Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-t8hqh Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-26T17:19:14.362Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

28 - When the Data and Theory Don’t Match

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 February 2015

Bertram Gawronski
Affiliation:
University of Texas at Austin
Robert J. Sternberg
Affiliation:
Cornell University, New York
Susan T. Fiske
Affiliation:
Princeton University, New Jersey
Get access

Summary

A few years ago, a study in my lab produced a pattern of results that was not only unexpected but inconsistent with a theory that my collaborators and I had proposed several years before. Making the situation even worse, the finding was directly implied by a competing theory that we aimed to refute. Our theory predicted that repeated exposure to two co-occurring stimuli would form a mental association between the two stimuli even when people reject the co-occurrence as meaningless or invalid. A useful example to illustrate this hypothesis is the concern that repeated claims of Barack Obama being Muslim may create a mental association between Obama and Muslim even when people know that the claim is factually wrong. This possibility is explicitly denied by theories assuming that newly formed memory representations depend on how people construe co-occurrences and whether they consider them as valid or invalid. Consistent with the latter theories, and in contrast to the predictions of our own theory, our study showed that the effects of repeated exposure to information about other individuals were generally qualified by the perceived validity of this information; there was no evidence for unqualified message effects that were independent of perceived validity. My graduate student and I replicated this pattern in three independent studies, so there was no question about its reliability. Yet, a major question was: What should we do with the data? Should we publish them and discredit our own theory? Or should we ignore the data and pretend that our theory is correct despite our discovery that one of its central predictions has failed?

We eventually decided to submit the data for publication, and after an initial rejection the paper was accepted pending minor revisions at another journal. It was not easy to state in the paper that our theory includes an incorrect assumption, but the data ultimately helped us better understand the phenomena our theory had been designed to explain. Since the paper came out, some people have asked me why we invested so much effort into conducting and publishing research that discredits our own theory. Looking back, I still think it was the right thing to do, because the data told us something important that was inconsistent with what we believed at that time. Two years later, someone else published a study on the same question using a different operationalization. Their results confirmed the original prediction of our theory, so it turned out that we were not completely mistaken with our initial assumptions. However, taken together, the two articles suggest that our theory is at least incomplete, in that it fails to specify an important moderator of the predicted effect (which still needs to be identified). And that’s important to know if our goal is to advance science instead of pursuing our own personal agenda.

Type
Chapter
Information
Ethical Challenges in the Behavioral and Brain Sciences
Case Studies and Commentaries
, pp. 85 - 86
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2015

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×