Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-q99xh Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-24T01:32:01.023Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Lucretius 1. 102–105

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  11 February 2009

Howard Jacobson
Affiliation:
University of Illinois, Vrbana

Extract

Bailey posed the problem succinctly and clearly: ‘Though you can be said to “fashion a dream for yourself”, it is not easy to see how you can do it for someone else.’ He agrees with Giussani: somnia = ineptae fabulae, which is unexceptionable. But in fact Bailey's objection to the ‘literal’ meaning of the text is baseless. Dream control was indeed practised in antiquity.

Type
Shorter Notes
Copyright
Copyright © The Classical Association 1982

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Aside from its obvious virtues, Marullus' emendation possunt is probably supported by Claudian's imitation at Eutrop. 1. 170 fingere somnia possunt, though in Claudian somnia is subject rather than object.

2 The Vergilian line qui amant ipsi sibi somnia fingunt (Ecl. 8. 108) is the only other example I know of somnia fingere. It is, however, not relevant for an understanding of the Lucretian text both because, as Bailey says, it refers the action to oneself and also because it is a traditional description of lovers, here phrased in Lucretian language.

3 This need not imply that Lucretius believed in it, only that he knew others did. We might also recall Lucretius' interest in the terrifying consequences of dreams elsewhere (1. 133,4. 34–7).

4 To Professor Abraham Wasserstein I am indebted for helpful suggestions.