Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-tf8b9 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-28T17:25:31.789Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Human Rights, Global Ethics, and the Ordinary Virtues

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  10 March 2017

Extract

In a 1958 speech at the United Nations, Eleanor Roosevelt took stock of the progress that human rights had made since the proclamation of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights ten years before. Mrs. Roosevelt had chaired the UN committee that drafted the Universal Declaration and had hoped that, in time, it would become “the international Magna Carta of all men everywhere.” Her answer to the question of how to measure human rights progress has become one of the most frequently quoted remarks of the former First Lady:

Where, after all, do universal human rights begin? In small places, close to home—so close and so small that they cannot be seen on any maps of the world. Yet they are the world of the individual person; the neighborhood he lives in; the school or college he attends; the factory, farm, or office where he works. Such are the places where every man, woman, and child seeks equal justice, equal opportunity, equal dignity without discrimination. Unless these rights have meaning there, they have little meaning anywhere. Without concerted citizen action to uphold them close to home, we shall look in vain for progress in the larger world.

Type
Essays
Copyright
Copyright © Carnegie Council for Ethics in International Affairs 2017 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

NOTES

1 Roosevelt, Eleanor, quoted in “In Your Hands: A Guide for Community Action on the 10th Anniversary of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights” (New York: Church Peace Union, 1958)Google Scholar.

2 Simmons, Beth, Mobilizing for Human Rights: International Law in Domestic Politics (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2009)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

3 Ron, James and Crow, David, “Who Trusts Local Human Rights Organizations? Evidence from Three World Regions,” Human Rights Quarterly 37, no.1 (2015), pp. 188239 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

4 For a full account of the Carnegie project see Ignatieff, Michael, The Ordinary Virtues: Moral Operating Systems in a Post-Imperial World (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2017)Google Scholar.

5 For more on this observation, see Boo, Katherine, Behind the Beautiful Forevers: Life, Death and Hope in a Mumbai Undercity (New York: Random House, 2012)Google Scholar; and Steinberg, Jonny, Man of Good Hope (New York: Knopf Doubleday, 2015)Google Scholar.

6 Arendt, Hannah, The Human Condition (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2nd ed. 1998)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

7 Hume, David, A Treatise of Human Nature, Selby-Bigge, L. A., ed. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1956 [1896]), p. 481 Google Scholar.

8 Arendt, Hannah, The Origins of Totalitarianism (New York: Schocken, 2004 [1948]), p. 381 Google Scholar.

9 Marx, Karl, Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844 (New York: Dover, 2012)Google Scholar.

10 de Montaigne, Michel, “On Cruelty,” in The Complete Works, Frame, Donald M., trans. (New York: Everyman's Library, 2003 [1948]), pp. 372–86Google Scholar.

11 Rodrik, Dani, in Institutions, Development, and Economic Growth, Eicher, Theo S. and García-Peñalosa, Cecilia, eds. (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 2006)Google Scholar; and Acemoglu, Daron and Robinson, James A., Why Nations Fail: The Origins of Power, Prosperity, and Poverty (New York: Crown, 2012)Google Scholar.