Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-g7gxr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-09T23:05:44.572Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Linguistic structure and the languages-of-thought

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 September 2023

Gabe Dupre*
Affiliation:
School of Political, Global, and Social Studies, Keele University, Staffordshire, UK [email protected] https://gabedupre.weebly.com/

Abstract

Quilty-Dunn et al. adopt a methodology for psychology connecting behavioral capacities to the format of the mental systems underlying them. This methodology opens up avenues connecting linguistic theory to comparative psychology. On the assumption that language structures thought, identifying the formal structure of human language can generate hypotheses connecting distinctively human cognitive traits to the distinctive structures of human language.

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press

Quilty-Dunn et al. identify a cluster of traits (discrete constituents, predicate–argument structure, role-filler independence, logical operators, inferential promiscuity, and abstract conceptual content) characteristic of “language-like” psychological states and processes, and marshal a wide range of empirical evidence that seems best explained by the positing of psychological systems with these properties. As they note, however, there are many different ways that mental systems could exemplify these properties (see also Mandelbaum et al., Reference Mandelbaum, Dunham, Feiman, Firestone, Green, Harris and Quilty-Dunn2022). Specifically, even within the genus of “language-like” systems, there are a wide variety of possible specific formal structures, or formats. The methodology they endorse for identifying and classifying mental systems involves identifying an organism's behavioral and cognitive capacities, and seeing which sort of mental format would best account for these. Although they are rightly keen to stress the difference between claims that some organism thinks in a language-of-thought and that this organism thinks in natural (i.e., human) language, and of course to avoid quibbling about whether some “language-like” system is really a language, this opens up the possibility of explaining a range of specifically human cognitive capacities by appeal to the apparently unique formats made available by natural language. In this brief comment I will point in some suggestive directions along these lines.

The cluster of traits identified by Quilty-Dunn et al. seems most apt to characterize systems with roughly the structure of predicate logic. They specify an n-place predicate, and n arguments, generating the traditional philosopher's notion of a proposition, which can then serve as an input for further combination and manipulation, such as logical inference. From the perspective of linguistic theory, such structures are more closely analogous to a verb phrase (VP), the domain of lexical content, rather than a complete sentential clause. A fairly widespread, although controversial, view in generative linguistics (see, e.g., Wiltschko, Reference Wiltschko2014) is that in addition to the lexical domains which specify, roughly, events and their participants, human linguistic structures contain a “functional spine,” the locus of a range of linguistic features including inflection, mood, force, and more. If these aspects of linguistic structure are indeed distinctive of human language, this raises the possibility that we might be able to appeal to them in explaining aspects of human cognition not found elsewhere in the animal kingdom, along the explanatory lines described by Quilty-Dunn et al. Where we find distinctive formal structure, we can seek distinctive cognitive capacities to be explained.

Of course, linguists posit such structures precisely to appeal to distinctive human cognitive and behavioral capacities involving our use of language. But, if certain hypotheses connecting human language to human thought more generally are along the right lines (e.g., Carruthers, Reference Carruthers2002; Chomsky, Gallego, & Ott, Reference Chomsky, Gallego and Ott2019; Dupre, Reference Dupre2020), our explanatory reach may be greater, and we may be able to explain distinctively human, but intuitively nonlinguistic, capacities by appeal to the mental structures made available by our linguistic faculty.

Consider, for example, the inflectional phrase (IP), one of the most prominent constituents of the functional spine. On one standard view, the primary function of IP is to “anchor” the event description provided by the VP to features of the discourse (see, e.g., Enç, Reference Enç1987; Ritter & Wiltschko, Reference Ritter and Wiltschko2014). Most commonly, this involves tense-marking, locating the described events in time, relative to the time of conversation, but other options appear to be available, anchoring described events spatially or relative to conversational participants (Ritter & Wiltschko, Reference Ritter and Wiltschko2009). Such anchoring appears to be required by the structures and operations made available by the language faculty, even in superficially tenseless languages (see, e.g., Matthewson, Reference Matthewson2006; Sybesma, Reference Sybesma2007).

If, and these are big “ifs,” human thought is structured by human language, and if human language requires anchoring, this is suggestive of a unification of language and one of the other allegedly unique capacities of the human mind, namely “mental time travel.” No other animal has uncontroversially demonstrated the ability to associate specific event-type representations with times and individuals the way humans do in episodic memory (see, e.g., Roberts & Feeney, Reference Roberts and Feeney2009; Hoerl & McCormack, Reference Hoerl, McCormack, Andrews and Beck2017, for reviews). If the structures of nonhuman cognition are well-characterized by the propositional structures described by Quilty-Dunn et al., although human thoughts are structured by the functional hierarchy posited by generative grammarians, this could go some way to turning two unique features of human cognition into one: Our ability to anchor our memories to specific temporal windows may be, or be causally/developmentally related to, our ability to form linguistic structures with an IP serving precisely this function.

Of course, much more work would need to be done to turn this suggestive similarity into a substantiated empirical hypothesis. And all of the work I have appealed to here is highly controversial. But I believe that the framework for psychological explanation provided by Quilty-Dunn et al. provides a highly productive way to bring to bear the results of contemporary linguistic theory onto questions in comparative psychology, in this case and a wide range of others.

Financial support

Funding for this research was provided by the Leverhulme Trust (Ref: ECF-2020-424).

Competing interest

None.

References

Carruthers, P. (2002). The cognitive functions of language. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 25(6), 657674.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Chomsky, N., Gallego, A. J., & Ott, D. (2019). Generative grammar and the faculty of language: Insights, questions, and challenges. Generative Syntax. Questions, Crossroads, and Challenges [special issue:] Catalan Journal of Linguistics, 229261.Google Scholar
Dupre, G. (2020). What would it mean for natural language to be the language of thought? Linguistics and Philosophy, 44, 773812.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Enç, M. (1987). Anchoring conditions for tense. Linguistic Inquiry, 18, 633657.Google Scholar
Hoerl, C., & McCormack, T. (2017). Animal minds in time: The question of episodic memory. In Andrews, K. & Beck, J. (Eds.) The Routledge handbook of philosophy of animal minds (pp. 5664). Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mandelbaum, E., Dunham, Y., Feiman, R., Firestone, C., Green, E. J., Harris, D., … Quilty-Dunn, J. (2022). Problems and mysteries of the many languages of thought. Cognitive Science, 46(12), e13225.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Matthewson, L. (2006). Temporal semantics in a superficially tenseless language. Linguistics and Philosophy, 29(6), 673714.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ritter, E., & Wiltschko, M. (2009). Varieties of INFL: Tense, location, and person. Alternatives to Cartography, 153, 202.Google Scholar
Ritter, E., & Wiltschko, M. (2014). The composition of INFL: An exploration of tense, tenseless languages, and tenseless constructions. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory, 32, 13311386.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roberts, W. A., & Feeney, M. C. (2009). The comparative study of mental time travel. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 13(6), 271277.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sybesma, R. (2007). Whether we tense-agree overtly or not. Linguistic Inquiry, 38(3), 580587.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wiltschko, M. (2014). The universal structure of categories (Vol. 142). Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar