamma ^{V[g]}_\infty \subset L(B^*,\mathbb {R}^{V[g]})$ .

4 Divergent models of $\mathsf {AD}^+$ over UB

In this section, we give the proof of Theorem 1.7. The proof closely resembles Woodin’s original proof of the existence of divergent models of $\mathsf {AD}^+$ in [Reference Farah1, Section 6]; the reader is advised to consult that proof for details we omit here.

Let ${\mathcal {M}},\Psi $ be as in the statement of the theorem and assume this is a minimal such mouse. Let ${\mathcal {P}}_0 = ({\mathcal {M}}|\delta _0)^\sharp $ be as in clause 1 of Definition 1.6. Let $\lambda = \lambda ^{\mathcal {M}}> \delta _0$ be the Woodin limit of Woodin cardinals of ${\mathcal {M}}$ . Let $c\in V$ be a Cohen real over ${\mathcal {M}}$ and let $A\in \Gamma _\infty $ be such that c is $OD$ in $L(A,\mathbb {R})$ .

The existence of A follows from countable self-iterability and the argument in [Reference Farah1, Section 6.2]. We sketch a proof here. A codes a pair $(P,\Lambda {\mathop{\restriction} } HC)$ where P is the transitive collapse of a countable $X\prec V_{\delta +1}$ such that $c\in X$ and $\delta $ is large enough that $\delta $ -universally Baire sets are universally Baire, and $\Lambda $ is a $\delta $ -universally Baire strategy of P. P is an extender model since $V= L[\vec {E}]$ is an extender model. Therefore, A is universally Baire. So $L(A,\mathbb {R}) \models \mathsf {AD}^+$ . By replacing P by $Hull^P(\{c\})$ we may assume P projects to $\omega $ and $\Lambda $ is the unique iteration strategy for P. Since $c\in P$ , P is an extender model, and $\Lambda {\mathop{\restriction} } HC$ can be extended to a unique $\omega _1+1$ -iteration strategy for P in $L(A,\mathbb {R})$ , the direct limit of all countable nondropping iterates of M via $\Lambda $ is defined and is $OD$ in $L(A,\mathbb {R})$ and hence c is $OD$ in $L(A,\mathbb {R})$ .

We may and do choose A such that $Code(\Psi ) <_w A$ as witnessed by a real $x^*$ .Footnote 7 To see such an A exists, suppose $Code(\Psi ) = p[T] = \mathbb {R}\backslash p[U]$ , where $T,U$ are trees witnessing $Code(\Psi )$ is $\delta $ -universally Baire for some $\delta $ . By choosing A coding the first order theory of $(HC,\in , (P,\Lambda ))$ with real parameters such that:

  • P is the transitive collapse of some countable $X\prec V_{\gamma +1}$ and

  • $(T,U)\in X$ for $\gamma $ sufficiently large that $\Lambda $ , the strategy for P, is universally Baire,

we can compute $\Psi $ from A as follows. Note that $\Lambda $ exists by countable self-iterability and since $\Lambda \in \Gamma _\infty $ , so is A. Let $x\in Code(\Psi ) = p[T]$ , let $\pi : P \rightarrow N$ be the iteration map that is induced by a genericity iteration according to $\Lambda $ to make x generic for the extender algebra at the first Woodin cardinal of N; we assume the first Woodin cardinal is $< \gamma $ . Let $(T^*,U^*)$ be the image of $(T,U)$ under the transitive collapse map $\tau $ and $(\tilde {T},\tilde {U}) = \pi (T^*,U^*)$ . We claim that $N[x] \models x\in p[\tilde {T}]$ ; otherwise, since $\tilde {T},\tilde {U}$ are absolutely complemented for forcings of size the first Woodin cardinal of N, $N[x]\models x\in p[\tilde {U}]$ . Since $\Lambda $ is a $\tau $ -realizable strategy, there is an embedding $\sigma : N \rightarrow V_{\gamma +1}$ such that $\tau = \sigma \circ \pi $ . This easily gives $x\in p[U]$ . Contradiction. Similarly, if $x\in p[U]$ , then $N[x] \models x\in p[\tilde {U}]$ . The above calculations show that $Code(\Psi )$ is projective in $Code(\Lambda )$ : for any $x\in \mathbb {R}$ , $x\in Code(\Psi )$ if and only if there is a non-dropping, countable tree ${\mathcal {T}}$ with last model N according to $\Lambda $ such that letting $\pi : P\rightarrow N$ be the iteration map, $x\in p[\pi (T^*)]$ . By the choice of A, $Code(\Psi )$ is Wadge reducible to A.

Say c is the $\alpha $ -th real in the canonical well-order of $HOD^{L(A,\mathbb {R})}$ . Let $C=B^\sharp $ , where B codes the first order theory of $(HC, \in , A)$ with real parameters; again, $C\in \Gamma _\infty $ and hence $L(C,\mathbb {R})\models \mathsf {AD}^+$ . Let $\pi : {\mathcal {M}}\rightarrow {\mathcal {N}}$ be the map induced by a countable iteration according to $\Psi $ above ${\mathcal {P}}_0$ such that:

  1. 1. letting $\lambda ^* = \pi (\lambda )$ , then $(C{\mathop{\restriction} } \lambda ^*,\mathbb {R}{\mathop{\restriction} } \lambda ^*)$ is in ${\mathcal {N}}[g]$ , where $g\in V$ is ${\mathcal {N}}$ -generic for $\pi (W^{\mathcal {M}}_\lambda ) =_{def} W^{\mathcal {N}}_{\lambda ^*}$ , the $\lambda ^*$ -generator extender algebra of ${\mathcal {N}}$ at $\lambda ^*$ ,Footnote 8

  2. 2. $\mathbb {R}\cap L[C{\mathop{\restriction} } \lambda ^*] = \mathbb {R}^{{\mathcal {N}}[g]}$ and $L(C{\mathop{\restriction} } \lambda ^*,\mathbb {R}{\mathop{\restriction} } \lambda ^*)\prec L(C,\mathbb {R})$ ,

  3. 3. $c,x^* \in \mathbb {R}^{{\mathcal {N}}[g]}$ .

The proof of these items, making substantial use of the fact that $\lambda $ is Woodin limit of Woodin cardinals, is the same as in [Reference Farah1, Section 6.3]. So in ${\mathcal {N}}[g]$ , there is an $\aleph _1$ -universally Baire set A Footnote 9 and two reals $c,x$ such that:

  1. 4. $L(A,\mathbb {R}) \models \mathsf {AD}^+$ ,

  2. 5. c is Cohen over ${\mathcal {N}}$ and c is the $\alpha $ -th real in the canonical well-order of $HOD^{L(A,\mathbb {R})}$ ,

  3. 6. $\pi (\tau )^g <_w A$ as witnessed by x.Footnote 10

We note that clauses 4 and 5 follow from clause 2; clause 6 follows from clause 3 and the choice of A.

Say $p\in g$ forces (4)–(6). Note that by appropriateness of ${\mathcal {N}}$ (clauses 3 and 4) and (6), in ${\mathcal {N}}[g]$ , $\Gamma _\infty \subset L(A,\mathbb {R})$ . Let $g_1\times g_2\subset W^{\mathcal {N}}_{\lambda ^*}\times W^{\mathcal {N}}_{\lambda ^*}$ be ${\mathcal {N}}$ -generic and contains $(p,p)$ . In ${\mathcal {N}}[g_1\times g_2]$ , for $i\in \{1,2\}$ , there is a triple $(A_i, c_i, x_i)$ satisfying (4)–(6) for ${\mathcal {N}}[g_i]$ . As in [Reference Farah1, Section 6.3] and the proof of Theorem 1.2, in ${\mathcal {N}}[g_1\times g_2]$ , there are sets $A_1^*, A_2^*$ and embeddings $\pi _i: L(A_i,\mathbb {R}^{{\mathcal {N}}[g_i]}) \rightarrow L(A_i^*,\mathbb {R}^{{\mathcal {N}}[g_1\times g_2]})$ that fix the ordinals.

By (6), we have that $\pi (\tau )^{{\mathcal {N}}[g_1\times g_2]} = \pi (\tau )^{{\mathcal {N}}[g_2\times g_1]} \in L(A_i^*,\mathbb {R}^{{\mathcal {N}}[g_1\times g_2]})$ for $i\in \{1,2\}$ . Therefore, by appropriateness,

(2) $$ \begin{align} \Gamma_\infty^{{\mathcal{N}}[g_1\times g_2]} \subset L(A_1^*,\mathbb{R}^{{\mathcal{N}}[g_1\times g_2]})\cap L(A_2^*,\mathbb{R}^{{\mathcal{N}}[g_1\times g_2]}). \end{align} $$

As in [Reference Farah1, Section 6.3], $\pi _1(c_1) = c_1 \neq \pi _2(c_2) = c_2$ as $c_1, c_2$ are mutually generic over ${\mathcal {N}}$ . So in ${\mathcal {N}}[g_1\times g_2]$

(3) $$ \begin{align} L(A_1^*,\mathbb{R}^{{\mathcal{N}}[g_1\times g_2]}), L(A_2^*,\mathbb{R}^{{\mathcal{N}}[g_1\times g_2]}) \textrm{ are divergent models of } \mathsf{AD}^+. \end{align} $$

By elementarity of $\pi $ applied to (2) and (3), in a generic extension of ${\mathcal {M}}$ , there are divergent models of $\mathsf {AD}^+ M_1, M_2$ such that $\Gamma _\infty \subset M_1\cap M_2$ .

Remark 4.1. We note in the construction above, letting g be a generic over ${\mathcal {M}}$ such that in ${\mathcal {M}}[g]$ there are divergent models $M_1,M_2$ as above, letting $\Delta = M_1\cap M_2\cap {\wp }(\mathbb {R})$ , then $\Gamma _\infty ^{{\mathcal {M}}[g]}\subsetneq \Delta $ . This is because $\tau _g\in M_1\cap M_2$ . By a result of Woodin, $L(\Delta )\cap {\wp }(\mathbb {R}) = \Delta $ and $L(\Delta )\models \mathsf {AD}_{\mathbb {R}}$ ; therefore, there are Suslin co-Suslin sets in $M_1\cap M_2$ that are not universally Baire.

5 Open questions

We collect some open problems concerning divergent models of $\mathsf {AD}^+$ . First, we do not know if divergent models of $\mathsf {AD}^+$ is consistent with or follows from various other strong hypotheses that imply $\mathsf {CH}$ fails.

Question 5.1.

  1. 1. Does $\mathsf {MM}$ imply there are divergent models of $\mathsf {AD}^+$ ?

  2. 2. Is the theory “there are divergent models of ” consistent?

One way to answer the following question is to show it is possible to construct appropriate mice.

Question 5.2. Is the theory “there is a proper class of Woodin cardinals and there are divergent models of $\mathsf {AD}^+ M$ and N such that $\Gamma _\infty \subset M\cap N$ ” consistent?

Acknowledgements

The author would like to thank G. Sargsyan for many illuminating discussions involving the topic of this paper. We thank the referee for comments that improve the paper.

Funding

The author’s research was partially supported by the NSF Career Award DMS-1945592.

Footnotes

1 It has come to my attention recently that G. Sargsyan (unpublished) has shown this.

2 By this we mean ${\mathcal {P}}_0$ is the first active initial segment of ${\mathcal {M}}$ extending ${\mathcal {M}}|\delta _0$ .

3 See [Reference Sargsyan and Trang5] for a detailed theory of lsa hod mice. Roughly, ${\mathcal {P}}_0$ is a hod mouse with the largest Woodin cardinal $\delta _0$ and the least $<\delta _0$ -strong cardinal is a limit of Woodin cardinals.

4 What is missing from [Reference Steel8] is a theory of short-tree strategy mice in the least-branch hierarchy.

5 It is clear that $\mathbb {R}^{M_\infty } = \mathbb {R}^{N_\infty } = \mathbb {R}_g.$

6 This follows from [Reference Woodin9, Theorem 10.63]. The maps $j_A, j_B$ map each $X\in \Gamma _\infty ^V$ to its canonical interpretation in $V[g]$ .

7 This means $x^*$ induces a continuous function $f:\mathbb {R} \rightarrow \mathbb {R}$ such that $a\in Code(\Psi )$ if and only if $f(a) \in A$ . Recall the function $Code$ introduced in Section 2 that codes subsets of $HC$ by sets of reals in a natural way.

8 Since $\mathsf {CH}$ holds in V, we identity $(\mathbb {R},C)$ with a subset of $\omega _1$ that codes it in a reasonable way.

9 In ${\mathcal {N}}[g]$ , $C{\mathop{\restriction} } \lambda ^*$ is $\aleph _1$ -universally Baire, not necessarily fully universally Baire.

10 Recall that $\tau $ is the term relation in ${\mathcal {M}}$ that interprets the short-tree strategy $\Sigma $ in all generic extensions of ${\mathcal {M}}$ .

References

Farah, I., The extender algebra and ${\varSigma}_1^2$ -absoluteness, preprint, 2016, arXiv:1005.4193.Google Scholar
Neeman, I., Inner models in the region of a Woodin limit of Woodin cardinals . Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, vol. 116 (2002), nos. 1–3, pp. 67155.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sargsyan, G., Hod Mice and the Mouse Set Conjecture, Memoirs of the American Mathematical Society, vol. 236(1111), American Mathematical Society, Providence, 2014.Google Scholar
Sargsyan, G. and Trang, N., The exact consistency strength of the generic absoluteness for the universally Baire sets. Forum of Mathematics, Sigma , 2019, to appear.Google Scholar
Sargsyan, G. and Trang, N., The Largest Suslin Axiom, Lecture Notes in Logic, vol. 56, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2023, to appear.Google Scholar
Steel, J. R., The derived model theorem , Logic Colloquium 2006, Lecture Notes in Logic, vol. 32, Association for Symbolic Logic, Chicago, 2009, pp. 280327 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steel, J. R., An outline of inner model theory , Handbook of Set Theory, Springer, Dordrecht, 2010, pp. 15951684.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steel, J. R., A Comparison Process for Mouse Pairs, Lecture Notes in Logic, vol. 51, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2022.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Woodin, W. H., The Axiom of Determinacy, Forcing Axioms, and the Nonstationary Ideal, revised ed., De Gruyter Series in Logic and Its Applications, vol. 1, Walter de Gruyter, Berlin, 2010.CrossRefGoogle Scholar