Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-dlnhk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-23T01:43:16.654Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Advanced testing of the LoT hypothesis by social reasoning

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 September 2023

David J. Grüning*
Affiliation:
Psychology Department, Heidelberg University, Heidelberg, Germany. [email protected] Department of Survey Design and Methodology, GESIS – Leibniz Institute for the Social Sciences, Mannheim, Germany

Abstract

I elaborate on Quilty-Dunn et al.'s integration of the language-of-thought hypothesis in social reasoning by outlining two discrepancies between the experimental paradigms referred to by the authors and the social world: Self-referential projection and deliberate thinking in experiments. Robust tests of the hypothesis in social reasoning should include observational, natural, and cross-cultural approaches.

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press

I aim to elaborate on Quilty-Dunn et al.'s illustrative argumentation in support of the language-of-thought (LoT) hypothesis through the social psychological lens presented in the last section of their article. Although the authors’ address of conflict problems (target article, sect. 6.1) and implicit attitude research (target article, sect. 6.2) is compelling in its experimental context, it is not far-reaching enough, that is, it is only weakly informative about the actual socially embedded reasoning of individuals. What is missing is a conceptual test of the LoT hypothesis in real-life social situations of logical reasoning – for example, such situations prevalent in research on competitive or collaborative games and strategic thinking (e.g., Colman, Reference Colman2003; Grüning & Krueger, Reference Grüning and Krueger2021, Reference Grüning and Krueger2022; Hedden & Zhang, Reference Hedden and Zhang2002). Realistic social situations of reasoning are different to the cases addressed by Quilty-Dunn et al. in several aspects. In this commentary, I outline two aspects in more detail: (1) social and self-referential projection, and (2) deliberate thinking through experimental artificiality.

First, social situations of logical reasoning are highly complicated by experiential social learning and self-referential projection. For illustration let us turn to an example: Quilty-Dunn et al. iterate an experiment by Kurdi and Dunham (Reference Kurdi and Dunham2021) in which participants were presented with, among other statements, the following simple logical statement: “If you see a green circle, you can conclude that Ibbonif is malicious” (target article, sect. 6.2, para. 3). Adapting this straightforward statement to a context of social inference – for instance: “If you see a smirk on the face, you can conclude that Peter is malicious,” – can quickly ascend individuals into a rabbit hole of applying their (1) own social learning and (2) induction from introspection about their self. Both confounds substantially with learning and testing phases as presented in the original study. For one, the absence of a smile is not as unambiguously informative as the absence of the green circle in Kurdi and Dunham's (Reference Kurdi and Dunham2021) experiment. Social cues, like facial expressions, are predominantly multicausal and, hence, ambiguous in their information about the real state of the world, more so the less contextual information is provided (e.g., “Peter is smiling after something has happened.” vs. “[…] after something terrible has happened.”). An individual can never “conclude” with full certainty what a social signal informs one about. Second, when evaluating real social situations, individuals cannot step away from using themselves as referential source of information to evaluate the situation. In the asocial situation of coloured circles and Ibbonifs, self-referential inference is not applicable, unless in the unlikely event that an individual draws connections between these concepts and their self and personal experiences. However, in social situations, that is, situations including other people in interaction, self-referentiality is a very prominent strategy for social reasoning (e.g., Krueger, Reference Krueger2008, Reference Krueger2013; Krueger & Grüning, Reference Krueger, Grüning, Forgas, Crano and Fiedler2021; Krueger, Grüning, & Heck, Reference Krueger, Grüning and Heck2023). Both of the here outlined complications occur when we move from quasi-social to in-fact social statements. They are intended to illustrate that simple cases where associative (i.e., social learning) and propositional logic are easily distinguishable, and self-referential projection is no confound are difficult to find in actual social reasoning.

Second, the high artificiality of the experimental context and task in both of the authors’ research examples should be taken into account when interpreting their results as evidence for a specific reasoning hypothesis. The experimental context itself is expected to increase participants’ cognitive alertness and motivation for accuracy (e.g., Orne, Reference Orne1962; Zizzo, Reference Zizzo2010). The artificiality of most experimental reasoning tests, including the authors’ examples, is further likely to encourage participants’ deliberate instead of intuitive thinking regarding reasoning statements (see, as process explanation; Evans, Reference Evans2008; Kahneman, Reference Kahneman2011; recently, De Neys, Reference De Neys2022) as stimulus materials. In this respect, a strong interpretation of the discussed experiments might commit the same fallacy as early interpretations of human bias (e.g., Kahneman, Slovic, Slovic, & Tversky, Reference Kahneman, Slovic, Slovic and Tversky1982) that were later challenged to contain experimental artefacts (e.g., Gigerenzer, Reference Gigerenzer1996; Hertwig, Leuker, Pachur, Spiliopoulos, & Pleskac, Reference Hertwig, Leuker, Pachur, Spiliopoulos and Pleskac2022; but also see, Vranas, Reference Vranas2000). I hasten to note that this is largely an inherent problem of the experimental context created by conversational norms and the idiosyncrasy of the experimental design (e.g., Schwarz, Reference Schwarz and Zanna1994, Reference Schwarz1999), not a shortcoming by the authors. Experimental exploration is, by all means, meaningful. However, at the same time, it is just a first step to investigate a psychological phenomenon, even more so when considering social cognition phenomena like social reasoning. The experimental artificiality can be fled by also using observational and field study designs, exchanging some internal for ecological and external validity. Before the experiments, that Quilty-Dunn et al. call upon to argue for LoT in the social psychological space, have been extended to more ecologically valid contexts, generalizable claims of any sort, including the LoT hypothesis, should be modest.

Concluding, I welcome Quilty-Dunn et al.'s attempt for an exhaustive integration of the LoT hypothesis in psychological theory and empirics. Relevantly, with my commentary I do not attempt to rebut or support the LoT hypothesis. I seek to make the authors and readers aware of the fact that for a robust, that is, a persuasive, test of the LoT hypothesis in the social context, researchers cannot exclusively revert to simple experimental imitations of social reasoning. Instead, existing findings from realistic social inference-making scenarios have to be considered by the authors and observational and field experimental approaches need to be focused on in the future. Cross-cultural exploration, as an advanced extension of social psychology, would provide an additional opportunity to test the generalizability of the LoT hypothesis.

Financial support

This research received no specific grant from any funding agency, commercial, or not-for-profit sectors.

Competing interest

None.

References

Colman, A. M. (2003). Depth of strategic reasoning in games. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 7(1), 24. https://doi.org/10.1016/S1364-6613(02)00006-2CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
De Neys, W. (2022). Advancing theorizing about fast-and-slow thinking. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 168. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X2200142XGoogle ScholarPubMed
Evans, J. St. B. (2008). Dual-processing accounts of reasoning, judgment, and social cognition. Annual Review of Psychology, 59, 255278. https://doi.org/10.1146/annurev.psych.59.103006.093629CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gigerenzer, G. (1996). On narrow norms and vague heuristics: A reply to Kahneman and Tversky. Psychological Review, 103(3), 592596. https://doi.org/10.1037/0033-295X.103.3.592CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grüning, D. J., & Krueger, J. I. (2021). Strategic thinking: A random walk into the rabbit hole. Collabra: Psychology, 7(1), 24921. https://doi.org/10.1525/collabra.24921CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grüning, D. J., & Krueger, J. I. (2022). Strategic thinking in the shadow of self-enhancement: Benefits and costs. PsyArXiv. https://doi.org/10.31234/osf.io/gtc2mGoogle Scholar
Hedden, T., & Zhang, J. (2002). What do you think I think you think?: Strategic reasoning in matrix games. Cognition, 85(1), 136. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0010-0277(02)00054-9CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hertwig, R., Leuker, C., Pachur, T., Spiliopoulos, L., & Pleskac, T. J. (2022). Studies in ecological rationality. Topics in Cognitive Science, 14(3), 467491. https://doi.org/10.1111/tops.12567CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kahneman, D. (2011). Thinking, fast and slow. Farrar, Straus and Giroux.Google Scholar
Kahneman, D., Slovic, S. P., Slovic, P., & Tversky, A. (Eds.). (1982). Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics and biases. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krueger, J. I. (2008). From social projection to social behaviour. European Review of Social Psychology, 18(1), 135. https://doi.org/10.1080/10463280701284645CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krueger, J. I. (2013). Social projection as a source of cooperation. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 22(4), 289294. https://doi.org/10.1177/0963721413481352CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krueger, J. I., & Grüning, D. J. (2021). Psychological perversities and populism. In Forgas, J. P., Crano, W. D., & Fiedler, K. (Eds.), The psychology of populism (pp. 125142). Routledge.10.4324/9781003057680-9CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krueger, J. I., Grüning, D. J., & Heck, P. R. (2023). Inductive reasoning model. PsyArXiv. https://doi.org/10.31234/osf.io/3yasfGoogle Scholar
Kurdi, B., & Dunham, Y. (2021). Sensitivity of implicit evaluations to accurate and erroneous propositional inferences. Cognition, 214, 104792. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2021.104792CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Orne, M. T. (1962). On the social psychology of the psychological experiment: With particular reference to demand characteristics and their implications. American Psychologist, 17(11), 776783. https://doi.org/10.1037/h0043424CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schwarz, N. (1994). Judgment in a social context: Biases, shortcomings, and the logic of conversation. In Zanna, M. P. (Ed.), Advances in experimental social psychology (Vol. 26, pp. 123162). Academic Press. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0065-2601(08)60153-7Google Scholar
Schwarz, N. (1999). Self-reports: How the questions shape the answers. American Psychologist, 54(2), 93105. https://doi.org/10.1037/0003-066X.54.2.93CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vranas, P. B. (2000). Gigerenzer's normative critique of Kahneman and Tversky. Cognition, 76(3), 179193. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0010-0277(99)00084-0CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Zizzo, D. J. (2010). Experimenter demand effects in economic experiments. Experimental Economics, 13, 7598. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10683-009-9230-zCrossRefGoogle Scholar