Book contents
- Frontmatter
- Contents
- General editors' preface
- Acknowledgments
- Translators' introduction
- Guide to abbreviations and the translators' notes
- I Metaphysik Herder, 1762–1764 (selections) (Ak. 28: 39–53)
- II Metaphysik L1, mid-1770s (complete except for the Natural Theology and Heinze extracts) (Ak. 28: 195–301)
- III Metaphysik Mrongovius, 1782–1783 (complete) (Ak. 29: 747–940)
- IV Metaphysik Volckmann, 1784–1785 (selections) (Ak. 28: 440–450)
- V Metaphysik L2, 1790–1791? (complete except for the Natural Theology) (Ak. 28: 531–594)
- VI Metaphysik Dohna, 1792–1793 (selections) (Ak. 28: 656–690)
- VII Metaphysik K2, early 1790s (selections) (Ak. 28: 753–775)
- VIII Metaphysik Vigilantius (K3), 1794–1795 (complete) (Ak. 29: 943–1040)
- English-German glossary
- German-English glossary
- Latin-German equivalents occurring in the text
- Concordance of Baumgarten's Metaphysics and Kant's Metaphysics lectures
- Explanatory notes (with bibliography of Kant's works cited)
- Name Index
- Subject index
III - Metaphysik Mrongovius, 1782–1783 (complete) (Ak. 29: 747–940)
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 05 May 2013
- Frontmatter
- Contents
- General editors' preface
- Acknowledgments
- Translators' introduction
- Guide to abbreviations and the translators' notes
- I Metaphysik Herder, 1762–1764 (selections) (Ak. 28: 39–53)
- II Metaphysik L1, mid-1770s (complete except for the Natural Theology and Heinze extracts) (Ak. 28: 195–301)
- III Metaphysik Mrongovius, 1782–1783 (complete) (Ak. 29: 747–940)
- IV Metaphysik Volckmann, 1784–1785 (selections) (Ak. 28: 440–450)
- V Metaphysik L2, 1790–1791? (complete except for the Natural Theology) (Ak. 28: 531–594)
- VI Metaphysik Dohna, 1792–1793 (selections) (Ak. 28: 656–690)
- VII Metaphysik K2, early 1790s (selections) (Ak. 28: 753–775)
- VIII Metaphysik Vigilantius (K3), 1794–1795 (complete) (Ak. 29: 943–1040)
- English-German glossary
- German-English glossary
- Latin-German equivalents occurring in the text
- Concordance of Baumgarten's Metaphysics and Kant's Metaphysics lectures
- Explanatory notes (with bibliography of Kant's works cited)
- Name Index
- Subject index
Summary
Introduction to metaphysics
<Prolegomena metaphysices>
Our cognitions are connected in a twofold way: first as an aggregate, when one is added to another [in order to] constitute a whole, e.g., a sand hill is not in itself a connection of things, but rather they are arbitrarily put together (there is nothing determinate here), second, as a series of ground and consequences, the parts of the series being called members because we can cognize one part only through the others, e.g., in a human body each part is there through the others. We easily comprehend that a connection of cognitions as an aggregate provides no determinate concept of a whole, and it is as if I add one small piece to another until a hill arises, etc., until a planet or terrestrial body comes into being; at least we can so think of it. In a series there is something that makes the connection according to a rule, namely, grounds and consequences. With grounds and consequences we must think of a priori boundaries, i.e., a ground that is not also a consequence, and a posteriori boundaries, i.e., a consequence that is not a ground, e.g., with human generations: human beings are members in a series, yet here we must think of a human being who does conceive but is not born, thus an a priori limit <terminus>, and of one who is born but conceives no one, thus an a posteriori limit <terminus>.
- Type
- Chapter
- Information
- Lectures on Metaphysics , pp. 107 - 286Publisher: Cambridge University PressPrint publication year: 1997
- 1
- Cited by