Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-dh8gc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-08T02:44:54.463Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false
This chapter is part of a book that is no longer available to purchase from Cambridge Core

1 - Human Rights

Louise Chappell
Affiliation:
University of Sydney
John Chesterman
Affiliation:
University of Melbourne
Lisa Hill
Affiliation:
University of Adelaide
Get access

Summary

Even if we are sure that liberal democracy is the best possible regime for the realisation of human flourishing – and no matter how developed a liberal democratic system is – it would be a mistake to assume that justice can be achieved in such a system purely via electoral processes. Given that public decision making in democracies relies upon the approval of a time-poor and imperfectly informed electorate as well as on the actions of representatives who are obliged to accommodate the electorate's preferences in order to retain legitimacy and power, it is unsurprising that democracy turns out to be a rather blunt instrument for the delivery of individual and minority rights. This flawed but unavoidable dynamic between the electorate and its representatives is, undoubtedly, one of the virtues of – and chief justifications for – democracy, but it is also one of its weaknesses.

Despite his enthusiastic advocacy of representative government, British philosopher John Stuart Mill was acutely alert to this reality. Mill endorsed representative democracy because of its tendency to put power into the hands of the majority or, in his words, to admit ‘all to a share in the sovereign power of the state’ (Mill 1991 [1863], 256). And yet, while democracy might ameliorate the problem of tyranny by a select elite, it still held the potential for oppression by the democratic majority over minorities (via ‘the acts of the public authorities’) (Mill 1991 [1863], 8–9; Wolff 1996, 115).

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2009

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Baier, Annette, 1995. Moral Prejudices: Essays on Ethics. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Bay, Christian, 1977. ‘Human Needs and Political Education.’ In Human Needs and Politics, ed. Fitzgerald, Ross. Sydney: Pergamon.Google Scholar
Bay, Christian, 1982. ‘Self-respect as a Human Right: Thoughts on the Dialectics of Wants and Needs in the Struggle for Human Community.’ Human Rights Quarterly, 4 February: 53–75.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bede, Harris, 2002. A New Constitution for Australia. Sydney: Cavendish Publishing.Google Scholar
Berlin, Isaiah, 2002. ‘Two Concepts of Liberty.’ In Four Essays on Liberty, ed. Berlin, I., London: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bryce, James, 1901. Studies of History and Jurisprudence. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Burdekin, Brian, 1994. ‘Foreword.’ In Towards an Australian Bill of Rights, ed. Alston, Philip. Canberra: National Capital Printing.Google Scholar
Charlesworth, Hilary, 1993. ‘The Australian Reluctance About Rights.’ Osgoode Hall Law Journal 31(1): 195–232.Google Scholar
Charlesworth, Hilary, 2002. Writing in Rights: Australia and the Protection of Human Rights. Sydney: UNSW Press.Google Scholar
Clark, Andrew Inglis, 1901. Studies in Australian Constitutional Law. Melbourne: Maxwell.Google Scholar
Cockburn, Alexander, 1898. Official Record of the Debates of the Australasian Federal Convention, Third Session, 20 January to 17 March 1898. Melbourne: R. S. Brain, Government Printer.Google Scholar
Collins, Hugh, 1985. ‘Political Ideology in Australia: The Distinctiveness of a Benthamite Society.’ In Australia, the Daedalus Symposium, ed. Graubard, S. R.. Sydney: Angus & Robertson.Google Scholar
Cranston, Maurice, 1967. ‘Human Rights, Real and Supposed.’ In Political Theory and the Rights of Man, ed. David, D. Raphael. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Cranston, Maurice, 1973. What are Human Rights?London: The Bodley Head.Google Scholar
Dixon, Sir Owen, 1965. Jesting Pilate and Other Papers and Addresses by Sir Owen Dixon. Melbourne: The Law Book Company.Google Scholar
Donnelly, Jack, 2003. Universal Human Rights in Theory and Practice. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Donovan, Todd, Denemark, David and Bowler, Shaun, 2007. ‘Trust, Citizenship and Participation: Australia in Comparative Perspective’. In Australian Social Attitudes 2: Citizenship, Work and Aspirations, eds Denemark, David et al. Sydney: UNSW Press.Google Scholar
Fields, A. Belden, 2003. Rethinking Human Rights for the New Millennium. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Galligan, Brian, 1990. ‘Australia's Rejection of a Bill of Rights.’ Journal of Commonwealth and Comparative Politics 28(3): 344–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Galligan, Brian, 1994. ‘Australia's Political Culture and Institutional Design.’ In Towards and Australian Bill of Rights, ed. Alston, Philip. Canberra: Centre for International and Public Law.Google Scholar
Galligan, Brian, and McAllister, I., 1997. ‘Citizen and Elite Attitudes Towards an Australian Bill of Rights.’ In Rethinking Human Rights, eds Galligan, Brian and Sampford, C.. Sydney: Federation Press.Google Scholar
Garran, Robert, 1897. An Australian Handbook of Federal Government. Sydney: Angus & Robertson.Google Scholar
Gewirth, Alan, 1996. The Community of Rights. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Green, Reginald Herbold, 1981. ‘Basic Human Rights/Needs: Some Problems of Categorical Translation and Unification.’ Review of International Commission of Jurists, 27 December: 53–8.Google Scholar
Hancock, William, 1961 [1930]. Australia. Reprint. London: E. Benn.Google Scholar
Hill, Lisa, 2001. ‘The First Wave of Feminism: Were the Stoics Feminists?’, History of Political Thought, 22(1), pp. 12–40.Google Scholar
Hohfeld, Wesley, 1978 [1919]. Fundamental Legal Conceptions as Applied to Judicial Reasoning. Reprint. Westport, CT: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Ivison, Duncan, 2008. Rights. Montreal and Kingston: McGill-Queen's University Press.Google Scholar
Kirby, Michael, 2000. ‘Constitutional Interpretation and Original Intent: A Form of Ancestor Worship.’ Melbourne University Law Review 24(1): 1–14.Google Scholar
Kymlicka, Will, 1989. Liberalism, Community, and Culture. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Locke, John, 1990 [1690]. Two Treatises of Government. Reprint. London: J. Dent and Sons.Google Scholar
Menzies, Robert, 1967. Central Power in the Australian Commonwealth. London: Cassell.Google Scholar
Mill, John Stuart, 1991[1863]. On Liberty and Other Essays, ed. John, Gray. Reprint. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Moffatt, R. L. C., 1965. ‘Philosophical Foundations of the Australian Constitutional Tradition.’ Sydney Law Review 5: 59–88.Google Scholar
Nickel, James, 2006. ‘Human Rights.’ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Accessed online at www.science.uva.nl/∼seop/entries/rights-human/, 8 June 2008.Google Scholar
Ober, Josiah, 2000. ‘Quasi-Rights: Participatory Citizenship and Negative Liberties in Democratic Athens.’ Social Philosophy and Policy 17(1): 27–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Offord, Baden, 2006. ‘Activating Human Rights Through Questions of Value and Activism.’ In Activating Human Rights, eds Porter, Elisabeth and Offord, Baden. Bern: Peter Lang.Google Scholar
Okin, Susan Moller, 1998. ‘Feminism, Women's Human Rights, and Cultural Differences.’ Hypatia 13(2): 32–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ostwald, Martin, 2004. ‘Shares and Rights: Citizenship Greek Style and American Style.’ In Demokratia: A Conversation on Democracies Ancient and Modern, eds Ober, Josiah and Hendricks, Charles. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Otto, Dianne, 2001. ‘From Reluctance to Exceptionalism: The Australian Approach to Domestic Implementation of Human Rights.’ Alternative Law Journal 26(5): 219–22.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Patapan, Haig, 1997. ‘The Dead Hand of the Founders? Original Intent and the Constitutional Protection of Rights and Freedoms in Australia.’ Federal Law Review 25(2): 211–36.Google Scholar
Patapan, Haig, 2000. Judging Democracy: The New Politics of the High Court of Australia. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Quinn, Warren, 1993. Morality and Action. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Rubenstein, Kim, 1997. ‘Citizenship and the Constitutional Convention Debates: A Mere Legal Inference.’ Federal Law Review 25(2): 295–316.Google Scholar
Scanlon, Thomas, 2003. The Difficulty of Tolerance: Essays in Political Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shue, Henry, 1996. Basic Rights: Subsistence, Affluence and US Foreign Policy. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Sumner, L. W., 1987. The Moral Foundation of Rights. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Williams, George, 2002. ‘Five Reasons to Rewrite the Constitution.’ In The Big Makeover: A New Constitution: Labor Essays, eds Patmore, Glenn and Jungworth, Gary. Sydney: Pluto Press.Google Scholar
Williams, George, 2004. The Case for an Australian Bill of Rights: Freedom in the War on Terror. Sydney: UNSW Press.Google Scholar
Wolff, Jonathan, 1996. An Introduction to Political Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Human Rights
  • Louise Chappell, University of Sydney, John Chesterman, University of Melbourne, Lisa Hill, University of Adelaide
  • Book: The Politics of Human Rights in Australia
  • Online publication: 05 June 2012
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511841545.002
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Human Rights
  • Louise Chappell, University of Sydney, John Chesterman, University of Melbourne, Lisa Hill, University of Adelaide
  • Book: The Politics of Human Rights in Australia
  • Online publication: 05 June 2012
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511841545.002
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Human Rights
  • Louise Chappell, University of Sydney, John Chesterman, University of Melbourne, Lisa Hill, University of Adelaide
  • Book: The Politics of Human Rights in Australia
  • Online publication: 05 June 2012
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511841545.002
Available formats
×