Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-m6dg7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-05T13:34:03.968Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Bibliography

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  18 December 2017

Hichem Naar
Affiliation:
University of Nebraska, Omaha
Fabrice Teroni
Affiliation:
University of Geneva
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2017

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Àrdal, P. S. 1989. Passion and Value in Hume’s Treatise. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.Google Scholar
Aristotle, 1987. De Anima, trans. Lawson-Tancred, H.. London: Penguin Classics.Google Scholar
Armon-Jones, C. 1986. ‘The Thesis of Constructionism’, in Harré, R. (ed.), The Social Construction of the Emotions. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 3256.Google Scholar
Armon-Jones, C. 1991. Varieties of Affect. New York: Harvester Wheatheaf.Google Scholar
Armstrong, D. M. 1968. A Materialist Theory of the Mind. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Armstrong, D. M. 1970. ‘The Nature of Mind’, in Borst, C. V. (ed.), The Mind/Brain Identity Theory. London: Macmillan, pp. 6779.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arnold, M. B. 1960. Emotion and Personality. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Arpaly, N. and Schroeder, T. 2014. In Praise of Desire. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Austin, J. 1956. ‘A Plea for Excuses’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 57(1): 130.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Averill, J. 1980. ‘A Constructionist View of Emotion’, in Plutchik, R. and Kellermann, H. (eds.), Emotion: Theory, Research and Experience. New York: Academic Press, pp. 305–39.Google Scholar
Bagnoli, C. 2000. ‘Value in the Guise of Regret’, Philosophical Explorations 3(2): 169–87.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baglioni, C., Spiegelhalder, K., Lombardo, C., and Riemann, D. 2010. ‘Sleep and Emotions: A Focus on Insomnia’, Sleep Medicine Reviews 14: 227–38.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Baier, A. 1990. ‘What Emotions Are About’, Philosophical Perspective 4: 129.Google Scholar
Barrett, L. 2006. ‘Are Emotions Natural Kinds?’, Perspectives on Psychological Science 1: 858.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Betzler, M. 2004. ‘Sources of Practical Conflicts and Reasons for Regret’, in Betzler, M. and Baumann, P. (eds.), Practical Conflicts, New Philosophical Essays. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 197222.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bird, A. 2016. ‘Overpowering (How the Powers Ontology Has Over-Reached Itself)’, Mind 125(498): 341–83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Block, N. (ed.) 1980. Readings in Philosophy of Psychology, 2 vols. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Block, N. and Fodor, J. 1972. ‘What Psychological States Are Not’, Philosophical Review 80: 159–81.Google Scholar
Bower, G. H. 1981. ‘Mood and Memory’, American Psychologist 36: 129–48.Google Scholar
Brady, M. S. 2007. ‘Recalcitrant Emotions and Visual Illusions’, American Philosophical Quarterly 44(3): 273–84.Google Scholar
Brady, M. S. 2009. ‘The Irrationality of Recalcitrant Emotions’, Philosophical Studies 145(3): 413–30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brady, M. S. 2013. Emotional Insight: The Epistemic Role of Emotional Experience. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brady, M. 2014. ‘Emotion, Attention, and the Nature of Value’, in Roeser, S. and Todd, C. (eds.), Emotion and Value. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 5271.Google Scholar
Broad, C. D. 1954. ‘Emotion and Sentiment’, in Lewis, H. D. (ed.), Broad’s Critical Essays in Moral Philosophy. London: Allen and Unwin, 1971, pp. 283301.Google Scholar
Burge, T. 2010. Origins of Objectivity. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cacioppo, J. T. Berntson, G, Larsen, J., Poehlmann, K. and Ito, T. 2000. ‘The Psychophysiology of Emotion’, in Lewis, M. and Haviland-Jones, J. (eds.), Handbook of Emotions, 2nd edn. New York: Guilford pp. 173–91.Google Scholar
Campbell, J. 1994. Past, Space and Self. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Campbell, K. 1990. Abstract Particulars. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Campbell, N. 1996. Biology, 4th edn. San Francisco: The Benjamin/Cummings Publishing Company.Google ScholarPubMed
Cassam, Q. 2007. The Possibility of Knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chalmers, D. J. 1996. The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Chalmers, D. J. 2002. ‘Consciousness and Its Place in Nature’, in Chalmers, D. J. (ed.), Philosophy of Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 247–72.Google Scholar
Chemero, A. 2003. ‘An Outline of a Theory of Affordances’, Ecological Psychology 15: 81195.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chudnoff, E. 2015. Cognitive Phenomenology. New York: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Churchland, P. S. 1986. Neurophilosophy. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Cioran, E. M. 1992. On the Heights of Despair, trans. Zarifopol-Johnston, Ilinca. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Clore, G. L., Schwartz, N., and Conway, M. 1994. ‘Affective Causes and Consequences of Social Information Processes’, in Wyer, R. S. and Srull, T. K. (eds.), Handbook of Social Cognition. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum, pp. 2762.Google Scholar
Cohen, J. 2010. ‘Color Relationalism and Color Phenomenology’, in Nanay, B. (ed.), Perceiving the World. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 1333.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Colombetti, G. 2014. The Feeling Body: Affective Science Meets the Enactive Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Colombetti, G. and Thompson, E. (2008). ‘The Feeling Body: Towards an Enactive Approach to Emotion’, in Overton, W., Müller, U., and Newman, J. (eds.), Developmental Perspectives on Embodiment and Consciousness. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum, pp. 4568.Google Scholar
Cosmides, L. and Tooby, J. 2000. ‘Evolutionary Psychology and the Emotions’, in Lewis, M. and Haviland-Jones, J. (eds.), Handbook of Emotions. New York: Guilford Press, pp. 91115.Google Scholar
Cottingham, J. 1985. ‘Cartesian Trilism’, Mind 94: 218–30, reprinted in Cartesian Reflections: Essays on Descartes’s Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008, pp. 173–87.Google Scholar
Crane, T. 1998. ‘Intentionality as the Mark of the Mental’, in O’Hear, A. (ed.), Contemporary Issues in the Philosophy of Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 229–51.Google Scholar
Crane, T. and Mellor, D. H. 1990. ‘There Is No Question of Physicalism’, Mind 99: 185206.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crowther, T. 2011. ‘The Matter of Events’, Review of Metaphysics 65(1): 133.Google Scholar
Crowther, T. 2016. ‘Failures of Rationality and Self-Knowledge in Addiction’, in Segal, N. and Heather, G. (eds.), Addiction and Choice. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 8296.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crowther, T. forthcoming. ‘Experience, Dreaming and the Phenomenology of Wakeful Consciousness’, in Dorsch, F., Macpherson, F., and Nida-Rumelin, M. (eds.), Phenomenal Presence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Damasio, A. R. 1994. Descartes’ Error: Emotion, Reason, and the Human Brain. New York: Putnam.Google Scholar
Damasio, A. R. 2003. Looking for Spinoza: Joy, Sorrow, and the Feeling Brain. Orlando, FL: Harcourt.Google Scholar
D’Arms, J. and Jacobson, D. 2000. ‘The Moralistic Fallacy: On the “Appropriateness” of Emotion’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 61: 6590.Google Scholar
D’Arms, J. and Jacobson, D. 2003. ‘The Significance of Recalcitrant Emotion’, in Hatzimoysis, A. (ed.), Philosophy and the Emotions. New York: Cambridge University Press, pp. 127–46.Google Scholar
Darwin, C. 1998. The Expression of the Emotions in Man and Animals. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davidson, R. J. 1994. ‘On Emotion, Mood, and Related Affective Constructs’, in Ekman, P. and Davidson, R. J. (eds.), The Nature of Emotion: Fundamental Questions. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 303–5.Google Scholar
Davis, C. G., Lehman, D. R., Wortman, C. B., Silver, R. C., and Thompson, S. C. 1995. ‘The Undoing of Traumatic Life Events’, Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 21: 109–24.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
de Sousa, R. 1987. The Rationality of Emotions. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
de Sousa, R. 2014. ‘Emotion’, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2014 Edition), Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/emotion/.Google Scholar
Deigh, J. 1994. ‘Cognitivism in the Theory of Emotions’, Ethics 104: 824–54.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
DeLancey, C. 2006. ‘Basic Moods’, Philosophical Psychology 19(4): 527–38.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dennett, D. C. 1969. Content and Consciousness. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. C. 1993. ‘Quining Qualia’, in Goldman, A. I. (ed.), Readings in Philosophy and Cognitive Science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 381414.Google Scholar
Deonna, J. 2006. ‘Emotion, Perception and Perspective’, Dialectica 60(1): 2946.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Deonna, J. and Teroni, F. 2009. ‘Taking Affective Explanations to Heart’, Social Science Information 48(3): 359–77.Google Scholar
Deonna, J. and Teroni, F. 2012a. The Emotions: A Philosophical Introduction. New York: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Deonna, J. and Teroni, F. 2012b ‘From Justified Emotions to Justified Evaluative Judgements’, Dialogue 51(1): 5577.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Deonna, J. and Teroni, F. forthcoming. ‘Emotional Experience: Affective Consciousness and Its Role in Emotion Theory’, in Kriegel, U. (ed.), Oxford Handbook of the Philosophy of Consciousness. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Descartes, R. 1989. The Passions of the Soul, trans. Vonn, S. H.. Cambridge: Hackett Publishing.Google Scholar
Di Paolo, E. A., Rohde, M., and De Jaegher, H. 2010. ‘Horizons for the Enactive Mind: Values, Social Interaction, and Play’, in Stewart, J., Gapenne, O., and Di Paolo, E. (eds.), Enaction: Toward a New Paradigm for Cognitive Science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 3387.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Döring, S. A. 2003. ‘Explaining Action by Emotion’, The Philosophical Quarterly 53 (211): 214–30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Döring, S. A. 2007. ‘Seeing What to Do: Affective Perception and Rational Motivation’, Dialectica 61(3): 363–94.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Drayson, Z. 2012. ‘The Uses and Abuses of the Personal/Subpersonal Distinction’, Philosophical Perspectives 26(1): 118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dretske, F. 1969. Seeing and Knowing. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Dretske, F. 1973. ‘Perception and Other Minds’, Noûs 7(1): 3444.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dretske, F. 1979. ‘Simple Seeing’, in Gustafson, D. F. and Tapscott, B. L. (eds.), Body, Mind, and Method. Kluwer Academic Publishers, pp. 115.Google Scholar
Dretske, F. 1981. Knowledge and the Flow of Information. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Dretske, F. 1988. Explaining Behavior: Reasons in a World of Causes. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press/Bradford Books.Google Scholar
Dretske, F. 1995. Naturalizing the Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Ekman, P. 1992. ‘An Argument for Basic Emotions’, Cognition and Emotion 6: 169200.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ekman, P. 1994. ‘Strong Evidence for Universals in Facial Expression: A Reply to Russell’s Mistaken Critique’, Psychological Bulletin 115: 268–87.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ekman, P. 1997. ‘Basic Emotions’, in Dalgleish, T. and Power, M. (eds.), The Handbook of Cognition and Emotion. New York: John Wiley and Sons.Google Scholar
Ekman, P. 2003. Emotions Revealed: Recognizing Faces and Feelings to Improve Communication and Emotional Life. New York: Henry Holt.Google Scholar
Ekman, P. and Davidson, R. J. (eds.) 1994. The Nature of Emotion: Fundamental Questions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Ellsworth, P. 1994. ‘William James and Emotion: Is a Century of Fame Worth a Century of Misunderstanding?’, Psychological Review 101, 222–9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ellsworth, P. 2013. ‘Appraisal Theory: Old and New Questions’, Emotion Review 5: 125–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ellsworth, P. C. and Schrerer, K. R. 2003. ‘Appraisal Processes in Emotion’, in Davidson, R. J., Goldsmith, H. H., and Scherer, K. R. (eds.), Handbook of Affective Sciences. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 572–95.Google Scholar
Elster, J. 1999. Alchemies of the Mind: Rationality and the Emotions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Emmons, R. A. and McCullough, M. E. (2003). ‘Counting Blessings versus Burdens: An Experimental Investigation of Gratitude and Subjective Well-Being in Daily Life’. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 84(2): 377–89.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Fernández-Dols, J. M. and Ruiz-Belda, M. A. 1997. ‘Spontaneous Facial Behavior during Intense Emotional Episodes: Artistic Truth and Optical Truth’, in Russell, J. A. and Fernández-Dols, J. M. (eds.), The Psychology of Facial Expression. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 255–74.Google Scholar
Fine, K. 1999. ‘Things and Their Parts’, Midwest Studies in Philosophy 23: 6174.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fine, K. 2008. ‘Form and Coincidence’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary 82: 101–18.Google Scholar
Fine, K. 2013. ‘Guide to Ground’, in Correia, F. and Schneider, B. (eds.), Metaphysical Grounding. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 3780.Google Scholar
Fish, W. 2005, ‘Emotions, Moods, and Intentionality’, in Forrai, G. and Kampis, G. (eds.), Intentionality Past and Future. New York: Rodopi, pp. 2535.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fisher, M. L. and Exline, J. 2010. ‘Moving towards Self-Forgiveness: Removing Barriers Related to Shame, Guilt and Regret’, Social and Personality Psychology Compass 4(8): 548–58.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. 1974. ‘Special Sciences, or the Disunity of Science as a Working Hypothesis’, Synthese 28: 97115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. 1987. Psychosemantics: The Problem of Meaning in the Philosophy of Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press/Bradford Books.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. 1990. A Theory of Content and Other Essays. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Fredrickson, B. L. and Branigan, C. 2005. ‘Positive Emotions Broaden the Scope of Attention and Thought-Action Repertoires’, Cognition and Emotion 19(3): 313–32.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Frijda, N. 1986. The Emotions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Frijda, N. 1994a. ‘Emotions Are Functional, Most of the Time’, in Ekman, P. and Davidson, R. J. (eds.). The Nature of Emotion: Fundamental Questions. Oxford University Press, pp. 197202.Google Scholar
Frijda, N. 1994b. ‘Varieties of Affect: Emotions and Episodes, Moods and Sentiments’, in Ekman, P. and Davidson, R. J. (eds.), The Nature of Emotion: Fundamental Questions. Oxford University Press, pp. 5967.Google Scholar
Gallagher, S. 2008. ‘Direct Perception in the Intersubjective Context’, Consciousness and Cognition 17: 535–43.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Geach, P. 1969. God and the Soul. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Gibson, J. J. 1986. The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception. New York: Taylor and Francis.Google Scholar
Goldie, P. 2000. The Emotions: A Philosophical Exploration. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Goldie, P. 2002. ‘Emotions, Feelings and Intentionality’, Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 1: 235–54.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldie, P. 2004. ‘Emotion, Feeling, and Knowledge of the World’, in Solomon, R. C. (ed.), Thinking about Feeling: Contemporary Philosophers on Emotions. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 91106.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldie, P. 2010. ‘Love for a Reason’, Emotion Review 2(1): 6167.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldie, P. 2011. ‘Grief: A Narrative Account’, Ratio 24 (2): 119–37.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldie, P. 2012. The Mess Inside: Narrative, Emotion, and the Mind. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldschmidt, T. (ed.) 2013. The Puzzle of Existence: Why Is There Something Rather Than Nothing? London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Gordon, D. M. 1992. The Road Not Taken: A Phenomenological Investigation of the Experience of Regret. PhD diss., University of Tennessee. http://trace.tennessee.edu/utk_graddiss/1484.Google Scholar
Gordon, R. 1987. The Structure of Emotions: Investigations in Cognitive Philosophy. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Grahek, N. 2001. Feeling Pain and Being in Pain. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Green, M. 2007. Self-Expression. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Green, M. 2010. ‘Perceiving Emotions’. Aristotelian Society Suppl. Vol. 84(1): 4561.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Green, O. H. 1992. The Emotions: A Philosophical Theory. Dordrecht: Kluwer.Google Scholar
Greenspan, P. S. 1988. Emotions and Reasons: An Inquiry into Emotional Justification. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Grèzes, J., Tucker, M., Armony, J., Ellis, R., and Passingham, R. E. 2003. ‘Objects Automatically Potentiate Action: An fMRI Study of Implicit Processing’, European Journal of Neuroscience 17: 2735–40.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Griffiths, P. E. 1997. What Emotions Really Are: The Problem of Psychological Categories. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Griffiths, P. E. 2004.‘ Towards a Machiavellian Theory of Emotional Appraisal’, in Cruse, P. and Evans, D. (eds.), Emotion, Evolution and Rationality. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 89105.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Griffiths, P. and Scarantino, A. 2009. ‘Emotions in the Wild: The Situated Perspective on Emotion’, in Robbins, P. and Aydede, M. (eds.), The Cambridge Handbook of Situated Cognition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 437–53.Google Scholar
Harré, R. and Madden, E. H. 1975. Causal Powers: A Theory of Natural Necessity. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Hatzimoysis, A. 2007. ‘The Case against Unconscious Emotions’, Analysis 67(296): 292–9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heidegger, M. 1927/1962. Being and Time, trans. Macquarrie, J. and Robinson, E.. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Heil, J. 1992. The Nature of True Minds. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heil, J. 2003. From an Ontological Point of View. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Heil, J. 2005. ‘Dispositions’, Synthese 144: 343–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heil, J. 2012. The Universe as We Find It. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heil, J. 2013. ‘Contingency’, in Goldschmidt, T. (ed.), pp. 167–81.Google Scholar
Helm, B. 2001. Emotional Reason: Deliberation, Motivation, and the Nature of Value. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hinde, R. A. (1985). ‘Expression and Negotiation’, in Zivin, G. (ed.), The Development of Expressive Behavior. New York: Academic Press, pp. 103–16.Google Scholar
Höfler, A. 1897. Psychologie. Wien: Tempsky.Google Scholar
Hofweber, T. (2014). ‘Logic and Ontology’, in Zalta, E. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2014 Edition) https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/logic-ontology/.Google Scholar
Hornsby, J. 2010. ‘The Standard Story of Action: An Exchange’, in Aguilar, J. and Buckareff, A. (eds.), Causing Human Action: New Perspectives on the Causal Theory of Action. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 5768.Google Scholar
Hume, D. (1739–40), A Treatise of Human Nature, edited by Selby-Bigge, L. A., Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1896.Google Scholar
Hume, D. (1748). An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, in Selby‐Bigge, L. A. (ed.), Enquiries Concerning Human Understanding and Concerning the Principles of Morals, 3rd edn. rev. Nidditch, P. H.. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975.Google Scholar
Hursthouse, R. 1991. ‘Arational Actions’, Journal of Philosophy 88: 5768.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hutcheson, F. 1742/2003. An Essay on the Nature and Conduct of the Passions and Affections, with Illustrations on the Moral Sense. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund, Inc.Google Scholar
Isen, A. M. 1984. ‘Toward Understanding the Role of Affect in Cognition’, in Wyer, R. S. and Srull, T. K. (eds.), Handbook of Social Cognition. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum, pp. 179236.Google Scholar
Jackson, F. 1977. Perception: A Representative Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Jackson, F. 1986. ‘What Mary Didn’t Know’, The Journal of Philosophy 83: 291–5.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jacob, P. 2011. ‘The Direct-Perception Model of Empathy: A Critique’, Review of Philosophy and Psychology 2(3): 519–40.Google Scholar
Jacobson, D. 2013. ‘Regret, Agency and Error’, in Shoemaker, D. (ed.), Oxford Studies in Agency and Responsibility Volume 1. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 95125.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
James, W. (1884). ‘What Is an Emotion?’, Mind 9(34): 188205.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
James, W. (1890) 1981. The Principles of Psychology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
James, W. (1894) 1994. ‘The Physical Basis of Emotion’, Psychological Review 101, 205–10.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jaworska, A. 2007. ‘Caring and Internality’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 74(3): 529–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jaworski, W. 2011. Philosophy of Mind: A Comprehensive Introduction. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Jaworsk, W. 2012. ‘Structures, Powers, and Minds’, in Groff, R. and Greco, J. (eds.), Powers and Capacities in Philosophy: The New Aristotelianism. London: Routledge, pp. 145–71.Google Scholar
Jaworski, W. 2014. ‘Hylomorphism and the Metaphysics of Structure’, Res Philosophica 91: 179201.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jaworski, W. 2016. Structure and the Metaphysics of Mind: How Hylomorphism Solves the Mind-Body Problem. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johnston, M. 2006. ‘Hylomorphism’, Journal of Philosophy 103: 652–98.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jones, K. 2006. ‘Quick and Smart? Modularity and the Pro-emotion Consensus’, in Faucher, L. and Tappolet, C. (eds.), The Modularity of Emotions, Canadian Journal of Philosophy sup. vol. 32: 327.Google Scholar
Juslin, P. and Laukka, P. 2003. ‘Communication of Emotions in Vocal Expression and Music Performance: Different Channels, Same Code?’, Psychological Bulletin 129: 770814.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kenny, A. 1963. Action, Emotion and Will. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Kim, J. 1972. ‘Phenomenal Properties, Psychophysical Laws, and the Identity Theory’, Monist 56: 177–92. Selections reprinted in Block, N. (ed.) 1980. Readings in Philosophy of Psychology, 2 vols. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, pp. 234–6.Google Scholar
Kim, J. 1998. Mind in a Physical World. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press/Bradford Books.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kind, A. 2013. ‘The Case against Representationalism about Moods’, in Kriegel, U. (ed.), Current Controversies in the Philosophy of Mind. New York: Routledge, pp. 113–34.Google Scholar
Kirk, R. 1974. ‘Zombies versus Materialists’, Aristotelian Society Proceedings (suppl.) 48: 135–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kirk, R. 2005. Zombies and Consciousness. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koons, R. 2014. ‘Staunch vs. Faint-Hearted Hylomorphism: Toward an Aristotelian Account of Composition’, Res Philosophica 91: 151–78.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koslicki, K. 2008. The Structure of Objects. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kreibig, S. 2010. ‘Autonomic Nervous System Activity in Emotion: A Review’, Biological Psychology 84(2): 394421.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kriegel, U. (ed.) 2013. Current Controversies in the Philosophy of Mind. New York: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krueger, J. 2012. ‘Seeing Mind in Action’, Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 11(2): 149–73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lacewing, M. 2007. ‘Do Unconscious Emotions Involve Unconscious Feelings?’, Philosophical Psychology 20(1): 81104.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ladyman, J. and Ross, D. 2007. Every Thing Must Go: Metaphysics Naturalized. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laird, J. 2007. Feelings: The Perception of Self. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laird, J. and Lacasse, K. 2014. ‘Bodily Influences on Emotional Feelings: Accumulating Evidence and Extensions of William James’s Theory of Emotions’, Emotion Review 6(1): 2734.Google Scholar
Landman, J. 1993. Regret: The Persistence of the Possible. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lange, C. G. 1885. Om sindsbevaegelser; et psyko-fysiologisk studie. Kjobenhavn: Jacob Lunds Forlag.Google Scholar
Lazarus, R. S. 1991a. Emotion and Adaptation. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lazarus, R. S. 1991b. ‘Cognition and Motivation in Emotion’, American Psychologist 46: 362–7.Google ScholarPubMed
Lazarus, R. S. 1994. ‘The Stable and the Unstable in Emotion’, in Ekman, P. and Davidson, R. J. (eds.), The Nature of Emotion: Fundamental Questions. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 7985.Google Scholar
LeDoux, J. 1996. The Emotional Brain. New York: Simon and Shuster.Google Scholar
Levenson, R. W. 2003. ‘Autonomic Specificity and Emotion’, in Davidson, R. J., Scherer, K. R., and Goldsmith, H. H. (eds.), Handbook of Affective Sciences. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 212–24.Google Scholar
Levin, J. 2013. ‘Functionalism’, in Zalta, E. (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Fall 2013 edition, http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2013/entries/functionalism/.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. K. 1966. ‘An Argument for the Identity Theory’, Journal of Philosophy 66: 1725.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D. K. 1972. ‘Psychophysical and Theoretical Identifications’, Australasian Journal of Philosophy 50: 249–58.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D. K. 1980. ‘Mad Pain and Martian Pain’, in Block, N., (ed.) 1980. Readings in Philosophy of Psychology, 2 vols. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, pp. 216–22.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. K. 1983. ‘New Work for a Theory of Universals’, Australasian Journal of Philosophy 61: 343–77.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. K. 1997. ‘Finkish Dispositions’, Philosophical Quarterly 47: 143–58.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Locke, J. 1690⁄1979. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, Nidditch, P. H. (ed.), Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Long, G. M. and Toppino, T. C. 2004. ‘Enduring Interest in Perceptual Ambiguity: Alternating Views of Reversible Figures‘, Psychological Bulletin 130(5): 748.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Lormand, E. 1985. ‘Toward a Theory of Moods’, Philosophical Studies 47: 385407.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lyons, W. 1980. Emotion. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maienborn, C. 2005. ‘On the Limits of the Davidsonian Approach: The Case of Copula Sentences’, Theoretical Linguistics 31(3): 275316.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marmodoro, A. 2013. ‘Aristotelian Hylomorphism without Reconditioning’, Philosophical Inquiry 36: 522.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Martin, C. B. 1994. ‘Dispositions and Conditionals’, The Philosophical Quarterly 44: 18.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Martin, C. B. 1996a. ‘Properties and Dispositions’, in Crane, T. (ed.), Dispositions: A Debate, London: Routledge, pp. 7187.Google Scholar
Martin, C. B. 1996b. ‘Replies to Armstrong and Place’, in Crane, T. (ed.), Dispositions: A Debate, London: Routledge, pp. 126–46.Google Scholar
Martin, C. B. 1997. ‘On the Need for Properties: the Road to Pythagoreanism and Back’, Synthese 112: 193231.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Martin, C. B. 2007. The Mind in Nature. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Martin, C. B. and Heil, J. 1998. ‘Rules and Powers’, Philosophical Perspectives 12: 238312.Google Scholar
Martin, C. B. and Heil, J. 1999. ‘The Ontological Turn’, Midwest Studies in Philosophy 23: 3460.Google Scholar
Martin, C. B. and Pfeifer, K. 1986. ‘Intentionality and the Non-psychological’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 46: 531–54.Google Scholar
Matthews, G. and Wells, A. 1994. Attention and Emotion: A Clinical Perspective. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.Google Scholar
Maund, B. 2003. Perception. Chesham: Acumen.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mayer, J. D., Gaschke, Y. N., Braverman, D. L., and Evans, T. W. 1992. ‘Mood-Congruent Judgement Is a General Effect’, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 63(1): 119–32.Google Scholar
Mayer, J. D. and Hanson, E. 1995. ‘Mood-Congruent Judgement over Time’, Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 21(3): 237–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McDowell, J. 1982. ‘Criteria, Defeasibility, and Knowledge’, Proceedings of the British Academy 68: 455–79.Google Scholar
McLean, P. D. 1993. ‘Cerebral Evolution of Emotion’, in Lewis, M. and Haviland, J. (eds.), Handbook of Emotions. New York: The Guilford Press, pp. 6783.Google Scholar
McNeill, W. E. S. 2012. ‘On Seeing That Someone Is Angry’, European Journal of Philosophy 20(4): 575–97.Google Scholar
Mendelovici, A. 2014. ‘Pure Intentionalism about Moods and Emotions’, in Kriegel, U. (ed.), Current Controversies in Philosophy of Mind. New York: Routledge, pp. 135–57.Google Scholar
Michalak, J., Troje, N. F, Fischer, J., Vollmar, P., Heidenriech, T., and Schulte, D. 2009. ‘Embodiment of Sadness and Depression – Gait Patterns Associated with Dysphoric Mood’, Psychosomatic Medicine 71(5): 580–7.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Millikan, R. 1984. Language, Thought and Other Biological Categories. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mineka, S. and Sutton, S. K. 1992. ‘Cognitive Biases and the Emotional Disorders’, Psychological Science 3: 65–9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Molnar, G. 2003. Powers: A Study in Metaphysics, ed. by Mumford, S.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Moors, A. 2013. ‘On the Causal Role of Appraisal in Emotion’, Emotion Review 5(2): 132–40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moors, A., Ellsworth, P. C., Scherer, K. R., and Frijda, N. H. 2013. ‘Appraisal Theories of Emotion: State of the Art and Future Development’, Emotion Review 5(2): 119–24.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morris, W. N. 1989. Mood. The Frame of Mind. Berlin: Springer.Google Scholar
Morton, A. 1980. Frames of Mind. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Morton, A. 2013. Emotion and Imagination. Cambridge: Polity.Google Scholar
Mourelatos, A. 1978. ‘Events, Processes and States’, Linguistics and Philosophy 2: 415–34.Google Scholar
Mulhall, S. 1996. ‘Can There Be an Epistemology of Moods?’, in O’Hear, A. (ed.), Verstehen and Human Understanding. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 191210.Google Scholar
Mulligan, K. 1998. ‘The Spectre of Inverted Emotions and the Space of Emotions’, Acta Analytica 18: 89105.Google Scholar
Mumford, S. 1998. Dispositions. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mumford, S. 2009. ‘Causal Powers and Capacities’, in Beebee, H., Hitchcock, C., and Menzies, P. (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Causation. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 265–78.Google Scholar
Naar, H. 2013. ‘A Dispositional Theory of Love’, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 94(3): 342–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Naar, H. forthcoming. ‘Love as a Disposition’, in Grau, C. and Smuts, A. (eds.), Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Love. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Naar, H. and Tappolet, C. (ms.). ‘The Possibility of Instantaneous Emotions’.Google Scholar
Nagel, T. 2000. ‘The Psychophysical Nexus’, in Boghossian, P. and Peacocke, C. (eds.), New Essays on the A Priori. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 194235.Google Scholar
Noë, A. 2004. Action in Perception. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Noë, A. and O’Regan, J. K. 2002. ‘On the Brain-Basis of Visual Consciousness: A Sensorimotor Account’, in Noë, A. and Thompson, E. T. (eds.), Vision and Mind: Selected Readings in the Philosophy of Perception. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 567–98.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nussbaum, C. 2003. ‘Another Look at Functionalism and the Emotions’, Brain and Mind 4(3): 353–83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nussbaum, M. 2001. Upheavals of Thought: The Intelligence of Emotions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
O’Shaughnessy, B. 1972. ‘Mental Structure and Self-Consciousness’, Inquiry 15(1–4): 3063.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
O’Shaughnessy, B. 2000. Consciousness and the World. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Oakley, J. 1992. Morality and the Emotions. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Oatley, K. and Johnson-Laird, P. N. 1990. ‘Semantic Primitives for Emotions’, Cognition and Emotion 3: 125–37.Google Scholar
Oderberg, D. S. 2007. Real Essentialism. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Öhman, A. Flykt, A. and Esteves, F. 2001. ‘Emotion Drives Attention: Detecting the Snake in the Grass’, Journal of Experimental Psychology: General 130: 466–78.Google ScholarPubMed
Owens, H. and Maxmen, J. S. 1979. ‘Mood and Affect: A Semantic Confusion’, American Journal of Psychiatry I 36: 97–9.Google Scholar
Pacherie, E. 2002. ‘Emotion and Action’, European Review of Philosophy 5: 5590.Google Scholar
Panksepp, J. 1998. Affective Neuroscience: The Foundations of Human and Animal Emotions. New York, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Parkinson, B. and Colman, A. M. (eds.) 1995. Emotion and Motivation. London: Longman.Google Scholar
Parsons, T. 1989. ‘The Progressive in English: Events, States, and Processes’, Linguistics and Philosophy 12(2): 213–41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Parvizi, J. Arciniegas, D.B., Bernardini, G.L., Hoffmann, M.W., Mohr, J.P., Rapoport, M.J., Schmahmann, J.D., Silver, J.M. and Tuhrim, S. 2006. ‘Diagnosis and Management of Pathological Laughter and Crying’, Mayo Clinic Proceedings 81: 1482–6.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Phillips, I. 2010. ‘Perceiving Temporal Properties’, European Journal of Philosophy 18(2): 176202.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pickard, H. 2003. ‘Emotions and the Problem of Other Minds’, in Hatimoysis, A. (ed.), Philosophy and the Emotions: Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 52. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 87103.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pitcher, G. 1965. ‘Emotion’, Mind 74: 326–46.Google Scholar
Place, U. T. 1996a. ‘Intentionality as the Mark of the Dispositional’, Dialectica 50: 91120.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Place, U. T. 1996b. ‘Dispositions as Intentional States’, in Crane, T. (ed.), Dispositions: A Debate. London: Routledge, pp. 1932.Google Scholar
Popper, K. R. and Eccles, J. (eds.) 1977. The Self and Its Brain. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Price, C. 2006. ‘Affect without Object: Moods and Objectless Emotions’, European Journal of Analytic Philosophy 2(1): 4968.Google Scholar
Prinz, J. 2004. Gut Reactions: A Perceptual Theory of Emotion. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Prior, E. W., Pargetter, R., and Jackson, F. 1982. ‘Three Theses about Dispositions’, American Philosophical Quarterly 19: 251–7.Google Scholar
Pugmire, D. R. (1994). ‘Real Emotion’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 54(1): 105–22.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Putnam, H. 1967. ‘Psychological Predicates’, in Capitan, W. H. and Merrill, D. D. (eds.), Art, Mind, and Religion. Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh Press, pp. 3748. Reprinted as ‘The Nature of Mental States’, in Mind, Language, and Reality: Philosophical Papers, vol. 2 by Putnam, Hilary. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 429–40.Google Scholar
Rea, M. C. 2011. ‘Hylomorphism Reconditioned’, Philosophical Perspectives 25: 341–58.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Regier, W. 2004. ‘Cioran’s Insomnia’, Comparative Literature 119(5): 9941012.Google Scholar
Roberts, R. C. 1999. ‘Review: Emotions as Judgments: The Therapy of Desire by Martha C. Nussbaum’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 59(3): 793–8.Google Scholar
Roberts, R. C. 2003. Emotions: An Essay in Aid of Moral Psychology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Robinson, J. 1983. ‘Emotion, Judgment and Desire’, Journal of Philosophy 80: 731–41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Robinson, J. 1995. ‘Startle’, Journal of Philosophy 92: 5374.Google Scholar
Robinson, J. 2005. Deeper than Reason: Emotion and Its Role in Literature, Music and Art. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Robinson, J. 2017. “‘Tú, ser abrazable‘: La emoción como percepción para la acción,” (“Embraceable You: Emotion as Perception for Action”), in Pérez, D. and Lawer, D. (eds.), The Second Person and Emotion. Buenos Aires: SADAF. English version first presented in 2014 in Antwerp.Google Scholar
Roese, N., Epstude, K., Fessel, F., Morrison, M., Smallman, R., Summerville, Z., Galinsky, A., and Segerstron, S. 2009. ‘Repetitive Regret, Depression and Anxiety: Findings from a Nationally Representative Survey’, Journal of Social and Clinical Psychology 28(6): 671–88.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roseman, I. J. 2001. ‘A Model of Appraisal in the Emotion System’, in Scherer, K. R., Schorr, A., and Johnstone, T. et al. (eds.) Appraisal Processes in Emotion. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 6891.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Russell, B. 1921. The Analysis of Mind. Mineola: Dover Publications.Google Scholar
Russell, J. A. 2003. ‘Core Affect and the Psychological Construction of Emotion’, Psychological Review 110: 145–72.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ryle, G. 1949. The Concept of Mind. London: Hutchinson & Co.Google Scholar
Scarantino, A. 2004. ‘Affordances Explained’, Philosophy of Science 71: 949–61.Google Scholar
Scarantino, A. 2014. ‘The Motivational Theory of Emotions’, in D’Arms, J. and Jacobson, D. (eds.), Moral Psychology and Human Agency. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 156–85.Google Scholar
Scherer, K. R. 1987. ‘Toward a Dynamic Theory of Emotion’, Geneva Studies in Emotion 1: 196.Google Scholar
Scherer, K. R. 2001. ‘Appraisal Considered as a Process of Multilevel Sequential Checking’, in Scherer, K. R., Schorr, A., and Johnstone, T. J. (eds.), Appraisal Processes in Emotion. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 92120.Google Scholar
Scherer, K. R., Schorr, A., and Johnstone, T. (eds.) 2001. Appraisal Processes in Emotion: Theory, Methods, Research. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scherer, K. R. Banse, R. and Wallbott, H. G. 2001. ‘Emotion Inferences from Vocal Expression Correlate across Languages and Cultures’, Journal of Cross-Cultural Psychology 32: 7692.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schmidt, R. E. and Van der Linden, M. 2013. ‘Feeling too Regretful to Fall Asleep: Experimental Activation of Regret Delays Sleep Onset’, Cognitive Therapy and Research 37: 872–80.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schmidt, R. E. and Van der Linden, M. 2013. ‘The Nocturnal Return of Neglected Regrets: Deficits in Regret Anticipation Predict Insomnia Symptoms’, Open Sleep Journal 4: 20–5.Google Scholar
Schmidt, R. E., Harvey, A. G., and Van der Linden, M. 2011. ‘Cognitive and Affective Control in Insomnia’, Frontiers in Psychology 2: 349.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Searle, J. R. 1983. Intentionality: An Essay in the Philosophy of Mind. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Shand, A. F. 1914. The Foundations of Character. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Shargel, D. 2014. ‘Constitutively Embodied Emotions’ (Doctoral dissertation). Retrieved from http://academicworks.cuny.edu/gc_etds/472.Google Scholar
Shargel, D. 2015. ‘Emotions without Objects’, Biology and Philosophy 30(6): 831–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shields, C. 2014. Aristotle, 2nd Edition. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shoemaker, D. W. 2003. ‘Caring, Identification, and Agency’, Ethics 114(1): 88118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shoemaker, S. 1980. ‘Causality and Properties’, in van Inwagen, P. (ed.), Time and Cause. Dordrecht: Reidel, pp. 109–35.Google Scholar
Siegel, S. 2011. The Contents of Visual Experience. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Siegel, S. 2017. The Rationality of Perception. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Siemer, M. 2009. ‘Mood Experience: Implications of a Dispositional Theory of Moods’, Emotion Review 1(3): 256–63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Siemer, M. and Reisenzein, R. 1998. ‘Effects of Mood on Evaluative Judgements: Influence of Reduced Processing Capacity and Mood Salience’, Cognition and Emotion 12(6): 783805.Google Scholar
Sizer, L. 2000. ‘Towards a Computational Theory of Mood’, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 51: 743–69.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, C. A. and Kirby, L. D. 2001. ‘Toward Delivering on the Promise of Appraisal Theory’, in Scherer, K. R., Schorr, A., and Johnstone, T. (eds.), Appraisal Processes in Emotion. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 121–38.Google Scholar
Smith, J. 2010. ‘Seeing Other People’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 81(3): 731–48.Google Scholar
Smith, J. 2015. ‘The Phenomenology of Face-to-Face Mindreading’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 87(2): 274–93.Google Scholar
Smith, J. 2016. ‘Perceptual Recognition, Emotion, and Value’, in Dodd, J. D. (ed.), Art, Mind, and Narrative: Themes from the Work of Peter Goldie. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 121–37.Google Scholar
Smith, M. 1987. ‘The Humean Theory of Motivation’, Mind 96(381): 3661.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Solomon, R. C. 1988. ‘On Emotions as Judgments’, American Philosophical Quarterly 25: 183–91.Google Scholar
Solomon, R. C. 1993. The Passions: Emotions and the Meaning of Life. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Company, originally published in 1976.Google Scholar
Solomon, R. and Stone, L. 2002. ‘On “Positive” and “Negative” Emotions’, Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 32(4): 417–35.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Soteriou, M. 2013. The Mind’s Construction: The Ontology of Mind and Mental Action. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sperry, R. 1984. ‘Emergence’, in Weintraub, P. (ed.), The Omni Interviews. New York: Ticknor & Fields, pp. 187207.Google Scholar
Stephens, C. L., Christie, I. C., and Friedman, B. H. 2010. ‘Autonomic Specificity of Basic Emotions: Evidence from Pattern Classification and Cluster Analysis’, Biological Psychiatry 84: 463–73.Google ScholarPubMed
Steward, H. 1997. The Ontology of Mind: Events, Processes and States. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Steward, H. 2013. ‘Processes, Continuants, and Individuals’, Mind 122(487): 781812.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steward, H. 2015. ‘What Is a Continuant?’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 89: 109–23.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stout, R. 1997. ‘Processes’, Philosophy 72: 1927.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stout, R. 2003. ‘The Life of a Process’, in DeBrock, G. (ed.), Pragmatic Process Philosophy. Amsterdam: Rodopi, pp. 145–58.Google Scholar
Stout, R. 2010. ‘Seeing the Anger in Someone’s Face’, Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 84(1): 2943.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Strawson, G., 1994. Mental Reality. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Strawson, G, 2006. ‘Realistic Monism: Why Physicalism Entails Panpsychism’, in Freeman, A. (ed.), Consciousness and Its Place in Nature: Does Physicalism Entail Panpsychism? Exeter: Imprint Academic, pp. 331.Google Scholar
Tappolet, C. 2000. Emotions et valeurs. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.Google Scholar
Tappolet, C. 2010. ‘Emotion, Motivation and Action: The Case of Fear’, in Goldie, P. (ed.), Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Emotion. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 325–45.Google Scholar
Tappolet, C. 2016. Emotions, Values, and Agency. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Teroni, F. 2007. ‘Emotions and Formal Objects’, Dialectica 61(3): 395415.Google Scholar
Thalberg, I. 1964. ‘Emotion and Thought’, American Philosophical Quarterly 1: 4555.Google Scholar
Thayer, R. 1989. The Biopsychology of Mood and Arousal. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Tomkins, S. 1984. ‘Affect Theory’, in Scherer, K. R. and Ekman, P. (eds.), Approaches to Emotion. Hillsdale, NJ: Psychology Press, pp. 163–95.Google Scholar
Tormey, A. 1971. The Concept of Expression: A Study in Philosophical Psychology and Aesthetics. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Toronchuk, J. A. and Ellis, G. F. R. 2007. ‘Disgust: Sensory Affect or Primary Emotional System?’, Cognition & Emotion 21: 17991818.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tye, M. 2008. ‘The Experience of Emotion: An Intentionalist Theory’, Revue internationale de philosophie 243: 2550.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Unger, P. 2006. All the Power in the World. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Van Inwagen, P. 1990. Material Beings. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Vance, J. 2014. ‘Emotion and the New Epistemic Challenge from Cognitive Penetrability’, Philosophical Studies 169(2): 257–83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vance, J. 2015. ‘Cognitive Penetration and the Tribunal of Experience’, Review of Philosophy and Psychology 6(4): 641–63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Varela, F. J. 1991. ‘Whence the Origin of Perception? A Cartography of Current Ideas’, in Varela, F. J. and Dupuy, J. P. (eds.), Understanding Origins: Contemporary Ideas on the Origin of Life, Mind and Society. Boston: Kluwer, pp. 235–65.Google Scholar
Varela, F. J., Thompson, E., and Rosch, E. 1991. The Embodied Mind: Cognitive Science and Human Experience. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vendler, Z. 1957. ‘Verbs and Times’, Philosophical Review 66(2): 143–60.Google Scholar
Wallace, J. 2014. The View from Here. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Watson, J. B. 1924 Psychology, from the Standpoint of a Behaviourist, 2nd edn. London: J.B. Lippincott.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Whittle, A. 2008. ‘A Functionalist Theory of Properties’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 77(1): 5982.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, B. 1963. ‘Ethical Consistency’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 39: 103–24. Reprinted in Williams, B.. 1973. Problems of the Self. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, pp. 166–86.Google Scholar
Williams, B. 1976. ‘Moral Luck’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 50: 115–35.Google Scholar
Williams, D. C. 1953. ‘On the Elements of Being’, Review of Metaphysics 7: 318. Reprinted as ‘The Elements of Being’, in Williams, D. C. 1966. Principles of Empirical Realism. Springfield: Charles C. Thomas, pp. 74–109.Google Scholar
Williams, D. C. 1966. Principles of Empirical Realism. Springfield: Charles C. Thomas.Google Scholar
Wimsatt, W. C. 1985. ‘Forms of Aggregativity’, in Donogan, A., Perovich, A. N., and Wedin, M. J. (eds.), Human Nature and Natural Knowledge: Essays Presented to Marjorie Grene on the Occasion of Her 75th Birthday, Dordrecht: Reidel, pp. 259–93.Google Scholar
Witasek, S. 1908. Grundlinien der Psychologie. Leipzig: Meiner.Google Scholar
Wollheim, R. 1999. On the Emotions. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Wong, M. A. Y. 2015. ‘Towards a Theory of Mood Function’, Philosophical Psychology 29(2): 157–78.Google Scholar
Wyer, R. S. and Srull, T. K. (eds.) 1994. Handbook of Social Cognition. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.Google Scholar
Young, J. Z. 1971. An Introduction to the Study of Man. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Zajonc, R. B. 1980. ‘Feeling and Thinking: Preferences Need No Inferences’, American Psychologist 35: 151–75.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zajonc, R. B. 1984. ‘On the Primacy of Affect’, American Psychologist 39: 117–23.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zeelenberg, M. and Pieters, R. 2007. ‘A Theory of Regret Regulation’, Journal of Consumer Psychology 17(1): 318.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zeimbekis, J. and Raftopoulos, A. (eds.) 2015. The Cognitive Penetrability of Perception: New Philosophical Perspectives. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Bibliography
  • Edited by Hichem Naar, University of Nebraska, Omaha, Fabrice Teroni
  • Book: The Ontology of Emotions
  • Online publication: 18 December 2017
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316275221.012
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Bibliography
  • Edited by Hichem Naar, University of Nebraska, Omaha, Fabrice Teroni
  • Book: The Ontology of Emotions
  • Online publication: 18 December 2017
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316275221.012
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Bibliography
  • Edited by Hichem Naar, University of Nebraska, Omaha, Fabrice Teroni
  • Book: The Ontology of Emotions
  • Online publication: 18 December 2017
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316275221.012
Available formats
×